Trung Luan
Mulamadhyamakakarika
of
Nagarjuna
THE PHILOSOPHYOF THE MIDDLE WAY
lntroduction, Sanskrit Text, English
Translation and Annotation
DAVID]. KA.LUPAHANA
MOTILAL BANARSIDASS, PUBLISHERS
PRNATE LIMITED e DELHIFirst Indian Edition: Delhi, 1991
ReprinL·· Delh~ 1996, 1999
C 1986 State UnivcrsiLy of New York,
All Rights Reserved
No part of this book may be used or rcproduced in any manner
whaLSoever \vithout wriuen permission excep t in the case of
brief ąuotations embodied in critical articles and reviews.
ISBN: 81-208-0774-x
Also availnbk at:
MOTILAL BANARSIDASS
41 U.A. Bungalow Road, Jawahar Nagar, Delhi 110 007
8 Mahalaxmi Chamoor, Warden Road, Mumbai 400 026
120 Royapettah High Road, Mylapore, Chennai 600 004
Sanas Plaza, 1302, Baji Rao Road , Pune 41l 002
J 6 St Mark's Road, Bangalore 560 001
8 Camac Streel, Calcutta 700 O17
Ashok Rajpath, Pama 800 004
Chowk, Varanasi 221 OOI
Library of C!'ngress Cataloging-ln-Publication Data
Nagarjuna, 2nd cent.
Mufamadhyamakakarika : the philosophy of the middle way
Translation of : Madhyamakakarika
lncludes bibliographical refercnces and index
L Madhyamika (Buddhism)-Early works to 1800
1. Kalupahana, David J., 1933- II. tilłe
m. Lille: Philosophy of the middle way
BQ2792.E5K35 1986 294-.3'85 85-14757
PRINTED IN INDIA
BYJAINENDRA PRAKASH JĄIN AT SHRI JAINENDRA PRESS.
A-45 NA.RAINA, PHASE I, NEW DELHI 110 028
AND PUBLISRED BY NARENDRA PRAKASH JAIN FOR
MOTILAL BANARSIDASS PUBLlSHERS PRIVATE UMTTED,
BUNGALOW ROAD, DELHI I IO 007To Profcssor N . A.
Jayawickrcma
(yo) 11c11n'yo 'hosi mam' atthak.amo U5.~0)PREFACE
Almost teo years ago, I undertook a new transłation of
Candrak.Irti's encydopaedic work the Pt4S(lnnapadi, a commentary on Nagarjuna's
primary philosophkal treatise, the Mu/41114dhyamak4kirikii.
Meer 1 bad
completed nearJy ten cbapters, 1'learoed through one of my
scudents about
a similar ·attcmpt by Professor Marvin Sprung. I was about
to give up my
· project, when my student, who -had prćviously srudied
under Professor
Sprung, shared wltb me a copy of Ptofessor Sprung's
ttanslatioo of the fitst
cbapter. Comparing his and my translations, I discovered
that Professor
Sprung's translation was to some cxtent influenced by
Stcherbatsky's wotk
(The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana, 1927). I fełt then that
my effon
would not be in vain, cspecially because l had expressed
strong disagreement with Stcherbatsky's interptctation of the Buddhist
philosophical tradicion (5ce my C4usality, The Cen/rai Philoióphy ofB11ddhism.
191)).
To my surprise1 Professor Sprung's ttanslation) consiting of
only seventeen chaptcrs (induding an incomplcte rendering of Chapter I),
appeated in
1979. As I plodded along through my own labocious work, I
began to
reałize how CandrakTtti was gradually leading me away from
Nag~juna's
phllosophical standpoint. My suspicioos wece sucngthcned in
1981 when I
visited Jndla oo a Smithsonian gtant. Meeting with some
scholai:s who were
brought up in the Vedantic uadition, I found them to be
extremcły comfon-
·able witll]'rągarjuna as intetpreted by Candrak.Trti and less
impressed by the
tcachings -of early Buddhlsm as recorded in the Nikayas and
the Agamas.
My suspkion tbat Nigarjuna and Candrakirti were ~pholding
two differeot
philosophical standpoints compeUed me to take a fresh look
at
Kumarajrva's Chung-lun, which is at least two ccncurics
prior to Candrak.Ttti. Translating the entire Chung-lun into English an.d
compating it
witb Nagarjuna's origioal Sanskrit text, I was pleasaotly
surprized by their
similaries:. I found no justiflcation whatsoever in l~oking
at Nagarjuna
through Candrakttti's eyes when there was a more faithful
and doser disciple of Nagarjuna in Kumarajrva. This discovery diminished my
enthusiasm
for deaning up my English ,:endeting of the Fraran1111p11dii
for possible
publication.
Mter translating botb the Sanskric and the Chinese versions
of Nigirjuna's tteatise, 1 proceeded to annotate both according to my
understan.ding
,of carly Buddhism as well as later Buddhist ttiditions
before Nagirjuna.
The annotation of the Sanskrit teiµ alone turned out to be
moce extcnsiveviii THE PH!LOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W/\Y
than anticipated. FU.Cthermore, considcdng the di.fficulties
that might arise
in publishing this work with Sanskrit and Chioese. texts
side by side, and
also with the Chinese characters in the body of the
annotation, 1 decided
once again to modify my project. The Sanskrit text is h~re
presented with
annotation and inttoduction. The Chinese text with
commentary wiH appear subsequently as a companion volume.
I am not unaware of the controversy this work may engender.
Hoping
that it will be a healthy one, I intend to raise one mąjor
questioo regarding
Nagarjtina-, especially in the light of the more recent
research in the bistory
of Bµdclhism. Professor Hajime Nakamura's monumental work,
Indian
Buddhis111. (1980). has provided more information regarding
the bistory of
Buddhist literature thań any other work published so far.
This carefully executed work not only deals with the cootents and authorship as
well as the
chronology of most of the Buddhist texts, but also compares
the different
versions available in Sanskrit, Paii, Chinese, Tibetan, and
Japanese. After a
careful reading of this work, l canoor help recognizing an
earlier stratum of
łiterature that has so far been lumped together with all the
literature that
carne to be called Mahayanistic. This indudes two famous
pieces, the
Kaśyapaparivarta and the Vajracchedikii-prajnapiiramit?i
(see Nakamura.
p. 159). I wondec whether the original versions of these
t~ts can be approriately called Mahayanistic, even though they were preserved
by the
Mahiiyiina schoołs. This objection, indeed, is not very
difficult from that
raised against considering the Nikayas and Agamas to be
Hlnayiinistic because
they were preserved by the Theravadins, the Sarvastivadins,
or any other later
uadition.
The major question that can be raised is: "Where would
a philosopher like
Nagarjuna go in order to discover the Buddha's teachings?''
This historical
ąuescioo bas, to my koowledge, neither been raised nor
aoswered. The
Sadriharmapu„t/anka-sutra that highlights the
Hlnayana-Mahayana controversy was not yet written. That does not meao that the
controversy was oot
known before Nagarjuna. Eveo if che controversy bad preceded
Nagarjuna,
what were the canonical tcns, embodying the pure Mahayana
phiłosophical
standpoint, that Nagarjuna could have utilized in order to
explain the
Buddha's message?
A careful reading of Nakamura's work shows it to be futile
co attempc to
discover a pure Mahayana text that Nagarjuna might have been
able to depend
upon. Before che compilation of the Saddharmapu??-(ianka,
ope can bardly
expect to find a carefuJly executed tceatise chat would
explicate the Mahayana
philosophy as it is presented by modern scholars. Since such
sohistićated
Mahayana sutras wece not available to Niigarjuna, he could
not help moving
on to the early discourses in the Nikayas and the Agamas in
search of the Bud-PREFACE ix
dha's teachings, especially at a time when he realized that
che probJems were
crcated not only by metaphysicians like the Sarvastivadins
and the
Sautrantikas>, but also by morc popular religious
ceachcrs like Aśvaghosa, who
over--emphasised the function of "faith" in the
emerging bdief in a traosccndeoc Buddha. A careful rcading of Nagarjuna's
rceatise will reveaJ that he
was.critical of both these trends. If Buddhagbosa wcre to be
coosidered the
model of a Thcravadin and Candrakfrti or Santideva were to
be looked upon as
ideał MahayanistS, oeither the Buddha, nor
Moggaupotta-tissa, nor Nigarjuna
would fit into thcir shoes. ·
The prcsent worlc may come as a surprise to many who arc
familiar with my
prcvious publications, espccially bccause it repudiates many
i:.hings chat I have
said about Nigarjuoa. Io those earlier works, my major
eodeavot was to show
how the Buddhism of ·the Buddha diffcred from both
Sthaviravada and
Mabayana, and the Jatter ioduded philosophers like
Nagacjuna. My main contention with scholars Jike Stcherbatsky and Murti has
been in regard to the_
manner in which the for.mer equated Sarvastivada with early
Buddhism and ·che
latter portrayed the Buddha as a half-hearted rnctaphysician
incroduciog a
theory ofdcments char carne to be rejccted by Nagarjuna. I
was preparcd co accept Murti's ioterpretation of Niigarjuna, white struggling
to find ways in
which that interprl:tation could be justified without
sacrificing the cmpiricism
of the Buddha. Amore detailed study of both Magarjuna and
Candrak!rti has
convioced me that the former stili rcmains faithful to the
Buddha, while the
lattec has moved more cowards a Vedantic inrerprctation,
chercby initiating a
proces~ that culminated in the disappearance of Buddhjsm as
a distinct..
ideology from the Indian scene a few cenruries
later.ABBREVIATIONS
(Consult Kenneth Inada's Niigiirjuna, for-a ·detailed
bibłiography on Nagarjuna and the Midhyamika school.)
A
AA
Ahh11t
AD
Adv
AK
Akb
'
Ch'ang
Chung
D
PIJ
DhsA
DhsT
It
Karika
Kp
Anguttara-nikiiya, cd. R. Morris and E. Hardy, 5 volumes,
London:
PTS; 1885-1900.
Manorathapura1j'i, [Anguttara-a(fhtikathaj, cd. M. Walleser,
London:
PTS, 1973.
AbhidhammatthavibhaWii-(ika. cd. D. Pannasara and P.
Vimaładhamma, Columbo: Mahabodhi Press, 1933.
Abhidharmadipa, see At;lv.
Abhidharmatlipa wilh Vibh'iifiiprabhii11rt1i, ed. P. S.
Jaini, Patna:
K. PJayaswal Research lnstirute, 1959.
Abhidharmako1a, sec Akb.
Abhidharmakośa- bha!a, ed. Pralhad Pradhao, Patna:·K.
P.Jayaswal
Research Institute, 1967.
Ch'ang A-han Ching (Dirghiigama), te. Buddhay~as. Tairho No.
.1.
Chung A-han Ching (Madhyamiigama), tr. Gautama Sarµghadeva
and Sarµgharalc$a, Tai.rho No.26.
Digha-flik41a, ed. T. W. Rhys Davids and J. E. Carpcnter, 3
volumes, London: PTS, 1890-1911.
Dhammappda, ed. V. Fausboll, London: Lu:zac, 1900.
Atthaiiilim , Dhamma.rangan'i'-atthtikath'ii, cd. E. Muller,
London:
PTS, !897.
Abhidhammamula(ikii [Ttka oo Dhamma.rańganl-affhakathaj ,
ed.
D. Pannasara and P. Wimaladhamma, Colombo: Mahabodhi Press,
1938.
ltivuttaka, ed. E. Windish, London: PTS, 1889.
See MKV{P), MKV(JQ.
Kiiśyapapari1111rta of the RPtnakuta:-sufra, ed. A .
Stael-Holstein,
Shanghai: Commercial Press, 1926.xu
M
Mi/n
MKV(P)
PEW
PTS
s
Sdv
Sdmp
Sn
Taisho
Thag
Thig
Tsa
Tseng
Ud
VbhA
THE PHILOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE WAY
Katha11at1h11, cd. A. C. Taylor, 2 volu.mes, London: PTS,
1894-1897.
Majjhima-nikiiya, cd. V. Trenckncr and R. Chalmers, 3 volumcs,
London: PTS, 1887-1901.
Milindapaflho, cd. V. Trcnckner, London: PTS, 1962.
Mlidhyamik.avrtti(Mmihyamakakiin'Jias),
cd. L. de la Vallćc Poussin,
Bibliotheca Buddhica 4, Sr. Petersburg: The Imperial Acadcmy
of
Scicnccs, 1903-1913.
Madhyamakaśiistra of Niigiirjuna with the commentary;
Prasannapt1'1ii by CandraRirti, cd. P. L. Va.idya, Darbhaoga: The Mithila
lnstiruce, 1960.
Philosophy East and West, cd. Eliot Deutsch, Honolulu: The
Univcrsity Press of Hawaii.
The Pali Text Society, London
Saf!Zulta-mlliiya, cd. L. Peer, 5 volumes, London: PTS,
1884-1904.
Sphu(iirth'iibhidhaimakofa-11:/iikhy'ii, cd. U. Wogihara,
Tokyo: The
Pubłication Association of Abhidłwmakosavyakhya, 1932-1936 .
Saddharmapu'!<fe'ika-siilra, cd. H. Kern and B. Nanjio,
St. Petersburg; The Imperial Acadcmy of Scieoces, 1912.
S11tfii-nipiita, cd. D. Anderson and H . Smith, London; PTS,
1913.
Tai.rho Shinshu Daizokyo, cd. J. Takakusu and K. Watanabe,
Tokyo: Daizo Shuppan Company, 1924-1934.
Thera-thefi-gathli, cd. H . Oldcnbcrg and R. Piśchel,
London: PTS,
1883.
See Thag.
Tsa A-han Ching (Saf!Zyukfiigama), tr. Gur,iabhadra, Taisho
No.99.
Tseng-i A-han Ching (Ekottaragama), tr. Gautama Saątghadcva,
Tai.rho No. 125.
Udiina, cd. P. Steinthal, London: PTS, 1948.
Sammoha11inodanl, Vibhangatfhakatha, cd. A. P. Buddhadatta,
London: PTS, 1923.ABBREVIATIONS xiii
Vin Vinay4 Pi{ala, cd. H. Oldcnbcrg, 5 volumcs, London: PTS,
1879·1883.
Vism The Vi.s11ddh1~magga ofB11ddhaghosa, cd. C. .A. F. Rhys
Davids,
London: PTS, 1975.CONTENTS
Preface vtt
Abbreviations xi
lNTRODUCTION
The Middle Path 1
Nagarjuna: The Myth 2
Nagarjuna: The Philosopher and Grand Commentator 5
Nagarjuna and.Kumarajiva 8
Nagarjuna·'s Buddha 9
Analysis of the Kaccayanagotta-Sutta 11
Buddha's Conception of Language and Truth 16
Period of the Śravakas 20
Moggaliputtatissa: The First Refotmer 23
Early Mahayana: The Second Reform Movement 24
Strućture of the Kii:rikii. 26
Analysis of the Karikii 31
Nagarujuna·'s Philosophical Enterprise 81
SANSKRIT TEXT, TRANSLATION AND ANNOTATION 99
Dedicatory Verses 101
CłiAPTER
1. Examination of Conditions (Pratyayaparik$ii) 105
2. Examination of the Moved
and the Not-moved (Gatiigata-paif/fJii) 118
3. Examination of the Faculty of Eye .
(Cakfur-indriya-pafi~ii) 132
4. Examination of Aggregates (Skandha-paiilfJa) 140
5. The Examination of Elements. (Dhiitu-parilfJa) 147
6. The Examination of Lust and the Lustful
(Riiga-rakttJr-pari~a)'
153
7. The Examination of the Conditioned
(Sarp.skrta-parilfJii) 159
8. Examination of Action and the Agent
(Karma-karaka-pari~a) 180xvi THE PmtosOPHY OF THE MrootE WAv
9. Examination of the Pńor Entity (PUrva-pari/eya) 188
10. Examination of Fire and Fuel (Agnzndhana-pari/eyii) 195
11. Examination of the Prior and Posteńor
Extremities (PUrvaparakoP,-paril~ii,) 206
12. Exatnination of Suffering (Duł_ikha-parileyii) 211
13. Ęxamination of Action and the Agent
(Sarriskara-parik.$a) 217
14. Examination of Association. (Sarrisarga-pariieyii) 224
15. Examination of Self-nature (Svabhiiva-pari~a) 2.28
16. Examination of Bondage and Release
(Bandhana-mo~a-parzl~a) 235
17. Examination of the Fruit of Action
(Karma-phala-pari~a) 243
18. Exarnination of Self (Atma-pari~ar 263
19. Examination of Time (Kala-pari~ii) 275
20. Examination of Harmony (Sii:magri-pań/eya) 280
21. Examination of Occurrence and Dissolution
(Sa1!llihava-vibhava-paril~ii) 292
22. Examination of the Tathiigata (Tathagata-pa~ii) 302
23. .Exrunination of Perversions (Viparyasa-pań~a) 312
24. Examination of th.e Noble Truths (Arya-satya-pari~ii)
326
25. Examination of. Freedom (Nirva?J.a-pan~ii) 355
26. Examination of the Twelve -Causal Factors
(D~iidasańga-pali~ii) 370
27. Examination of Views (D~ti-pa1i~ii) 377
INDEX TO THE .KARI.KA 393
Nominał Forms 393
Verbal Forms 402
General Index 406INTRODUCTION____THE MIDDLE PATił
Myths of huge proportions have developed around the
spiriruał and
philosophicaJ stature of various personaJities in aJmost
evecy scbool of Buddhism. Often these myths were inflated by sectarian
rivałrics tha~ continued to
plague the bistory of Buddhism , especially che rivałry
between the two major
schools, Theravada and 1.iahayaoa. These prejudices tended
to polarize che
phiłosophicaJ teachings of these two traditions chough. in
face, they are similar
if oot idencicaJ. They are simiłar in bcing faithful to the
basie teachings of che
Buddha; they are ałso comparable in the way in which chey
rejected certain
metaphysical ideas that concinued to creep into the
teachings.
The two aspeccs of the Buddha's teachings, the phiJosophica
ł and the practicaJ, which arc muruaUy dependent, are clearly enunciated io ewo
discourses·,
the Kaccaya11agolla-1utta1 and the
Dhamm111:akkappa11attana-sutta,2 both of
which arc heJd in high esteem by almosc all the schoołs of
Buddhlsm in spite of
theiI secrarian rivalries. The Kaccayanagotlll-Jutla, quoced
by almost all the
major schools of Buddhism, deals with the philosophicaJ
"middle path". płaced
against che backdrop of two absolutistic cheories in Indian
phiłosophy, o:imely,
permanent exiscence (atthifii) propounded in the early
Upant{ads and nihiłistic
non-existence (na11hitfi) suggcsted by the Materialists. The
middle position is
'exp łained as "dependent arising"
(paficcasamuppada) which , when utilizcd to
explain the nature of the human pcisonalicy and the world of
experience, appears in a formula consisting of twclvc factors (d11adaianga).
The practicaJ middle pach is enunciated in the equally famous
Dhammacakkappavattana-sulta,
respected by most Buddhists as the first sermon delivered by
che Bud~ha . Herc
the middle path is becween the ewo extreflłCS of
self-indulgence
(ka·maiuk.hallikanuyoga) and self-mortificarion
(attak.ilamathanyoga) and consists of tbe noble eightfold pach (an'yo
a!{hangiko maggo) leading to freedom
and happiness.
Throughouc che hiscory of Buddhism, Buddhists have
endeavored to remain
faithful to the doctrines enunciated in 'chese two
discourses, in spite of unforcunate divisions into Theravada and Mahayana and
in the face of enormous
pressures. either from inside or from outside, either social
or political, chat forced
them occasionaJly to deviated from the original message. For
example, in the
sphere of philosophical specułations, one of the sects
belonging to the so-called
Sthaviravada, namely, Sarvastivada, prescoted a theory of
"sdf-narure" or
"substance" (svabhava) and some of the
Mahayaniscs.admitted a conception of
" inherent thought of enlightenment"
(bodhi-cilta), both of which, as .may be
indicated in tbe following d iscussions, are theories
contrary to the fundamencal ·
12 TuE PHlLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
philosophical tenet of the Buddha, namely, "dependent
arising" (paficcasamuppida).
The practicał middle path as enunciated in the famous
Dhamffl(lcakkappavattana-sutta, which is complementary to or based upon the
philosophical middle path referrcd to above, was mote
susceptible to varia·
tions. The analysis of the wide variety of religous
practices th;n emerged in the
two ttaditions, Theravada and Mahayana, which appear to be
contrary to the
middle pach enunciated in the above discourse may require
aseparate volume.
The present treatmenr will therefore be confined to the
philosophical middle
path and its ~urvival, in spite of the heretical
interpretations tbat occasionally
appeared in the Buddhist tradition. The survival of that middle
position in
philosophy can be atttibuted to reformers lilce
Moggaliputta-tissa (litde known
among the Western scholars of Buddhism, in spite of the
important role he
played in the Buddhist council held during the re.ign of the
Emperor Asoka of
Jndia) and Nagarjuna. Such personałitics bave emerged from
time to time and
·they have been responsible fot the continuacion of the
Buddha's message. The
activities of such reformets have eitber been igoored, as in
the case of
Moggaliputta·tissa, or exaggerated, as in the case of
Nigarjuna.
The present essay is not intended as an attempt to bighlight
the conuibutions of the less ~nowo figures- like Moggalrputta-tissa. whose
famous
treatise, "The Points of Conuoversy"
(Kathii.vatthu),3 awaits a ca.refu! and sympathetic treatqient by
Buddhologists. On the contrary, this will be an attempt
to put into perspective the pbilosopbical and spiritual
stature of Nagarjuna,
wh1ch has been cxaggerated beyond limit.S, more by modern
scholars chan by
the classical Buddhiscs.
NAGARJUNA: THE MYTH
Nigarguna has been considered the second Buddha and has
occupied a second position in the line of patriarchs in almost all schools of
Mahayana Buddhism, primarily because the adherents of these schools refused to
recognize
the spiritual status of thousands of Buddha's immediate
disciples who, according to the Buddha's owo recognition, had attained the same
knowledge alld
understanding (fiii'!-t1-dassana) as well as the morał and
spiritual perfection attaioed by the Buddha. While the intellectuał and
spidtual attainments of the
immediate disciples are clearły portrayed in (excs like the
Theragatha and the
Thengatha, no such info..tmation is available to us about
Nagarjuna's spirirual
attainments exccpt the account of his conversion to . Buddhism
and. hislNTRODUCTION
scholastic activhies refecred to in a biogcaphkal account
uanslated into Chinese
by KumarajTva.4 Nagarjuna's stature as the second Buddha
derives, therefore,
from his basie writings, which are generally looked upon as
philosophicaJ 1nterpretations of the Mahayina suttas.
3
Kenneth lnada, who presented one of the most sympathetic
analyses of
Nagarjuna's thought, has admitted that the veneration of
Nagarjuna "at times
reached such ridiculous heights that his name was sanctified
and stamped
everywhete with recldess abandon even for purposes of
frauding scriprural
a.uthority."> He was probably referring to the
attempt on the part of some of
the later Tantric writers to seek authority and sanctity for
their ideas, which
were undoubtedly influenced by some later Indian religious
practices. Even if
one were to ignore such excesses, it is possible to maintain
that the exalted
position accorded to Nagarjuna yet reflects an uncritical
and dogmatic attitude
of some of the later Buddhists toward the spi.rirual ideii.I
of early Buddhism.
Such an attitude is reflected ·not only in some of the
Mahiyana texts butalso in·
some of the Theravada commentaries. For example, in the
later Theravada
commentarial liceratu.re, an exalted status is accorded to
the Abhidhamma in
relation to the discourses, so much so that the Buddha had
to ascend to the
world of deities (devaloka) and ps:each the Abh.idhamma to
his "mothe.t''. who
was residing there. 6 Such an admission, though intended to
provide authoriry
and santtity to a body of literature that emerged long after
the passing away of
the Buddha, undoubtedly carried the implication that the
Buddha's immediate
disciples were not capable of undersranding its contenrs.
However, even
though such an irnplication was there, the Theravadins did
not daborate this
story in such a way that it' would lead to the devaluation
of the ear:ly ideał of-.ui
arahant. Yet, when a similar need was felt by the
Mahayanists ro provide
authotiry aod sanctity to somc of the latcr Mahayina textS
such as the Ptajfiiiparamifii sutras, which were obviously later than the
Abhidharma treatises,
they were not satisfied with merdy saying }hat they were
"great dis_:ourses"
(11Pt'p11/ya-iiitra) 1 grearer than those included in the
Nikayas and the Agarnas.
They, in fact, proceeded to condemn the very ideał ofan
arahant embodied in
those discourses and to criticize the spititual attainments
of the early discipJes
of the Buddha.
In this particular movement, the
Saddhartnapuf'!r/affka-s11tra leads the
fiełd.7 The motivation or even the finał goal of this
roóvement may have been
very noble. It was, in fact, one of the earliest atrempts ro
unify all the conflicting ideas and ideals that were creating enotmous tifts
among the Buddhist
community. Yer, the manner in which such unification was
carried out led co
increasing conflicts rather than to their reconciliation or
appeasement.
Even a superficiaJ glance at the rustory of Buddhism wouJd
reveal the existence of"mooks'' (bhikfu) who deviated from the ideał and
who falsely claim-4 THE PHILOSOPHY 01' THE MIDDLE WA Y
c:d spirituaJ attainments white leading a form of life
infetior to that of ordinary
lay people. Such monks were reported even from the time of
the Buddha. The
Vinaya-pifaka8 as well as the Kif.Jyapararivarta9 generate
no sympathy for such
miscreant monks, the latter branding them as a pack of dogs
fighting cach
other for a morsel of food thrown at them.
Such sdfish and dishonorable behavior on th(' part of
certain monks may
hąve been counter productive. Self-sacrifice and absolute
altruism could
emerg~ as noble ideaJs in sucha context. However, such
actions and reactions
need not be a reason for condemning even the immediate
disciples of the Buddha, l!·rahanlr like Sariputta, Moggallana, and Kassapa, as
people of "low
aspirations" (liin'iibhirafii), 10 and forcing them to
discłaim thc:ir attainmc:ncs in
order to accept a new ideał, an idea] certainJy contrary to
the "middk path"
enunciated by the Buddha in his very first discourse to the
world. It is by
folłowing a "middle path" avoidiog the rwo
extremes of self.induJgence and
self-destruction that the discipłes of the Buddha attained
the state of freedom
called "the appeasement ofdispositions"
(sańkhara-samatha) and continued to
work for the welfate and happiness of mankind. Very
·authentic records
avaitabłe in the Thera- and Then-g'iithas bear ample
testimony to the ideał of
the ~arly discipłes, and it is also an idea! recognized' by
Nagarjuna, the champion of the ''middle way" (XVII.1).
While ~he Theravad~ns elevated the Abhidhamma to an exalted
position
without devaluing the ideas emhodied in the carty
discourses, the S11ddhar~
mapu„(llnka appears to have gone much funher in dealing with
this eotire
Buddhist phiJosophical and religious tradition beginning
with the Buddha
himself. It is responsible not only for condemning the early
disciples, but aJso
for down-playing the value of the carty discours.es. The
discoutses included in
the Nikayas and the·Agamas were considered to be inferior in
content. The
argument presented is that because the immediate disciples
could not understand the deeper doctrioe the.Buddha had to preach an jnfecior
and unsatisfattory doctrine to .suit their incełlectual capacity. Such a
statemeot, however, has
a hidden implication, nan1ely, that the Buddha lacked the
capacity to teach the
deepcr doctrines in a way that would be intelligible to the
people who were in
his presence. -In the Mahayana traditioo, the stage was thus
made ready for a
philosopher li.kc Nagarjuna, who is supposed to have best
expouoded the doctrine, to be ełevated to the level of a second Buddha, nay,
even to the starus of
a supreme Buddha more exalted chan Slikyamuoi. Thus1 it is
not surprizing to
find some modern commentators prodaiming the view that the
locus bud that
appeated in the world with che binh of the Buddha grew up
and blossomed
forth with the appearance of Nagatjuna. In fact, a scholar
like T. R. V. Murti
has maiotained that che Buddha even suggested a "theory
of elements'' (dharma), which carne to be be rejected by Nagarjuna when the
latter presented hislNTI\ODUCTION
cheory of "emptiness" (fiinyalii). 11 This
uodoubtedly places Nagarjuna in a
more exalted position than that occupied by the Buddha. Mosc
dassical and
some modern scholars have thus creaced an atmosphere where
the incerpreta·
don of Nagarjuna's philosophy wiłJ ha_ve to assume a
historical development
and unfolding of doccrines that wece merely suggested, not
taught, by the
historical Buddha. Some writers on Buddhism, intoxicated by
this conception
of the evolution of thought, havc shown rełuccance to
recognize che sophistication with which philosophical ideas were preseoted by
the Buddha 2500 years
ago. Having miserably failed to perceive the philosophical
ingenuicy of the
Buddha as reflected in the Nilcayas and che Agamas, as well
as the subsequent
degeneration of that system in the !acer commenrarial
tradition, followed by a
revival of the earlicr system by philosophers like
Moggaliputta-cissa and Nagarjuna, these writecs arc insisting upon a graduał
sophistication in Buddhist
thought comparable to what one can find in the Western
philosophical trad!·
tion. 12
N AGARJUNA: THE PHCLOSOPHER AND GRAND COMMENTATOR
In the followiog pages, an anempt will be made to present
Nagarjuna merely
as a grand commentator on che Buddha-word and to show that
he did not try to
improve upon the ceachings of the: Buddha. His work will be:
c:xplaincd as an at·
tempc co destroy che weeds thac had grown around che
Buddha's teachings as a
resulc of some of the ideas expressed by philosophers of
both che Schaviravada
and che Mahayaoa tradicions. Ir will be showo that tne
Mii/a-madhyamakakarika (hereafter abbreviated as Kiin'ka) is a superb
commentary oo the Buddha's owo KacciiyanagoJta-sulla, a commentary in which
Nagarjuna upholds
cvery statemenr made by the Buddha in that discourse,
bringing together more
materiał from the ocher discourses as well, and chen
clearing the watce muddied
by the speculations of some of che meraphysicians of the
later Buddhist ttad ition. The continuation of certain seccarian prejudices
among che faich.ful
adherencs of Theravada and Mahliylioa may be understandable.
Critical
scholarship. on the contrary, has a responsibility co remain
unsmeared by such
sectarian prejudices. Modern scholarship in Buddhism, which
began with th('
recogoition of this sectariao· rivalry as represencing a
major split in Buddhist
philosophical and religious ideology. has come a long way in
asserting ics
u n cenabiłity. Howcver, scholars are now beginning to realize
chat che
Theravada/ Mahayaoa discinccion is an cxaggeration and that
the fuodamencal·
reaching of the Buddha has remaiaed int~t throughouc the
cenruries. Now it is6 THE PH!LOSOPHY OFTHE MIDDLE WAY
time to exorcize the terms Theravada and Mahayana from our
vocabulary. A
major obstacle co the elimination of this distinction is the
manner in which
Nagarjuna's phiłosophy has come to be expoundcd by a
majority of modern
scholars. The presenc cranslation of Nigarjuna's Kiinka and
commentary upon
cach of che vcrscs therein are inteoded as a correctivc to
this intcrprctation.
A carcful study of the docuines in che cxteosivc corpus of
Buddhis~ literature
indicates ve.cy dcarly how certain fundamental idcas have
survived, in spite of
the occasional appearance of concepts chat conflict with the
basie teachings of
che Buddha and thus produce controversies among the Buddhist
thinkers.
Without undertaking a careful study of such insta.nces,
scholars have rather uncriticaUy lumped together the early discourses of the Buddha
and the summaries of their conten ts chat came to be preserved in the so-caJled
Abhidharma,
togcther with all d1e interpret.ive cexts compiled by some
of the later commentators, either in the form of vibhiif'ii or a!(hakatha, and
criticized trus whole
corpus as being representacive of Theravada or Hrnayana. The
same is clone
with some of the Mahayana discourses (sutra) and the
treatises (fastra). The
contents of d1e discourses as well as of the Abhidharma
literature arc examincd
only in the light of such commentarial explanations and not
independent of
them. Modern scholarship has thus failed to extricate
itselffrom commenta.riaJ
traditions. There seems to be oo justification for
coosidering the discourses and
even the eady Abhidharma literature as sectarian works of
the so-called
Thecavada. Theravada or Sthaviravada in generał , and
Sarvastivada and
Saucrantika in panicular, may be considered sectarian, but
their sectarian views
arc found not in the discourses and the Abhidharma but in
the commeotarics
tbat carne to be compiłed on these two bodies ofliteracure.
The elevation of the
Abhidharma to the level of a supreme body of literature,
moce exalted chan the
discourscs, is the work of these later commentators and not
of the compiłets of
chose Abhidharma texts. The Mahayanists themselves, bothered
by the
substantialist thought of the Sarvastivada and Sautrantika
schools, endeavored
to prcserve the eady teachings by emphasizing the negative
aspect of the Buddha's doccrioe, especially the doccrine of emptiness
(fUnyalii). The
Kiifyapapari11arta as well as the early Pcajfiapararnita
literarure represent tbis
reacrion co the substantialism of łatce Buddhism and t.h.is
literacure shouJd be
dissociated from the sectarianism chat cmerged as a result
of the arcempt at
unificacion in treatises like the Saddh11rmapu11tfonka.
An attcmpt will be made in the followiog pages to show that
even somc of
the moce prominent philosophers of Mahayana wece really
trying to overcome
such sectarian ioterpretations and go back to the
non-sectarian form of Buddhism as embodied in the early discourses, without
rcjecting either the
canonical Abhidharma texts that embody posicive teachings or
the early
Mahayana su tras that emphasizcd the ocgative aspect of the
Buddha's docrrine.[Nrn.OOUCTION
The present aoalysis will be confined co the v.:ork of
Nigarjuna in India.
Once Nigarjuna's philosophy is critically and objectiveły
analysed, h will be
possible to see whether there is any substance to the
rivalry between the two
major philosophical traditions, Madhyamika and Yogacara.
That projecc has
co be postponed to a later occasion.
A.K. Warder was one of the first to .taise the question
whetber Niga.r:juna
was a Mahayanist.n His reason for raising chat question was
that in the KJirika,
which undoubtedly was Nigarju.na's most significant work, no
reference what·
soever is made to any one of the major discourses of the
Mahayana tradition,
not even to the fatnous P.rajff?iparamita-sutra.r. Wa.rde.r
believed that the
discourse in the Samyukta served as a source for Nigatjuna's
treatise, even
though he did not specify them. The only discourse referred
to by name is Kiityay11niiva11ada,14 a discourse found both in the Pali
Nikayas1' and the Chioese
Agamas. 16 This single most important fact has often beeo
ovetlooked by mos.t
of the leading scholars who have written about Nagatjuna.
Even where this fact has beeo ooted, scholars have assumed
that Nagarjuna
was merely referriog to the Buddha's rejection of the two
extremes of existence
(atthitii) and non-existence (natthita) in that discourse
and that was all. So far,
no published work on Buddhism (available to the present
author) has treated
the contcnts of the Buddba's cliscoucse to Kaccayana in
detail before ptoceeding to analyse Nagarjuna's thought. Assuming that
Nagarjuna was a
Mahayanist and, therefore, must have rejected any literature
that carne to be
ptesctved by the Sthaviravadins, these scholars have
proceeded to analyze the
Kiiriliii in the light of their own prejudiced understanding
of Macłhyamika
philosophy. The ultimate .result is bafflement and
coofusion. Not only are tbey
reluctant to accept certain positive statements ofNiigarjuna
in the Kiirik.a, they
are also ready to abandon some of the most imponant chapters
in that work
eithet as later interpolations- or as having no relevance to
Nagarjuna's thesis.
7
To asswne that Nigarjuna was a philosophyet: who would
merely pick out
from the Buddha's statements only those that would support
ot fit in with his
own preconceived nocions is to do him g.reat injustice. lf
he was rejecting a
theory ofelements suggested by the Buddha (as Murti seems to
think). Nigarjuan, who was one of the most fearłess critics of metaphysical
views, would have
certainly said so. Nor is the.te any evidence to support the
hypothesis that the
"Admonition to Katyayana" (KJity1iyanava11tida)
that Nagarjuna was·referring
to was a vetsion different from the. Kacciiyanagotta-sutta
found in Pali and
Chinese. The Kiiśyapaparif!aflfl of the Ratnakuta contains
two discoutses, both
ofwhkh were addressed to Kasyapa and which deal with the
middle path. One
of them refcrs to the middle path and explains it in terms
of the twelve factors
of the human personality (d11adasańga), 11 while the other
explains the middle ·
path in negative terms as "non-ceasing, non-arising,
etc."18 This latter version is8 THE PHllOSOPHY OF THE MIODLE WAY
oot fouod in the Nikayas and the Agamas. Nagarjuoa was
probably aware of
the existence of both these versions and he understood their
implicatioos. His
Kiin"kti was an attempt to explaio the docuioe without
rejectiog the contents of
any one of them. However, his refcreocc to Kacyayana,
instead of Kaśyapa, is
extremely significant, in that be was conversaot with not
onJy the contencs of
~e Ratnaku{a versions but also the version included in che
Nikayas and che
Agamas. For this reason the analysis of Nagarjuna's
philosophy as embodied in
the Kiirika will be undenaken with a view to locating the
sources of those ideas
that arc accepted by him and those thar arc criticized and
rejected by him.
lt is anticipaced that an analysis of the Kiin"k.a in
relation to the "Discourse
to Katyayana" as well as ocher discourses iocluded in
the Nikayas and the
Agamas will lead to a better understanding of the Buddha's
philosophy
wichout exaggeracing the so-called Hlnayana-Mahayana
discinctioo.
NAGA.ff.JUNA AND KUMARAJIVA
Recent scholarship in the bistory of Buddhisc thougbt has
emphasized a
distioccion bctween Indian and Chinese forms of Buddhism.
Indian Buddhism
is explained as an attempt to deal with causation throug!'i
karma, white Sinitic
Mahayana is secn as advocatiog causation thcough
dharma-dhatu.19 Early Bud·
dhism. according to che proponencs of this thesis, underwent
a radical change
when it was introduced inro China. In order co deal with
this question of transition, it would be necessary to provide a complete
English translation of
Kumaraj"lva's rendition of Nagarjuna's Kiin"k'ii
into Chinese. Richard Robinson
made the first systematk attempt to deal with this problem of
transition. 20
However, that was done on the basis ofan inadequate
examioation of the first
chapcer of Nagarjuoa and Kumaraj"lva. A carefu1
scruriny of Kumarajiva's
work has convinced me that the form of Buddhism introduced
into China by
him was not at all differenr from chat of Nagarjuna. Thus,
if my contention
tbat Nagarjuna's philosophy is a mere rescatement of the
empiricist and
pragmacic philosophy of the Buddha, the form of Buddhism
incroduced into
China would also be the same as the originał teachings of
the Buddha wich oo
paradigm changes. Aod this may account for che survival of
Buddhism aloog
side of the equally pragmatic philosophy of Confucianism,
wbereas it failed to
survive in lndia in the face of a very strong idealistic
tradition. The prevalent
view - chat Buddhism, because of its idealistic character,
goc absorbed inco the
ideałistic tradition in lndia and failed co remain as a
separate enti cy - needs1NTRODUCTION 9
careful scrutioy, especialły when a leading philosopher like
Nagarjuna is not
seen to advocate such an idealistic view. This caHs for a
detailed treatment of
the Yogacara tradition in Buddhism that has not yet been
attempted.
NAGARJUNA'S BUDDHA
Nagarjuna's Buddha was no doubt Gautama (see KJirikii
XXVIl.30), the
prince from che Sakyan coupcry (p(esently pan~ of Nepal) who
attai.oed
enlightenment and rorned out to be the most formidable
opponent of almost
every major philosophical idea that came to be presented by
the lndians. In
fact, as will be explained below, the phiJosophical
atmosphere was so confused
during the Buddha's day thac sometimes be was fo.cced ro
coin new terms to ex-·
press his thoughts.
Two of the major philosopbical theories that dorńinated the
Indian scene
during this time were (1) existence (sat, astitva), proposed
and developed for
centuries by Indian chinkers since the time of the eady
Vedas, and (2) nonexistence (a.sat, 11iiistit11a), presented by the
Materialists reacting against the
craditional metaphysics. Existence or astitva was no
ordinary empirical existeoce
but the existence ofa permanent and eternal substratum in
man as well as in all
aspeccs of nature. In man. it was the immutable self(atman)
that remained in
boodage to the impermanent psychophysical personałity and
which returns to
its ultimate abode, the universal self(Atman), once it is
freed from thar bondage and reaches its ultimate moral status (Brahman) .
Attempting to eicplain
the origin of this reality in man as wełl as in oature, some
of the craditional
philosophers setcled for a conception of a creator god. As
it is, this may not
have generated much protest from tłte Buddha. However, the
Indian
philosophers wece not satisfied with the simple aorion of a
creator god. At a
very earły stage, they asserted chat this self(at1nan) was created
by a god or gods
who dete.rmined that it beloogs to one or the other of the
four·social classes: the
priestly (brtihmatJa), the warrior (k1atriya), che merchant
(vaiśya), and the ser-
\rant (śiidra). 21 Thus, cach individual's :aarus was
predetermined and unchangeable. It was this particular idea of creation that
elicited rhe most vehement criticism both from the Materialists as well as from
the Buddha.
Denying such a metaphysi<ial self, the Materialists moved
to the other extreme of advocatiog the annihilatioo of the human personaliry
aftec death, and
then ałso denied any mąral responsiblicy for human actions.
Instead, they propounded a theocy of the indestructibilicy of matter.22JO THE
PHILOSOPHY OFnlB MIDDLE WAY
Kaccayanagotta-Sutta
The Buddha's discourse to Kaccaya.na, a discourse wbose
authority was
recognized by aJmost aH the major philosophica1 schools of
BuddhJsm,
becomes mea.oingful only in the context of the
philosophica.l views mentioned
abovc. Following is the complete text of the discour:se as
reponed by Ananda:
Thus have I heard: The Blessed one was once living at
Savatth.i,
in the monastery of Ana(hapiJ:l<;łika, in Jeta's Grove.
At that time
the venerable Kaccayaoa of that dan carne to visit bim, and
saluting him, sat down at one side. So seatcd, he questioned
che
ExaJted one: "Sir [people] spcak of 'right view, right
view.' To what
cxtcnt is therc a right view?"
"This world, Kaccayaoa, is generally indined towards
two
[views]: cxistencc and oon-cxisrencc.
To him who perceives with right wisdom the uprising of the
world
as it has come to be, the ootioo of non-existence in the
world does
not occw. Kaccaya.na, to him who perceives with right wisdom
che
ceasing of the world as it has come to be, the ootioo of
existeoce in
the world does not occur.
The world, for the most part, Kaccayana, is bouod by
approach,
gra.sping and inclinacion. And he who docs not follow chat
approach and grasping, that determinacion of mind, chat inclination
and disposition, who does not eling to or adhere to a view: 'This
is
my self,' who chinks: 'suffedog chat is subject to arising
ariscs; suffcring chat is subjcct to ceasing, ceases,' such a person does not
doubc, is not perplexed. Herein, his knowledge js not
othcrdepeodenc. Thus far, ·Kaccayana, thcrc is 'right view.'
'Bverythiog exists,'- this, Kaccayana, is one excreme.
'Everything does not exisc,'- rhis, Kaccayana, is the second
extreme.
Kaccayaoa, without approaching either extreme, the Tathagaca
teaches you a docrrine by the middle.
Dependent upon ignorancc arise dispositions; dependent upon
dispositions arise consciousness; dependent upon
consciousncss
arises the psycbophysical personaJicy; dependent upon the
psychophysica.l persona.lity arise che six senscs; dependent
upon the
six senses arises contact; dependent upon contact arises
feeling;
dependent upon feeling arises craving; dependent upon·
craving
arises grasping; dependent upon ,grasping arises becoming;
det>endent upon becoming arises birth; dependent upon birch arise oJd
age and death, grief, Jameotation, suffering, dejection and
dispair.
Thus arises this encire mass of suffering. However, from the
utterlNTRODUCflON
fading away and ceasing of ignorancc, there is ceasing of
disposi·
cioos; from the ceasing of disposition.s, there is ceasing
of consciousness; from the ceasing ofconsciousness, there is ceasingof the
psychophysical persooality; ftom the ccasiog of the psychophysical personality.
therc is ceasing ofthe six seoses; from the ceasing ofthe si.x
senses, there is ceasingofcootact; from the ceasing
ofcontact, there
is ceasing offeeling; from the ceasing offeeling, there is
ceasing of
craving; from the ceasing of craving, there is ceasing of
graSpiog;
from the ceasing of grasping, there is ceasiog of becomiog;
from
the ceasing of becoming, there is ceasing of birth; ftom the
ceasing
of birth, there is ceasing ofold age and death, gcief.
łamencarion,
suffering, dejeccion and dispair. And thus tbere is the
ceasing of
this entire mass of suffering."23
ANALYSIS OF 1HE KACCAYANAGOTIA-SUTIA
11
The discourse is delivered in response to a fundamentał
question in
epistemology: "What is a right view
(sammadirtht)?" the Brahma1tila-suttanliJ
rcfers to sixty-two varieties of views prevalent during the
Buddha's day.i4 After
his enłightenment, the Buddha reałized that oone of these
were sacisfactory.
He was not willing to subscribe to any one of them. For this
reason, many
scholars of Buddhism have assumed that the Buddha did not
have a view to
present. Forthem, he had oo sixty-third view co propouod. If
that was the case,
the Buddha could have admonished Kaccayana not to be
bothered by any view,
whether it was right or wrong, true or fałse. However. that
was not the case.
The Budąha próceeds to enumerate tWO basieviews that are
prevaleot in the
world. The sixcy„two views referred to in the
Brahmajala-suttanta represent, in
one way or fillother. a proliferation of these two basie
views of permanent existeo.ce (atthitii, Sk. astitva) and non-existence
(n'atthilli, Sk niistitva). He chen
provides reasoos for rejecting both these 'Views. The
reasons arc epistemołogical
and therefore deserve detaiłed examinatioo. "For him,
who perceives with right
knowledge, the uprising of the world as it has come to be,
whatever view that is
i.o the world about non-existence will not ·be
acceptable."
The two terms of great epistemological significance that
occur in the above
statement are (1) "perceives" (passatz) and (2)
"right knowledge" (sammappa;Jfiii). There could be no mystery
associared with the implications of the first
of these two terms. Pa.ssali or "perceives" refers
to simple, ordinary sense
perception, for what is perceived is not something chat is
mysrerious bu~ simply ·
the arisiog arid ceasing of various phenomena in the world.
lt does not, at least12 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
in th.is instance, refer to a special or unique form of
insight not shared by the
ordinary people. What makes the difference is "r.ight
knowledge" (sammappanfia, or simply panifii), and that difference is then
explained in the next
paragraph.
The perceptions or sense experieoce of the ordinary person
in the world are
geoerally "bouod by approach, grasping and
inclination" (upaya-upadiinaabhinive.rt.i-vinibandha). They arc colored by
one's prejudices, by one's likes
and dislikes. lf a person is able to avoid such approach,
grasping-and inclinatioo, if he does not follow his dispositions, chen that
person would not cake a
detecmined stand and say: "This is my [per.rnanent]
self." He would perceive
phenomena in the world as arising and ceasing.
The perception ofarisiog and ceasing of phenomena
conditioned by various
factors is availablc even to ordinary people who have not
been able to completely
free themselves from prejudices. Thus, there is a common
denon1inator ber;ween the perceptioos ofan ordinaryperson and those of the
enlightened one.
However, the ordinary person continues to worry about a
permanent and eteroal substance behind phenomena or about a supreme being who
is the author
of all that happens in the world. He is assailed by doubtS about
wbat he
perceives. One way of overcoming such doubts is to confine
oheself to what is
given, chat is the causa! dependence ofphenomena, without
rrying to look for
something mysterious. The Buddha realized that "Wheo
phenomena (rlhamm'ii) appear befor<: the brahman who is ardenc and
contemplative, his doubts
disappear, as he sees their causal natute."2>
According to the Kaccayanagotta-sutta, if a person does no_t
make up his
mind that there is a permanentand eternal selfand continue
to look for it, but,
instead, merely uńderstands things as they have come to be
(yathabhUta'f(J), as
for example, understands suffering (dukkha) as something
that arises depending upon conditions, then he does not fa11 into doubc. In
other words, instead
of look.ing for mysterious causes one should start with
whatever .caµses one can
discover that are cootributory to each siruation. Of course,
in most cases. past
experiences arc a good index. Thus, in order to attain such
knowledge one does
not have to go around looking for a teacher who would
transmit that
knowledge in a secret session or in some mysterious way..His
knowledge would,
in chat case, 'not be other-dependent (apara-paccaya fla1Jam
ev 'as.ra etIha hott).
On the basis of such knowledge and experience, one is said
to have "right
view" (samm'ii-diftht). "Right view'' in early
Buddhism is cońt.rasted with
"wrong view" (mz~cha- rlitthz) . These ewo ace oot
contrasted in the way truth
and falsehood are contrasted in the pre-Buddhist cradicion.
In the latter case,
what is true is considered to be what exists (.rat).
Whatever ex.ists, is real, and by
definition whatever is real caonot be othcrwise. According
to this a pn'ori
definition, "truth" has to be something that
exiscs dlway.r. Yet, what is given toJNTRODUCTION 13
the sense expedences is nor available always. Hence it was
assumed that what is
true is something other than what is given to the sense
experiences, and that re·
mains always (saisata) and in everything. lt is the
ontological truth (atman) as
welJ as the mora.I truth (brahman) in evcrything.
As mentioned earlier, ::. theory of existence or a theory
that says "everything
exists' (sahba1{1 pttht) is wrong, not becausc it can be
proved to be false, but only
in the sense that it does not take into consideration the
empii:ically gi'ven fact of
cessation (nirodha). Hence, it is characterized as
"confusion" (musa, Sk. mrfii),
not as "non-existent" or "un-rruth" or
"falsehood" (P-satya).
· Avoidance of the theory that ''everything exists"
docs not, according to the
Buddha, make the opposite view, narody "everything does
not exist" (sab6P1{1
n 'fJttht), any tnore true. The reason for this is that this
latter theory implies
much more than a simple denial of a pcrmanent and eteroal
substance in man
(atman) or in the universe (btahman). 1t implies complete
discontinuii:y in.
phenomcna or their annihilation (uccheda), and this too is a
wrong view, not
bec.ause, like the former, it can be proved to be false, but
because it is partia! in
rhat som~ aspecrs of experience like arising (samudaya)
cannot be accounted for
by such a view.
The Buddha did not worry about discovering strictly Jogical
arguments to teject aoy one of these views. He merely avoided these two
theories in his explanation of existence. Hence his statement: "Without
approaching either excreme, the Tathagata teaches you the doctrine by the
middle" (ete te ubho ante
anupagamma majjhena lathagalo dhammaf?I desett).
The Buddha dearly distinguished hjs philosophy from that of
his contem·
porary, Saojaya Bella~~hiputta, who refused to make any
pronouncemeots
through fear that he would be found fault with.26 It makes
no sense to assume
that the Buddba, after criticizing the rwo exueme views,
avoided propoundfr1g
any view.or observed complete silence. Such an assumption would
undetmioe
the autheocidty ofalmostaU the docttines attr.ibuted to the
Buddha and wouJd
stand in the way of appreciacing the greatness of this
philosopher and spirirual
leader whose message clid not fade into oblivion, as .in the
case of the skeptic
Sat1)aya Bella~~hiputta , but instead became a formidable
world-view
throughout the last twenty-five ceoruries. For tbis reason,
the finał concłusion
of the Kaccifyangotta-sutta can in no way be ignoted as a
later interpolation by
the so-called Theravadtns.
In this fioal statement, the Buddha was attempting to
expfain the human
personality as well as its cicpe·rien~es in the world in
terms of the priociple of
dependence, without resorting to the two extreme views that
be criticized
earlier. ln the first part of that explanation, he was
describing the personality in
bondage, as it evolves conclicioned by "approacb,
grasping and inclination." ·
This is the twclvefold formula (d11adasang11) presented in
posicive terms,14 THE PHILOSOPHY OFTHE MIODLE W AY
describing the functions of ignotance, disposicions, and
behavior prompted by
such disposicions in the maner of propeUing human beings
into states of
uohappiness and suffecing as well as continued process of
binhs and deatłlS.
The negative statement e.xplains how, as a resułt of the
eliminacion of rhat igoorance and the dcvdopmeot of insighc, one comes co
pacify one's dispositions
a·nd ~hereby eliminate su.ffer'ing as well as the continued
cycle of births and
deaths. Such is the conclnsion of che Kacciiyanagotla-sutta.
The Ka&cayanagotta-sutla, though brief, lays down in no
unclear terms the
basie teachings of the Buddha. Funher elaboration of this
philo~ophy is
available in the huge collection of discourses of the
Nilcayas and the Agamas.
Although denying ex:istence and non-existence conceived of
in such a
mctapbysical manner, the Buddha recognized existence and
non-ex:istence in a
more empirical sense, such existence and non-existeoce being
understood in
terms of the experience of coosequences or effects (attha,
Sk. artha). Thus,
white bcing aware of the metaphysical implications of the
nominalized forms:
"exist-ence" (atthi-ta) and
"non-exist-ence" (n' atthi-fii), the Buddha continued to u~e che
verba! fo.rms "exists" (attht) and ''does not exist'' (n 'atthz) to
explain his view of existence.11
The existence of things as wdJ as their arising and P3:SSing
away arc clearly expressed in the famous formula:
When that exiscs, this comes to be; oo the arising of chat,
this
arises. Wheo chat does not ex:ist, this docs not come to be;
on the
cessation of chat, this ceases (/masmi'f!J sati idaf!t hoti,
imassa uppadii idaf!t uppa1j'ati. Jmasmif!t fi.fali idaf!t na hoti, imas.ra
nirodha
idaf!l niru1j'hatt).2e
Yet the linguiscic conventions of his day did not provide
che Buddha with
technicał terms to express this idea. The notion of
self-causation (.raya1(l kala1{Z,
Sk. .r11aya1'(l krtaf!l) was prevalent i.n the rradition of
his day, but unfortunately
it carried witb ie the implication of a mctaphysical
self(atman), permancnt and
eteroal (sassata), which he wanted to avoid.29 The idea of
external causation
(paraf'(l kataf'(l, Sk. para-krtatrJ) was not different from
the Materialist view of
anoihilation, especially in its denial of morał
responsibilicy,Jo A combinacion of
these rwo views was also not satisfactory, for the Buddha
was probably aware of
the implications of the Jaina theory of causation chat
atteropted to combine
both.H Under such circumstances, i.t was almost impossible
for him to express
his understanding of existence. This may also have
contributed to his initial
reluctance to exlain his ideas after this enlightenmenc.
However, he was equal
co the task.lNTRODUCTION I)
An attempt to explain rhe manncr in which a phenomenon gives
rise to or
produces aootber phenomenon, how a cause gives ri.se to an
effect, would have
involved bim not only in the taSk of unravelling the essence
or substance in a
cause rhat produces the effecr but ałso in the job
of.predicting the effect ari.sing
from a cause with absolute cenainty, a job for which he did
not have the
necessary empiricaJ mea.os. The Buddha decided to explain
this process in terms
of "dependence." He was thus led to speak of an
event that has occurred
(samuppanna) by uacing it back to a condition or set
ofconditions upon which
it depended (pa{icca). Having analysed the proccss of
becomiog (bha1Ja) in this
manner, he laid down a principlc that would cxplainfuture
occurreoces. Thus,
from observiog "dependently arisen"
(paficca-samuppanna) phenomena, he
asserted the principle of "dependent arising"
(paficca-.ramuppada). That termioology is indeed conspicuous by its absence in
the pre-Buddhist Indian
literature.
The old lndian term dhamia was retained by the Buddha to
refer to
phenomena or things. However, he was always careful to
define this dharma as
"dependeotly arisen phenomena"
(pa#cca-samuppanna-dhamma) . Most of the
controversies of the łater Buddhisrs centered on this
conception ofdharma, and
thercforc the various uses of the term in the Budaha's
discourses may be appropriatcly examined herc.
The term dhamma (Sk. dharma) has four rc!lated uses in the
early discourses.
{l ) Dhamm'ii (in the plural) meaning phenomena or things.'2
These arc the dependently arisen phenomena refer~ed to
earlier. They may also be described as elements
ofexperience.
(2) Dhammo (in the singulac) meaning the uriifotmity o(
phenomena ot things as represented by rhe principle of
dcpeadence (paficca-sarnuppada).H
(3) Dhamma (in the plural) referring to things or phenomeoa
cvaluated as good or bad in an ethical sense.H While good is
ofren designated dhamma, the notion of bad is expressed by
its oegation, (l-dhamma.
(4) Dha??JmO (in the singular) expressing che uniformity of
moral
phenomena, which ałso represeated the ideał or the standard
of morality derived from the mora! pcrfection attained by
the
saint. Hence, nibbana oc freedom is also called dhammo.
~>
In order to djstinguish this notion of dharnma from the
Indian concepcion
where the term dharma meant reality (atman), in an
oncological sense, the.
Buddha utilized the cooception of resulc or coosequc:nce or
fruit (attha, Sk. ar-16 THE Pl-IJLOSOPHY OF THE MIODLI! WAY
tha) to bring out the pragmatic meaning of dhamma. For the
Buddha.
whatever is true or real (bh'Uta, taccha) is alśo what
produces result (atthasa'f?lhita).36 This pragmatic definition of truth or
reality was moce often used in
expJaining mora! phenomena. Hence the reference to the three
types of results
or consequences or fruits:
1) bad, evil-an-atthf!, correspooding to a-dhamma.
2) good, beneficiaJ-attha, corresponding to dhamma, and
3) ulcimate good, ultimate fruit-param' attha, correspooding
co nibbana.31
BUDDHA'S CONCEPTION OF LANGUAGE AND TRum
While the term dharma, in the four contexts referred to
above, may be takeo
as implying empiricaJ truths, a more compreheosive use of
the term is also
available. In rhis case, the dharma (or sad-dharma)
expresses the ootioo of
"true doctrine," and without any hesitacion this
may be explained as a "true
st~temeot ,'' a use that may be most appealing to the modern
linguistic
philosopher who is generaUy averse to met.aphysics and
insists that "truth" pertains to statements. The use of the term
dharma in this sense at ooce renders
futile any attempt to speak ofa lioguistically transcendent
truth or reality in the
Buddhist cootext. ·
Dependent arising is the middle path presented by the Buddha
between the
extremes of etetnalism and annihilationism, ofstrict
determinism and chaotic
indeterminjsm, of absolute.reality and niliilistic
unreality, of permanent ideotity and absołute difference. Considedag the
mann.er in which he explained the
middle position between these extremes, no one could
maintaio that this middle position is beyond linguistic descciption or
uaoscends any forn1 of verba! expression. In fact, the two terms that are
generally utilized in the absolutistic
sy~tems ofIndian tbought to presentruch a standpoint, namely
''indescribable"
(avacya) and "indefinable" (anirv~antya), do not
occur in the.early discourses
of the Buddha. The ter:m "undeclared" or
"unexplained" (avyakata) occurs, but
it ~ used to refer to problems such as the duration and
extent of the universe,
the identity of or the difference betweeo che soul and the
body, as wełl as the
status of the tathagata after death- these beiog pcobJems
that could not be explaioed on the basis of any empirical evidence.~8 For the
Buddha, whatever is
empirically giveo is also describable or defiaabte without
having to Msume
!Uetaphysical standpoints.INTRODUCTION 17
Thus in the Buddha's view language is not, in itself, an
inadequate means of
expressing whac is cmpiricałly given. Yet modern incepreters
of Buddhism
seem to assume chat the Buddha considered Janguage
inadequatc to express the
truth about ex.istence that he d iscovered. The evidence for
such an intcrprctation is racher dubious. No attempt is made to examine che
Buddha's own
statements abouc his cnlighteoment, as recorded in such
9iscourses as "The Noble Quest" (Ariyapariyesana).l8 Most books on
Buddhism pubłished in the
modern world wiU atuibute to che Buddha, as well as to his
early disciples and
even to the łater ones łike Nigarjuna, a distinction between
sammuti and
paramattha. Sammuti (Sk. samvrh) is explained by Candrakirti
as language •0
and paramattha (Sic. paramartha) as ultirnace reality or
absołute ttuth. 41 The
terms sammuti as well as voh'lira occut in the early
discourses.41 Sammuti,
(derived from sam + V man ''to think") literaJly means
"agreement" and
therefore, "conventioo". Vohara (Sk. vyavaliiira)
means "usage." A rather lop-·
sided interpretation of rhese two terms as implying
"language" only has caused
havoc in the expłanatioo of the ceachings of the Buddha as
well as of Nigarjuna. Tbere seems to be no justification for confining the
meaoings of these
two terms to łanguage only.
Conventions (sammult) are of various cypcs- linguistic,
social, political,
mora! or ethicał, or even rełigious. Eveo a superficial
glance at pre-Buddhist
literary uaditions would reveal the manner in which the
Indians elevated
linguistic, social, political, morał , and religious
conventions to the level of absolute reałitics, permanent and ecernal. The
language of the Vedas became th e
absolute language, posscssing miraculous powers. In spite of
the existence of
such languages as Dravidian and Chinese, which have nothing
to do with the
Vedic language, some educated Indian schąlars stiłl believe
the Vedic is the
mothcr of aUlanguages. Therefore oot a single syllable of it
is to be tampered
with. Another convention, the social order consisting offour
castes, carne to be
considered absolute. Punishment awaited those who violated
it or ignored ie.
Arjuna was to be rewarded for maiotaining chat social order.
Political conveations derived their absoluteness from the absoluteness of the
social order. A
rules (k1atnya) who ignores the advice of the spirirual
leader and guide
(brahma1Ja)' was doomed to failure, since he was thereby
ignoring the law
(dharma). The absoluteness of the moral and ethical
conventions was equally
recogoized. No ocher form of moralicy except that which
concributcs to the
preservation of the social system was permissible, Rcligious
duties were specific
and unałtcrablc.
When, in che Sutta·nipata, the Buddha spoke of sammuti, he
was referring
to all these different kinds ofconventions .4~ According to
him, these coovc;ntions have come co be depending upon specific condicions
(puth111/ii). They
wece not absołute and ultlmace; rhcy were·noc universally
binding. The Buddha realized that when these convcncions were considered to be
absolutc and18 TuE PHILOSOPHY OP nm MIODLE WAY
ultimate (parama"!') they contributed to the worst form
of dogmatism (dittht),
which evenrually led to all the cooflicts (ka/aha, viggaha)
in the world.« These
constituted the worsr forms of obsession, obstruction,
constraint, or bondage.
Therefare, ilie Buddha claimed that a wise man (vidva) does
not approach (na
upei.1) such conventions.4) This does not mean that he
ignores all conventions.
fnstcad, he understands their conditionality and as welJ as
their fruitfulness
without clevating them to the level of ultimate realities,
thereby ma.king them
absolutei, or simply ignoring them as absolutely unreal and
therefore useless.
F,re"tdom (nibbana) could chen be interpreted more
appropriately as freedom
·ffom obsessions, obsessions for as well as against such
convencions. The
elimination of such obsessions or constraints (pap4fica)
turned out to be more
difficult chan abandoning pleasures ofsense, for if by
freedom was meant only
the łatter, the Buddha could have attained enlightenment
during the time he
was practicing self-mortificacion.
Herc again, the difficulty lies in adopting a middle path
without accepting
conventioos as being ultimate or rejecting them as being
usełess. The uniqueness of the Buddha's philosophy lies in the manner in which
a middle path
can be adopted with regard to any conveotioo, whethet it be
linguistic, social,
political, morał, or religious. Since the preseot aoalysis
of the Buddha's
philosophy is undenakeo ooly as a prelude to the examination
of Nagarjuna's
thought, and since the latter was more conceroed with the
,basic doctrines of the
Buddha, our attention at chis point will be focussed only on
the way in which
the Buddha adopted the middle pach in dealing with
linguistic conventioos.
As _poioted out above~~ term sammuti was used in the early
discourses to
refer to all kinds of conventions: Hó.wever, chere were two
terms that were.vCI'f
specifically employed to refer to linguistic conventions.
They are nirt#ti-patha
(the way of etymology) and adhivacana.patha (the way of
definitioo), The
Sarttyutt~nik'iiya contaios an important discourse dealing
with linguistic con·
ventions, which are neither to be clung to as absolute
truths, nor to be ignored
as mere conventioos. The discourse called Nirutti-patha runs
ćhus :
There are these three lioguistic conventions or usages
ofwords or
terms, which are distinct, have been distinct in the past,
are distinct
in the present and will be distinct w .the future and which
are not
ignorcd by the wise brahmans and recluses. Whatever materiał
form (rnpa) that has been, which has ceased ro be, which is
past
and has changed, is c.alled, reckoned and termed 'has been'
(ahost)
and it is not reckoned as 'lt CJtistS" (attht} or as
'it will be'
(bhavissatt). .. . [This is repeated for the other four
aggtegates:
feeling, perception, dispositions and consdousness.]
Wbatever
. materiał form has not arisen nor come co be, is called,
teckoned orlNTROOl)CTION
termed 'it will be' (bhavissatz) and it is not reckoned ;is
'ie eidsts (atthi) or as 'it has been' (ahost). , .. Whaeevet materiał form has
arisen, and has manifested itself, is called, reckoned, or
tecmed 'ie
exists' (atthi), and it is not reckooed as 'it has been'
(aho!z) nor as 'it
wiH be' (bhavissatt).'6
19
The Buddha advised his disciples "not to eling to
dialectical usage nor go
beyond the ł.imlts of linguistk convention"
(janapada-nirultif!t nabhinivese.yya
i?imafJfzaf?l natidhaveyya).47 Such being the middle
position adopted by the
Buddha regardiog linguistic conventioo, it would be an
extreme position to
maintain that language is either ułtimately real (as it was
the case with the Indians who made vae a supreme god) or that it is useless
when it comes to expressing ultimate reality. ·
For the Buddha, language derives its "meaoing"
(attha) when it is able to
p.roduce results (attha). and thus what is true (bhuta,
taccha) is that which bea.rs
results (attha-sarp,hita). 48 The Buddha did not recognize
anything rhat is fałse
to be productive of results. Truth in this sense can be
equated with "me.aningful" language. Thus, linguistic expressions
that imply permanence and annihilation would be "meaningless"
(an-attha) in that they do not commu"nicate
anything thac is given in e.xperience (dhamma), where
experience is understood
in terms of the felt results (attha) rather than in terms of
an indefinable
ultimate reality.
Having thus rejected the two views, namely, the traditional
Indian view that
che human personality consists of a permanent and eternal
spirirual ent'ity
(atman) and the Matetialist view the denied such a spiritual
entity and
recognized maccer (body) to be the only real~ty, the Buddha
continued to speak
of the psychophysical personality (nama-~pa), referring to
ie with such tetms
as "I" (aha'!IJ) and "you" (tvarp,) and
even the term "self' (atta) when speaking of
that personality.
With the emergence of Buddhism as a formidable phiLosophicaJ
and
spiritual movement that undermined the very foundations of
che tradirional
Indian phjlosophy and religion. Indian thinkers reformulated
their substaotialist world-view, presenting it in a morc subtłe and appeaJing
form in the
Bhagavadgzta. The notion ofdharma embodied in this text may
be analysed in
terms of the three Buddhist categories presented above,
namely, an-flrtha, ctrtha and pararrUirtha, Iastead of the pragmatic
definitions of the Buddhists, the
Indian thinkers were presenting a moce substantialisr
incerpretation where,
1) an-artha = che psychophysical personality (nama-rnpa)
which is uoteal and whic.h is corHtasted with rhe real self
(atman).20
2)
3)
THE Pl-l!LOSOPHY OFTHE MIDDLE WAY
attha = the permanent and eternal self(atman) in man, the
so-called dehin (the dweller in the body), which is in
bondage
because of attachmenc co che psychophysical personality, and
paramiirtha - = para11U1tman, which is the ultimate reality,
the universal self identified with God.
Thus was inaugurated an enormous controversy becween
Buddhists and Indian philosophers that continued to rage for severa! cenruries
until Buddhism
completely disappeared from the Indian soil as a
philosophlcal and spiritual
force around the seventh and eighty centurie.s, only to
survive and flourish in
the countries souch and southeast of India as well as in the
Far East.
~ -
THE PERIOD OF THE SRAVAKAS
The survival of a pragroatic philosophy in the face of an
extremely absolutistic tradition such as the one cmbodied in. the Bh4ga11adgT/a
was not
easy. One of the ways in which the Buddhists responded to
thac philosophy
was by compiling the now famous Buddhist classic, tbe
Dha1tJmapad11. As
the citle indicates, it was an attempc to counter the Indian
absolutist and
substantialist definition of dhamma. The Buddhist
philosophers, confronted
by the onslaught of Indian thinkers asserting the reality of
the self (atman),
spent most of their time analysing what they called dhamma
in o.rder to
show that there was no permanent and eternal self. As
Kenneth lnada has
rightly remarked , this represented 1'the most active,
highly vibrant and compecidve age in Buddhist bistory known as the Abbidhaana
period. ... lfthere
arc high watermarks to be considered in Buddhist bistory,
the Abhid.harrna
period certainły ta.ces a very high leveJ, a level of great
fermentation and
flourishment pf Buddhist thought. IdeologicaJly speaking, no
ocher period jn
Buddhist bistory, whether of the Tberavada or Mahayana, or
even national
Buddhist developments such as in T'ang Dynasty China, could
ever match, or
come up to the level of activiry as recorded during this
period." 49
Two complete sets of Abhidharma texts compiled during this
period are
available to us. One is preserved by tbe Theravadins
consisting of the foHowing
texts;
l. -
Dhammasangani,
2„
Vighanga,lNTRODUCTION 21
3. Dh111ukath'1i,
4.
Puggalapanńatli,
S. Kathavatthu,
6. Y1111111/ła,
and
7. Pauhana.
The other version was preserved by the Sarvastivada schooł
and comprises
one major work and six ancillary texts. They are as folłows;
1. ]fiangpraithana (atuibuted to Katyayaijfputra),
2. Sańgttiparyaya (attr. Maha Kau~~hila/Sariputra) ,
3. Prakaraf!apada (attr. Vasumitra),
4. Vijnanak'iiya (attr. Devaśarman) .
s. Dhatukaya
(attr. Pori:J~ or Vaśumitra),
6. Dharmaskandha
(attr. Sariputra/Maudgalyayana), and
7.
Prajńaptifastra (attr. Maudgalyayaoa).
That the Theravada and Sarvastivada schools preserved these
two bodies of
literarure does not make them sectarian, any more chan t_he
discourses, preserved by any school, could be branded as such. Ałthough the
treatment ofsubjectmatter io these two sets ofworks differs widely, the
subjecr-matter is pract.ically
the same. Both deal with the categories into which the human
personal.ity as
well as human experience carne to be aoalysed in the early
discourses where
tbey receive amore discursive treatment. The analysis of
human experience into
aggregates, eleme.nts, and faculties, all of which were
considered to be dharmas
~r elements of existence, seems to be the first and foremost
concern of the
Abhidharmikas. Undoubtedly, the purpose of this analysis is
co dcmonstrate
the absence of a self or substance in these phenomena.
Exhaustive analyses of
the various types of relations tbat obtain among them wece
also undertaken,
providing a sort of scholastic ad:v.ancernent in the study
of such phenomena,
but sti11 not deviating fro.m the fundarnental teac.hings
ofeady Buddhisip. Examination reveals that these two processes in some way
representan atte.mpt to
deal wich the same issues that the Buddha was concerned
wich, namely.
"dependently arisen phenomena''
(pa{iccaiamuppanna-dhamma) and "dependent arising"
(paficcasa1nuppada). The knowledge of these two processes was
looked upon as right understanding, which ułtimately leads
to the attainment
of freedom (niniiif!a).
Unfortunacely, ew.o of the schools thar were involved in
this Abhidharmic
enterprise were driven roo far in tbeir academic study of
the 4hfJN1UIS, probabJ.y
by the unrelenting criricisms łevelled against Buddhism by
the traditional22 THE PHlLOSOPHY OFTHE MIDDLE W AY
schoołs of Indian philosophy. These schoołs carne to be
knowa as Sarvastivada
and Sautrantika.
The Sarvastivada concluded their analysis ofdharmas with the
recognition of
ultimate discrete atomie elements which they wece unable to
put together even
with a theory offour basie relations. The result was that
they were compelled to
admir a singularly mec.aphysical conception of
"self-narure" (.rvabhava) to account for the experienced concinuity
of sucb discrcte phenomcna.>0 This selfnanae could not be Jooked upon as
something impcrmaneot and cbanging, for
thacwould be to defeat the very purpose for which it was
formulated in the first
pJace. Therefore they insisted that this self-nature
(svabhava, dravya) of dharmaJ remain during all cbree periods of time, the
past, the present and the
future. No ocher conception could be moce beretical in the
eyes of the Buddhisrs who were avowed non-substancialiscs (aniiJmaviidf ).
The view chat dhamJa.I have self-nacure had irs impru:t on
the cooceptioa of
"dependent ar.iśing" (prafiya-.ramutpada), the
central coocepcion in early Buddhism as wełł as in tpe early Abhidbarma.
Hcnceforward, "dependence" carne
co be expłained on the basis of self-natute. lt curned out
to be no mare different from the iden ticy theory of causation
(.ratkarya-11ada) formulated with
such precision, usiog logical arguments, by the Sankhya
school of thought.51
The celationship becween these two schools of thought is so
close that one can
hardly discount mucual iofluences and borrowings.
One of the schools chat reacted against chis concepcion
of"self-narure". other
than the tradition represcntcd by Moggauputcatissa·referred
to earłier, was the
Sautrantaka school of Buddhism. As ics name implies, this
school was openły
ancagonistic to the "treatises" (Jii.rtra) and
iosisted upon rerurning to the
"discourses" (sU.tranta) as sources for the study
of the Buddha-word.n lt considcred the notion of"self-nature" as a
theory of"self' (atma-11ada) in disguise.
Howevcr, for some inexplicable reasons chey failcd to
realize that neither a
theory of atoms (paramaf!u) nor a conceptioo of moments
(k!a11a) was part of
the early Buddhist teachings, either in che discourses or in
the Abhidharma
treatises. On che one.hand, chey p robably assumed that
these two conceptions
were not the root cause ofall the confusion among che
Sarvastivadins. On che
other hand, they felt that these two concepcions were, afcer
all. not incompatible with the docteioe of impermanence (anicca, Sk. anilya) in
che early
discourses. Wichouc abandoning atomism and momentarioess,
the
Sautrantikas proceeded to expJain "dependence" and
eoded up recognizing a
sorc of non-identity theory ofcausarion (asatkiirya-vada)
comparable to the one
proposed by che Vaise$ika school of Indian phiJosophy.B
Evcn though the Saucrancikas were openly critical of the
substantialist
conception of dharma advocated by the Sarvastivadins, their
reluctance to
abandon the theory of momcnrs (k.fa1Ja) Jeft them with the
difficułt task of ex-INTROOUCTION 23
plaining the experienced conrinuicy in the individuaJ
person. The ernergence of
schools filce "personalists" (pudgala-1iiida) and
"transm,igrationists" (samkrantt~
v'iida),>• closely related to and sometimes identicaJ
with the Sautraotikas, is indicative of the solutions that this school had to
offer in order to overcome the
dtfficulties arising from the accep tance of a thcocy of
moments.
The Satvastivlida and Sautraotika schools thus presented a
rather complicated set of theories, all concribucing ro philosophicał
confusion. The farmer
percdved a "self-nature" (svabh'iiva) in the cause
and emphasized the idenrity
(ekalfla) of cause and effect, while the latter, seeiog no
such "self-oature" but
merely perceiving "other-oature" (para-bhava).
insisced upon the difference
(niinatva) between cause and effect. The Sarvastivada
cooception ofself-nature
(svabhava) was extended to aJI phenomena, indudiog the human
persooality,
while the Saucrliocikas, denying self-nature in pheoomena,
surreptitiously iotroduced a conceprion ofself or peISOn (at1nan, pudgala) in a
human personality.
MOGGAllPUTIATI~A: THE FIRST REFORMER
The Russian-Buddhist scholar Tb. Stcberbarsky was one of the
first among
Western scholars to ignore the vecy significant differeoces
between early Buddhism and Abhidharma on the one hand, and Sarvastivada and
Sautrantika interpretations of the "discourses" and Abhidharma on the
ocher. For him, Sarvastivada was not only an interpretation of Abhidharma but
was Abhidhama,
and the early Buddhism of the discourses as well."
However, there was at least
one disciple of the Buddha who was not willing to accept
either the Sarvastivada or the Sautrlintika as the correct intetptetation of
Buddhism. This
was Moggalrputtatissa. Critical scholarship unforrunately
has blindly dismissed his views without much serious consideratioo, even though
they arc
presented with darity and logical acumen.
Almost 250 years after the Buddha and 300 yeacs before
Nagarjuna, Mogga.lrputtatissa was responsible fot the "great purge"
in the Buddhist tradition.
The Indian emperor Asoka, as he dcclared in his Minoc Rock
EdictS, was actuaJly
instrumeotal in unifying the Buddhist Order (Saf!Jgha) by
expelling the
miscreant and schismatist monks and getting them to don
white (lay)
garmentS. Yet, the backgro4nd fot this great purge was
prepared by MoggalTputtatissa wheo in his famous "Points of
Conttoversy" (Kath'iivatthu) be
refuted the ideas presented by almost seventeen beterodox
schools of Buddhism. "MoggalTpunatissa is said to have followed the mcthod
of discourse .
adopted by the Buddha-satthar'ii dinna-naya-11asena-at the
time he24 THJ! PHllOSOPl-IY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
established the matika, 'topics' of the
,K{111haJ11[11tthu]."'6 Th.is monumental
work is an attempt to go back to the early teachings, and in
doing so ~he
author, for the first time in Buddhist ·history , utilizes
even abscract logic.
Whether the use of such abstract logic. is appropriate is
not a matter that coocerns us herc. What is importaot is that Moggałfputtatissa
was critical ofcertain
ideas which were incompatible with the Buddha's phllosophy,
The· metaphysical theory of a person (pudgala), propounded
by the
Sautrancikas and rheir allies, was the first of the
mecaphysical views co be ta.ken
up for criticism in the Katha11atthu.>7 With great
ingeouiry and logical precision, Moggalfputtatissa descroyed the co·ncept of a person
propounded by the
Sautrantikas and established what may be called the
non-substantiałiry of the
human pecsonaliry (pudgala-nairatmya).
With equally cogent argumeoc.s, he anaihilated the
Sarvastivada, doctrine of
dhamza that implied substar:itial and eternal existence
(sabba'f{J sabbadii
attht),8 and established ·the non-substantiality of all
dharma.J (dharmanairiitmya]. These two unconuovertcd achievements, recorded in
one of the
most authencic texts, have been compJetdy ignored by those
who atcributed a
substanrialist theory of elements to the eady Buddhist
tradition.
EARLY MAHAYANA: THE SECOND REFORM MOVEMENT
The same text highlights anorher controversy that was
beginning co ntlł1e the
minds of Buddhist thinkers ducing the rhird cenrury BC and
which became the
topie of a heated debate during the fust and second ccnmries
AD. This pertained
to the questioo whether the Buddba is transcendent
(lokutlara). Moggauput·
tatissa rejected the view. gradually gaining ground in the
Buddhist tradition,
which favored craoscendence.'9 The biographies of the
Buddha, like the
Mahavastu
1 were probably not yet wricten. Mahayana, with its
conception ofa
coropleteły transcendent Buddha, had not come into existence
by that cime.
The Saddharmapu'łt/anka, which is responsible for condemning
the miscreant
monks (bhik!u) as wdl as the ideaJ of a saint (arhant) in
eiuly Buddhism, in"
dicates a graduał growth wich the finał version assigncd ro
the third century
AD. In the earliest versions of some of the early Mahayana
sutras, such as
Vajracchedika-prajnaparamita and the Kiiśyapa-pan·varta,
there is no mention
of a bodhisattva.60 .
What sort of Mahayana can chere be without the conception of
a ctanscendeot Buddha and the notion ofa borihiJattva? lt certainly ought to be
differeot
from the kind of Mahaya na that one comes across in che
avaiłab le versións oflNTRODUCTJON 25
the Saddharmapu„r!r;nka and other r:cxcs that indude a
condemnation of the
early arhant-ideał.
Iodeed the K.aśyapa-parivarta, even in the Sanskrit version
which is not the
earliest, will enable us to understand what that originaJ
Mahayana was. lt was
not the Mab.a:yana that carne to be deeply prejudiced
against early Buddhism as
weJl ~ Theravada, for, as pointed out eacJier, even though
we find a suong
criticism of the moak (bhik111). a criticism that may be
accepted even by the
Buddha and his disciples łike Moggalrputcatissa, this
criticism is not extended
to the early ideał of the "wonhy one" (arhant).
09e of the most important series of discourses ot
instruction (dharma~
paryaya) referred to in the Klifyap~pan·varta 'as "the
great pinade of gems"
(maha-ratna-kufa), percains to che "middle path"
(madhyam7i-prati'pat).6J
Hece we find a long list of middle paths, most of whicb are
described in
negative terms. However, side by side with the negative
descriptions, one also
discovers a positive description of the middle pach in ceans
of the twdve faccorś
of the human personał.ity (dvadasaizga). It is indeed an
abbreviation of the
Kacaayanagotta-sutta,"With Kasyapa as the interlocutor
or the person to whom
the discourse is addressed.
The need for negative descriptions, especially at a time
when Buddhahood
was nor yet looked upon as a transcendent state or as an
AbsoJute, caJls for an
explanation. Available historica1 records indicate that
soine of the canoaical
rexts chat emphasized the doctrine of non-subscanciality
(naimtmya) , and
which included the work of Moggatrputtatissa, found a haven
in Sri Lanka and
other South East Asian counrries after the third cenrury BC.
However, some of
the early discourses as well as some of the Abhidharma
teitts were still citculating in lndia and carne to be preserved in a Prakrit,
slighdy different from
Pali. Yet, what carne to be popular after the tbird cenrury
were the intCJpretations of the Buddhist metaphysicians, like the
Sarvastivadins- and the
Sautrahtikas. The early Mahayana that did nor indude either
the concept of
"ttanscendence" as applied to the Buddha or a
notion of bodhisattva, but
which emphasized a aegacive doctrine while at the same time
preserviag the
positive assertions of early Buddhism, was therefore a
response to the Sar-
. vastivada and Sautrantika metaphysics, rather than a
reaction to the early
Buddhism of the "discourses" or the Abhidharma.
N!igafjuna1s Mifsion
Nagarjuna, wbo lived at a time when the Theravada-Mahayana
conflicc had .
not degenerated to the level that is presented in the
SadclharmapurJt/aiika,26 THE PHILOSOPHY OF TI-IE MtDOLE WAY
therefore had an already different mission. It was indeed
not the least different
from the mission chat lay before Moggailputtatissa, to
expose the untenability
ofcerta.in heretical views chat were gradually becoming
popular in the Buddhist
uaditioo. A careful reading of the Kiirikii will ccveal the
fact that Nagarjuna
had all the help he needed to achieve this cask. As
mentioned before, even after
the transference of the Pali canon to Sri Lanka, che
discourscs and the
Abhidharma texts survived in lndia. Thus the discourses of
the Buddha as well
as the traditioo of the disciplcs (fravaka) were available
to Nagarjuua. The
humilicy with which Nigacjuna bows down to the BuJdha and
the respect with
which he treats the Buddha's disciples (Jravaka)61 are in
complcce contrast to
the unsympathetic attitude of the later Mahayanists toward
the eatlier Buddhist cradition.
In the foUowing analysis of che Kiirika, it will be shown
char Nagarjuna actempced to discredit heterodox views, especialły those of the
Sarvastivadins and
che Sautrantikas, and establish the non-substantialicy of all
dharmas (Chapcers
III - XV) as welł as the non-substantiality ofpudgala
(Chapters XVI - XXl) and
therc:after to explicate che positive doctrioes of che
Buddha as embodied io the
early discourses like the Kaccayanagoita-sutta.
The present analysis is, tberefore, conuacy to the more
popular incerprecacion ofNagatjuna espoused by commentators like Candrakirti
who emphasized
the reductio adabstJrdum (prasangika) metho~. lt will be
moce sympathetic co
the interpretations offered by Nagacjuna's disciples like
Bhavaviveka and the
moce positive thiokers of the Midhyamika school. While
highlighting the iogenuity and philosophical marurity cf Nagarjuna, the preseot
analysis wilł at
the same time be unsympathetic toward the mych that
Nagarjuna was a second
Buddha.
STRUCTURE OF THE KARlKA
Selec'tions from the works of a major philosopher belonging
to a tradition
may be hełpful in introducing that tradition but not in
providing acomplece
view of that phiJosopher's thought. The reason is thac when
a philosopher
presents his ideas io some form , he feels chat everything
he has said in chat
wock is relevant co his thought. If anything chat he has
said is ircelevant to what
he proposes to convey co his readecs, he would be not only
wascing his time, buc
also the readcr's.
Actempts have often been made by modern scholars co pick out
selections or
chapcers from the works ofernincocphilosophers of the East,
hopiog thereby coIN1'Rooucr10N 27
provide a complete and accurate picture of their ideas.
Sometimes they are c.onsidered to be essentialsecitons or cbapters, the
implication being th.at the rest is
inessential.6' This undoubtedly has conuibuted to a great
deal of
misunderstanding and sometimes deliberate distortion of the
author's ideas.
Coo.sidering the unsatisfaccoriness of such a method, the
present analysis of
Nagarjuna's thought will be presented on the basis of an
examination of his
Kiin'k'ii taken as a whołe, with ever,y word, every verse,
and every chapter in it
created as in integraf part of that work. This is done in
the absence of any concrete evidence that some portions of this work are not by
Nagarjuna.
A supetficial reading of this work, with 448 vetses divided
into 27 chapters,
could leave the reader with the impression chat the text is
repetitious. This
wrong impressioo will disappear like a mirage if one keeps
in mind the circumstances that led to the complication of this work, the
motivation for writing·
it, the background in which it was written, and the goal
that was to be achieved,
Such considerations will enable one to see a carefully
execuced plan or structure
in the Kiirika. In order to highlight di.is Stf\.lcture, the
Kari/iii will be aoalysed
hece into four major .sections, withouc changing the
sequence either of the individua! verses or of the cbapters.
Section I
This first seccion includes Chapters I and II. which deal
with the most fundame.ntal doctrines of Buddhism, causatioo and change. The
problem of causarion or "dependent arising" is taken up io the first
of these. If this were a cext
writteo during the Buddha's day , this cbapter would
undoubtedly have dealt
with theories of e.xistence presented by the traditional
schools of Indian
philosopby advocating the reality of a permaneot self
(atman) and the
Materialist school that denied such a self(an-atman) thereby
denying the concinuity of the human person as wdl as his mora! responsibility.
'HoweveI,
Nagarjuna was living in the second century AD and his
problems, as mentioned
earlier, were created more by the Sarvastivadins and the
Sautraotikas than by
the non-Buddhist schools. Th.is is dearly evidencfrom the
way in which Nagarjuna begins his first chapter.
The first verse in this chapter refers to four different
theories of causatioo or
arising: (i) self-causatlon, (ii} external causation, (iii)
both self- and external
causation, and (iv) arising out of a non-cause. After
enumerating four such
theories, any further explanatioń would naturally commeoce
with an analysis of
the first of these four theories, sełf-causatioo
(svata.utpattt). Thus, the four .
types of relations (pratyaya) referred co in the next verse
shoułd be takeo as ex-28 THE PHILOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE W/IY
arnples of the theory of self-causation (s,vata-uJpattt),
even though the most
respected modern interpreter of Nagarjuoa, narody T,R.V.
Murti, following
the footsteps of Candrak:Trti, took these four types
ofcausa! relations to represent the theory of externał causation, and not
self-causation.64 He assumed that
self-causation was ptesented by the Hindu schools and
external causation was a
theory advocated by the early Buddbists only. As explained
above, the early
13uddhisc theory ofcausation cannoc be placed under ~he
cacegoryofeicher selfcausation or external causation. Nagarjuna was clearly
aware of this and
therefo.re, even though in the tJJSt verse he denied the
p0$Sibility of any one of
the four causal theories, in the second verse he recognizes
four conditions
f.pmtyaya) without denying them~though to make his analysis
more comprehensive he denies a fifth condition. The denial comes onły in the
third
verse, but what is importaot to note is thar it is not a
denial of che four conditions (prtltyaya) but of the rnanner in which the
coodition is considered to be
relaced to the effect. When Nagarjuna said, ''The self
nature of an existent is
not evident in the causa! condition, etc." (Na hi
sfiabhavo bhavan"iit?i
pratyayadi;u11idyate, 1.3), he was not rejecting or denying
condicions, but only
self-nature (svabhava) that some philosophers were positing
in the condition
f.pratyaya) in order to account for the arising of the
effect. This is a quite elear
iodication that Nigarjuna was not rejecting the Adhidharma
theory ofconclitions but only its interpretation by some of the metaphysicians,
in this patticular case chat of the Sarvastivadins. As pointed out ·above,
there is every
evideoce that it was the Sarvastivadins who interpreted the
theory ofconditions
(pratyqya) on the basis of a concepcioo of substancc
(Ivabhfiva). In the same
verse, Nagarjuna proceeds to deny externał causation (partlkl-utpattz)
or, more
specifically, the conception of "other nature'~
f.par11--bliiiva) advocated by the
Sautrantikas. If this background is kept in rnind, the
understandiog of Nagarjuna's ideas in the Kiirika is not as formidable as has
been assumed.
Chapter II deals with the problems created.- not by an
empirical theory of
change and impermanence (anityata), for that was a
fundamentaJ conception
of early Buddhism- by a more metaphysical theory of change
and impermanence based on a logical or even a psychological theory of moments
(k;af!a-
1iiida).
Sectzon II
The second section includes thitteen chaptets, begioning
with an examination ofsense faculcies(lndriya, Chapter ITI) and ending with an
examination oflNTRODUCTION 29
substance (svabha11a, Chapter XV) . The entire section is an
attempt to establish
the doctrine of the non-substanriality of phenomena
(dharma-nairatmya)
without having to get rid of aoy one of the categories such
as the aggregaces
(skandha). spheres of sense (ayaJana), and ełements (dhatu).
all of which were
part of the early Buddhist teachings erobodied in the
discourses as well as in the
Abhidharma. Almost all the imporcant subjeccs dealt with in
early Buddhism
arc takćn up. once again not with the intentioo of rejecting
them, but with a
determination co rid them of a.ny metaphysical explanation,
espe~ially of existence (t11tit11a) and of non-existence (nastitva), implying
permanencc (fiiś11ala)
and annihilation (uccheda) which the Buddha was openJy
rejecting in the
Kaccayanagotttz.sutta.
Section III
The third secrion indudes eleven chapters from XVI to ~I. lt
is a section
chat has caused confusion in the minds of many who wrote on
Nagarjuna's
thought. First, many of the topics dealt with in the
previous section arc again
analysed here. Thjs gave the impression that the text is
repetitive and therefore
it is possible to ignore some of its parts when presenting
Nagarjuna's
philosophy. For example, the examination of action and agent
(karma-karaka)
was attempted in Chapter VIII , and a longer chapter (XVII)
on the examioation of the fruit of action (karma-phala) is induded in this
seccion. Secondly,
rhis particular chaptcr (XVII) deals with the docttine of
karma in a moce
positive way, asserting the existence of a moce appropriate
view than the one
criticized at the beginning of the chapcer. Such ao
assertion seems to go against
not only the doctrine of emptiness (śuyata), as it is
geoerally understood by
modern schola.rs, but also the view chat neither the Buddha
nor Nagarjuna had
a view to propound.
However, reading the eleven chapters one cannot help comiog
to the condusion that they were incended to establish the non-substanciality of
the individual (pudgala-nairalmya) but not to eliminate the cooception of an
individual or person altogether. The conception of the individual involves the
problems of bondage and freedom (bandhana-mo/qa) .ind, after
defining
these, five chapters arc devoted to the problem of bondage.
These five chapters
are undoubtedly commentary po a verse chat seems to have
been excremely
popular among the Buddhists and which both Nagarjuna and
Vasubandhu
wece cooversant with, for we find the latter composing a
whole treatise caUed
Karm4Iiddhiprakara11a.6>This verse is quoted by
CandrakUci 'in his commentary, and runs chus:30 nmPHILOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE wAy
Actions a.re not .destroyed even by [the passage of} huodred
myriads of aeons. Having reached the harmooy of condicions
and
the prope.r time, they bear fruits for the human beings.
Na pr_a„alyanti
karmil.t!i kalpako{ilatair api1
siimagrir(t
prapya kala'!' ca phalr#nti khatu dehinar(t.66
The deoiał ofa permanent self(atman) by the Buddha prompted
his critics
to insist that the Buddha coułd not satisfactoriJy explain
the problem of morał
responsibility. The present verse is only a summary of the
Buddha's causa.I explanation of the doctrine of morał responsibility, not an
admission of a permaoeot and eternał karma. In fact, the determinism that may
appear with the
reading of the fust line, is immediately corrected with the
conditionality
specified in the second line. Three main topics are dealt
with here: the imperishability of karma (aviprat{iiśa) , the harmooy of
tonditions (samagfi) and
the appropriate time (kala). It is therefore not surprising
to see Nagarjuna inserting two chapters oo "harmony" (samagfi. XJX)
and time (kala XX). after
stating the "imperishability" of karma (XVII) and
denying the existeoce of a
permanent and eternal "self' (atman , XVIII). To
eliminate any one of these
chapters as inesseotial co the underscanding of Nagarjuna's
thought is,
cberefore, hlghly unwatranted.
Mter a clarification of the meaning of bondage (bandhana) in
the context of
a human beiog who is without a permanent and eteroal self
and who still concinues to wander along experiencing births and deatbs,
happiness and suffering, Chapter XXII takes up a person who has attained
freedom (mokfa), who
has "thus gone" (tathagata) without'having to
waoder along as a person in bond~ge . No other issue in Buddhist thought has
been as misunderstood and
misinterpret~d. not only by the non-Buddhists, but also by
the Buddhists
themselves, as the conception oftathagata. Probably for this
reason, Nagarjuoa
felt the need to begin his discussion of freedom witb an
examination of the
conceptioo oftathiiggta. It will be shown that Nagarjuna's
arui.lysis follows exactly the method ofanalysis given by the Buddha. The
chapter that follows explaios the reasons for such misconcepdons (viparyiisa,
XXJII).
Modern scholarship on Nagarjuna has empahsizcd the
cooception of two
uuths to the c.oroplete oeglect of his explanation of the
fout truths as enunciated by the Buddha. It will be shown that the two truths
in Nagarjuna are not
an improvement on the four noble truths, nor a spccial
insight on the part of
Nagarjuna, buc an understanding of a doctrine that is
already clearly expressed
in the early discourses. This lengthy chapter (XXIV)
concludes with a recogni-INTROOUCilON 31
tion of the four noble truths and the docuine of dependent
arising chat is the
foundation of the four noble truths.
The chapter on 111niii11a (XXV) is a refutation of the
absolutisc interpretation
of the notion of freedom and a determined attempt to go
baclc to the nonabsolucist form of Budcłhism enunciated in the early
discourses.
Conuary to the view ot most modern scholars of Nigarjuna's
thought,
Chapter XXVI (Dvadailingapankf1i) is hece presented as an
ełaboration of the
Buddha's owo conclusion in the KJUcayanagotta-sutta. lt
deals with the Buddha's positive explaoation of how a human beiog in bondage
cin free himself
from the mass of suffering.
Section IV
Nigarjuna could have concluded his ueatise with the previous
secdon.
However, he was aware that his most favoritc discourse-che
Kaccayanagottasutta- began with che queston regarding "right view
(sammad1/th1). Nigarjuna has already explained almost every aspect of the
Buddha's doctrine and
sbown what conscirutes a "right view'' as against the
"wrong or confused views"
(micchadiflht) chat appeared in the Buddhist tradition. Yet
there wece some
views that che Buddha lefc aside without either asserting or
denying them.
These penained to the cen, and sometimes fourteen,
unexpJaioed or
undeclared questions (avyakata, Sk. avyakrta). A treatment
of these questions
was nceded bcfore Nigarj_una could make a finał comme.nt
about the attitude
of the Buddha, the "freed one" (nibbuta), with
regard to aJI varic:ties of vicws,
whether they be right or wrong. One could hardly cxpect a
better condusion co
a tcxt intended to bring about freedom from all obsessioos
(prapancopaiama)
than this last chapcer. lt represcnts an expJanation of the
higbcst form of
frecdom, chat is. freedom from ideoJogical cooscraints, thac
che Buddha as well
as his disciples (Jravaka) had actained and wbich made
Buddhism one of the
mosc tolerant religions ever to appear on earth.
ANAlYSIS OF 1li.E KARIKA
Part-I (Causa/ity and Change)
l. Conditions (pratyaya). The Buddha'~ main phiJosopbicaJ
insight, as has
heco shown, was expressed by the term "dependent
arising" (pa(i"asamup-32 'THE. P!-111.0SOPHY OP 'TłlE MIDDLE W AY
pada). It was presented against the four theories of
self-causation, external
causacioo, both self- and external causation and
non-causacion. Nagatjuna, be~
ing a true disciple of the Buddha, is thetefore seen as initiating
his prima.ty
philosophical treatise by categorically denying these four
causa! theorjes (1.1).
According to the Buddha, the four theories imply the
existence or nonexistence or both or neither, ofa permanent existence, an
eternal and substan.-
tial self (atman). That same impJication 'is assumed by
Nagarjuna when he used
the term bl:iiiva (instead of bhava) to refer to the
entities that are explained in
these four ways. Thus. in the very first stanza Nagarjuna's
denial pertains to a
metaphysical existence (bhiiva) and not to the empirical
notion of becomiog
(bhtt1N;) characterized by acising (utpada) and ceasing
(vyaya).
In verse 2, Nagarjuna refers to four types of conditions
(pratyaya), etnphaticaUy declaring that there is no fifth. However, therc is no
categorical
denial of the four conditions, compared to the denial of the
four causa! theories
in the previous ver.se. The reason for th.is is very
evident. Nagarjuna, a 'łery
sophisticated philosopher, realized that the Buddha rejected
the four causa!
theories mentioned in verse 1. He also knew that the later
Buddh.ist disciples
(J.riivaka) attempted to ełaborate upon the B.uddha's
conception of "dependent
adsing'' (praiityPJarnutpada) by formulating a theory of
four conditions
(pratyaya); these wece the earły Abhidharmikas. H e saw no
reason for an
outright rejection of the theory of foUI condicions.
However, io verse 3, he immediately takes up a particular
interpretation ofa
conditioo (pratyaya) and oegates it: "The self-nature
ofexistent:S is not found in
the condition, etc." lt is not difficult to see what is
being denied here. To
Nligarjuna, it seems that some philosophers werc
ioterpreting the Buddhist
(Abhidharmika) theory of four condicióas (pratyaya) in terms
Qf one or the
other of the theories mencioned in verse 1, whkh the Buddha
himself had rejected. Nagarjuaa could not have been unaware of the face chat
the
philosophers who spoke of conditions (pratyaya) at this
early period in Indian
thought were the Buddhists and not the noo-Buddhists.
Therefore, his attencion is now directed to these Buddhist interpreters and not
to the nonBuddhists.
As meotioned earlier, among the Buddhists the only school
that gave a
susbstantialist interpreracion of phenomena (dharma) during
this early period was
the Satvastivada school. Their theoty of self-nature
(S11abhava) carne
dangerously close to the Indian conception of self (atman).
Nagarjuna was,
therefore, mercly criticizing the view of the Sarvastivada
school of Buddhists,
who were suggesting a substantialist 1nterpretation of the
four conditions.
'fhus, the categocical denial in stanze 3 pertains to the
view of the Sar-.
vastivadins, who assumed a self-naturc or substance
(svabhava) of the existent
(bhava) in the conditioos (pratyaya).lNTROOUCTION 33
What son of argument does Nagarjuoa present in order to deny
the existence of self-nature? Murti and others who saw in Nagatjuna's method a
dialectic eomparable to that of Immanual Kant have
considered self-nature
(111abhava) and other-nature (parabha11a) as antinomies.
This may be true.
However, such a dialectic is not used by Nagarjuna in his
first refiitation of the
nocion ofself-nature. Nagatjuna rejects self-nature, not
because ie is relative to
other-nature, but: because it is not evident (na 11idyate).
The argument from
relativity is utilized'. to reject other-narure onły and not
self-'natuce. ("In the
absence ofself-nature, other-nature is ałso not
evident.") What is found hece is
a simpJe and sttaighdorwatd denial ofself-nature on
epistemologicaJ grounds,
even though h e does not elaborate upon tbat epistemology at
this point.
Throughout the text, one finds Nagarjuna using the negated
verb, na vidyata,
and somecimes the ptesent participle, avidyamiintJ. The
former is often
rendeced as "not found," and in our ttanslation
preference is given to the more
epistemologically oriented rendering; "is not
evident." This emphasis is dearly·
evident from the manner in which he rejects
"self-nature," as explained above.
In other words, Nagarjuna appears more as an empicicist than
as a diałecti·
ciao who merely utilizes reason. Thus, the text begin.s with
a simple deniał of
self-narure as something that is not evident. What Nagarjuna
means by
evidence will be expłained later oo in this essay. If this
point ls kept in mind, it
becomes rather easy to understand the rest of Nagarjuna's
analysis of condi-
.
uons.
Thus, in the verse that follows (1.4), Nagarjuna speaks of
action (kriya) and
conditioo (pratyaya). In this case, neither the action nor
the condition is
denied. What is denied is the sort of 1elatiooshlp that is
assumed between
them, that is, ioherence which emphasizes identity. The
denial of identity is
prompted by the fact that it is equated with
"sdf-nanue'' (wabhava) which , in
its turo, was looked upon as a permaneot entity. Difference
was likewise denied
because it was perceived as other-nature, which implied
annihilation or lack of
any continwty.
Verse 5 takes up the definition of a coodition. A condition
is such because
depending upon it others arise. However, the teason why
Nagarjunarejects this
definition is not that it is not empiricalły valid, but that
there j5 a rider attached
to the definition, That rider impUes that this dependence is
eteroał and permanetlt. ln other words, that which is dependent and that upon
which it depends
a.re substaotially coOI)ected through a telation of
inherence. Hence,
Nagarjuna's queston• "So long as it [the effect] does
not arise, wby is it Ithe
cause] not coosidered to be a non-condition?"
Verse 6 completes Nagarjuna's generał criticism of
eonditions. Most modern
translators have failed to bring out the significance of
this verse, primarily
because the term artha ( = effect, fruit, result, rendered
into Chinese as kuo)34 THE PHILOSOPHY OFTHE MlDDLE WAY
failed to attra.ct their attencion. What is denied is,
therefore, not the arising of
an effect as ordinarily understood, but the arising.ofan
effect that is already ex·
istent (sato arthmy11) or one that is non-existent (asato
arthtJJya). These again
represent the identity (1atkarya) or the oon-identity
(a..ratkarya) theories of
causation presented by the Sarvastivadins and the
Sautrantikas.
Verses 7-10 represent the criticism of the four types of
conditions referred to
at 1.2 as interpreted by the Sacvastivadins and the Sauttantikas.
Ifthe 1at(existent) and a1at (non-existent) qualifying dharma (phenomena) are
undetstood
as implying "the substantia1ly (1vabha11ato) existent
and oon-existent," a
quatification that Nagarjuna often make~. then it will be
easy to understand
the nature of Nagarjuna's criticism. This is especiaJJy so
in verse 10 where, on the
surface, it appears that Nagarjuna was criticizing the
Buddha's owo statement:
"When that exists, this comes to be," (t1Jmi'f?'l
.rafidam bhavatt). However,
Nigarjuna was very careful in dealing with this stacement,
for in the first line
he was explicit with regard to the sort of existence he was
criticizing, that existence being none other that "substancial
existence" (sat-ta).
Verses 11-14 deal with severa! other aspects of the theo.ry
ofcausacion such as
the arising of an effect from a combination of conditions.
lt is indeed the coocluding line of the last verse (1.14) that possibly can
give rise to all the
inisunderstanding regarding Nagarjuna's analysis of causa!
conditions. "In the
absence of the effect, whence can thece be a condition or a
non-condition." lt is
easy to interpret this statement to-meao that Nagarjuna did
not accept either a
cause or an effect that is dependent upon a cause. To take
it as a sirople deniaJ
ofcause and effect would be to ignore evetytbing that
Naga.rjuna has beeo t.ty·
ing to say earliet in the chapter, regarding self-nature
(s11abhava) or substantial
or permanent
ex.isteoce (sal). Thete seems to be no tationałe fot interpteting
this statemeot independent of the basie premises with which
he set out on his
examinacion of conditions. To conclude; Whar is denied bere
is not the simple
effect that depends upon the condltion or conditions for its
acisiog, but an effecr rhat is either pre-existent, and therefore permanent, or
oon-existent
because ie is not pre-existeot. It is also teasonable to
assume that a siroilac
denial pertains not to a simple cause or condition but to a
cause or condition
that produces an already existent or non-existent effect.
"Dependent arising" or casuaJity
(pratftytZJamutpada) was, to reiterate, the
principle in terms of which the Buddha was able to explain
the funccioning of
phenomeoa (dharma) without resorting to a conception of
permaoent and eternaJ entity (nitya atman). In other words, dependent arislog
explaios the impermanence (anityata) ofphenomena·that are dependently arisen
(pratftytJJam1ttpanna) without which no identification of "dependent
arising" is possibJe.
Bccause such phenomena acc dependently arise, they acc rmpecmanent
(anitya). Impermaneoce involves change and
movement.lNTRODUCTION
2. Change or movement (gat'iigata). Chapter Il of the
Klin'kiis is an attempt to
reconsider this conceptioo of impermanence, i.e., change or
movement. Such a
reconsideration, Jike the examination of causality, w.as
necessitated not by a
de.sire to transcend it but by a desire to return to the
original teachings of the
Buddha. Herc too the watets were muddied by the speculations
of the Sarvastivadins and the Sautrantikas. In the first instance, Nagarjuna
was compelled
to re-examine the conception of causality because these two
schools wece confronting eacb other as a result of the former's recognition of
a self-nature or
substance (svabhava). Why did the conception ofself-na,ture
emerge at all? As
we have seeo, the two schools had wrongly conceived of
change and impermanence.
The Buddha descrihed time and temporality in a more
empirical way when
he said tbat the arising of pheoomena, the change of what
has come to be and
their cessation arc evident.67 The three temporaI petiods of
past (affta), present
(paccuppanna), and furure (anagata) in rełatioo to phenomena
were thus
tecognized. To refer back to the discoutse on
"Linguistic Conventions" (Niruttip4tha) mentioned earlier, the Buddha
even examined the three linguistic conventions (adhivacana) such as
"existed" (ahost), "exists (attht) and "will exist"
(bhavissatt), pointing our that these should not be ignored.
However, in their enthusiasm to demarcate the boundaries of
the three
periods of time, the Sarvastivadios and the Sautrantikas
were led to an atomie
notion of time and temporałity,68 unaware of the dangers
chat lay ahead of
them. [n order to overcome the clifficulties they faced as a
result of their acceptance of an atomie conception of time, the Sarvastivadins
were bold enough to
admit an underlying substance that remaios unchanged, eveo
though they did
not (ealize that sucha docttioe was incompatible with the
Buddha's notion of
non-substantlality (anatman). The Sautrantikas, on the
contrary, denying such
a substance and claiming themselves to be the fafrhful
interpreters of the
discoutses, stili maintained the momeotary destructioo
(h.a11abhanga) of
phenomeoa. They did not realize that their conceptioo of the
momentary
desttuction of phenomena was forcing them to recognize a
subtle
transmigracing entity. Hence, they carne to be characterized
by their opponents
as "transmigrationists" (saf!tkrantivadin).
Nagarjuna's attempt, therefore, was to show that a
speculative notion of
time and tempor~ity such as the one emphasized by the
Sautrantikas was not
an empirically justifiable one. A modern critic ofa simiJar
conception of time,
Williamjames, has provided the following analysis: ·
In short, the practicaJly cognized preseot is no
.knife-edge, but a
saddle-back, with a certain breadth of its own on which we
sit perchcd,36 TuE PHlLOSOPHY OF TiłE MIDDLE WĄY
and from which we look into two directions into time. The
unit of
composition ofour perception of time is a duration. with a how
and
a stera, as it were-a rearward- and a forward-Jooking end.69
The very first verse in Chapter II suggests the kind of
movement or motion
that is under ctiticism: "What has. moved is not being
moved."
For someone ro daim t~at what: has already moved (
=present), the underlying assumption is that eveo though there is a distinction
in terms of temporality,
there is indeed the sense in which what is being moved in
the present is not different from what, on an earlier occasion, was also in a
state Óf moving. This can
easiły give rise to the view that phenomeoa are in a
constant flux, a continuous
uninterrupted flow (santatz). While such an explanation may
account for the
continuity of phenomena tha.t are analyscd into discrete
events, it aL50 explains
the ideotity of cach inruvidual stream (santiina). This
latter idea, carded to its
extrernes, led to the roetaphysical notion ofa subtle but
substantial pcrsonality
(pudgala), neither 1dential nor differentfrom the
a,ggregates (skandha). This is
the school of "pcrsonalists" (pudgalavada).
Thus, following the same method chat he adopted in
criticizing the substantialist ootion of causality, Nagarjuna focuses his
attention on the metaphysical
interpretacions of ideas of change and movement, without
atternpting to deny
the cooccpts such as "the moved" (gata), "the
not moved" (agata), or "the present moving" (gamyamana) perse.
After a detailed analysis of the unhealthy
consequences of such metaphysical interpretations,
Nagarjuna, in che end,
specifies the sort of view he is criticizing when he
maintained:
An existing mover does not carry out the movement in any
ofthe
three ways. Nei~er aoes a non-existiog mover carry out the
movement in any of the three ways. Nor does a person carty out a movement, both
existing and non-existing, in any of the ®ee ways.
Therefore, neither the morion, nor the mover, nor the space
moved
is evident. (Il.24-2~ . )
The 'existing mover' (stlflbhuto gania) is indeed similar to
the 'exitcot'
(bha11a) possessing self-nature (s11abha11a) which was
criticized in the previous
chaper. The denial of morion, the mover 1 and the space
moved is thus not a
categodcal denial but the denial of a substancialist
interpretation of these
phenomena.
Even though the refutation of che subscantiaiist view of existence
(bhava,
s11abha11a) remains- the primaty coocern in Chapters I and
II, the ideas examined
in Chaptet I seen1s to be predominantly those of che
Sarvastivada school, while
Chapter II seems to _conccntrate more on the teocts of the
Sautrantikas, whoINTRODUCTLON 37
were mote aligned with the "transmigrationists"
(.raft'k.rantivadin) and the
"personalists" (pudgalavadin).
The m ethod developed in these two chapters provides a large
framework oo
the basis of which the innumerable concepts are analysed in
the chapters that
follow.
Part II (Dharma-nairatmya)
As mentioned earliec, Cbapters lll and XV deal with almost
all the major
Abhidharma categories that are treated under general rubric
"dharma." Of
these various categories, the most irnportant are aggregates
(.rk.andht1) .
faculties/spheres (indriyalayatana), and elements (dhiitu).
T~is is the order iJł
which these are normally eoumerated. However, Nagatjuna was
interested in
epistemoJogy, and therefore ie is natura! for hlm to take up
the faculties (indriya) for examination at the very outset.
3. Faculties (indriya). Chapter !Il, verse 1, refers to the
six faculties and their
spheres. Yet, there is oo denial ofany one of them. This
roay be compared with
Nagarjuna's statement in Chapter 1, verse 1, chat refers to
the four causaJ
tbeories, all of which ·were iostantly deoied. However, in
verse 2, Nagarjuna
criticizes a parcicular defu1ition of ''seeing'' (darfatJa)
and that definition involves "the perception·of itself"
(.rvat1!J(Z11af!J darśanaft') . This undoubtedly is
the Indian version of the Cartcsian ':c;ogito" which
led to the belicf in a perma·
nent and eternal self during the period of the Upani!ad.r;0
and continued to
flourish in the speculations of the later Indian
philosophical schools.H lt rs the
defioition that p.coduced the most roetapbysical of ideas,
such as the conception of the "inner controller" (antaryiimin) chat
tums out to be the permanent
and eternal self or souJ (atman). Any form of perceptioo,
fot them, involved
self-awareness as a necessary pre-condition, after which
every ocher form of activity follow~. In fact, łater oo Nagarjuna devotes an
entire chapter (IX) to an
examination of this notion ofan antecedent self. Whether
this view influenced
the Yogacara conception of "self-perceiving
consciousness" (s11a.raf{1vedaka-
11ijfifina) remaios to be scen. For Nagarju.na, however,
sucha defioition was not
sat:isfactory, sioce it implies the conception of a
substantiał entiry.
Here again. after ma.king a categorical denial of
"śeeing" as "seeiog itsełf,"
Nagarjuoa procecds to draw the implication, as he did in his
criticism of othcrnature (para-bh'iiva, 1.3) , that "if seeing cannot see
itself, how caQ it see .
another?" Such a cridcism on the part of Nagarjuna
would srill Jeave inract che
Buddha's owo expianatioo of perceptual experience in terms
of the pciociple of
dependence (prafitya.ramutpada). Cn fact, it is for this
reasoo that łater on38 THE PHILOSOPHY OFTHE MIDDLE Wt.Y
Niigiirjuoa was able to speak of visual perceprion (cak;ur-11ijflt1nt1)
as a product
of causal dependence (sec XXVI.4).
The criricism of "seeing" (thrlt1na) in 111 .~ is
similar to the criticism of causa!
condition in I. 5. Nigarguna assumes that the implicacion of
the substantialist
notioo of "seeiog" is that "sceiog must
always sec." Thus, if the Sarvastiviidins
wece to recognize a "self-natute" (wt1bhava) in
"seeing" , then it could possibly
not be "not seeing" even on some occasions, for
the very nature of sceing is to
~e . Therefore, when Nagiirjuna asserts that "tbere
cannot be a non-seeing seeing'' (1111 tTj;afytlffliinaf!I- dańanaf!J), he was
merely stating the substantialist definition of the Sarvastiviidins. Hence the
second statemcnt "seeing sees' (thrlt1n11f!1.
p4iyat1) becomes a merc tautology and, as such, is not
appropriate. The rest of
the chapter deals with a criticism of all forms of
perception conceived in the
above manner , indicating tt"lt "grasping"
(upatliina), etc. wilJ remain inexplicabłe in such a contcxt.
4. Aggregates (skandha). Of the five aggregates into which
the human personality carne to be anałysed in the Budd.łUst tcadition,
Nagarjuna takes up only
the first, namely, materiał form (ripa). .After expłaining
Niigarjuna's treatm~nt of materiał form , Inada rightly remarks: "But all
this does not mean that
neither rupa nor che elemencs cease to exist."'2 This
confirms what we have said
about Nigarjuna's treatment of other concepts such as cause,
effcct, morion, or
secing. However, lnada's expłanarion of the reason for this
needs to be
qualified. He maintains: "Nigarjuna is only trying to
exhibit the face that any
cooception or thing cannot be describcd by rcfcrencc to a
simplc cause-effect
rclationship in order to escablish its existentiaJ status.''
On the contrary, it
seems that Nagarjuna may not have aoy difficułty in
maintaining that there is a
simpłe cause-effect· relationship betweeo d1e four primary
clements (manbliuta) and material form (riJpa), so Jong as char cause-effect
relatiooship is
understood as one of dependence, which was the Buddha's owo
view.n Yet,
what is being introduced herc is not such a simple theory of
dependence of the
effcct upon the cause.
The conception of k'iir1111ti chat Nigarjuna refers to hcre
is one of the six
causcs (hetu) referred to in the Sanskrit .Abhidbarma texts
and interpreted by
the Sarviistivadins as a "unique cause," that is,
"anything other than itsełf"
(s11ato 'nye Riira„ahe111f?). H In other words, it is any
cause whose self-nacure is
different from that of the effect. The four grcat element.s
(mahabhuta) depending upon ~hich the material form (nipa) comes to be would be
the kiir111!11 of
materiaJ form. Yet as a k'iira'fa of materiał form it would
be distinct from
_materiał form. lt is this panicular definition of ~'iira„a
that is criticized by
Niigiirjuna. His reason for denyiog it is stated in IV.2:
"lf materia! form is
scparatcd from the unique-cause of materiał form [i.e. the
four great elemeots],fNTRODUCrJON 39
it would imply thar macerial form is without a cause
(ahet11ka)." However,
Nagarjuna's empiricist and analytical approach does not
allow him to recognize
an effect (artha) which is without a cause (ahetuka).
Existence (bh'ii11a), wbich Nagarjuna was ofreo criticizing
iroplied selfexistence (s11ahha11a). The fact that the Sarvastivadins defined
not only materiał
form, but also the other four aggregates-feeliog,
perceptioo, disposition, and
consciousness-as self-exiStent entities (bh'iiva) is evident
from Nagarjuna's
statement at IV.7. Thus, Nagarjuna's basie criticism of the
Sarvastivadins in
this chapter is that they could not consistently speak of a
unique cause
(karar,a), while at the same time recognizing a cause and an
effect that arc
related by way of self-nature (svabhava). In other words,
the notion of selfcausation (svatotpath) contradicts a "unique cause"
(kara?Ja), for it is anythlog
other than itself.
5. Elements (dhatu). In the early Buddhlst tradition, the
psychophysical personality was ~ysed into five agg,regates (skandha) in order
to show that there
was no permanent spiritual entity or self (atman) as
recognized by the traditional Indian phllósophers. Therefore, rhe psychic part
of the personality was
analysed in detail. In order to refute the view of the
Materialists that the eternal
entity is matter, not a spiritual or psychic entity, the
Buddha once again analysed
the human personality into six elements (dhatu) witha
detailed examinatioo of
the physical part of the persooality. 'rhus we have the
category of ełements consisting ofearth {Prth111) , water (apm) , fue (tejm),
air (vayu), space (akafa) and
consciousness (vijńiina). ·
While the cooceptlon ofa "unique cause" (karafła)
was iotroduced in the ex.
amination of the aggrcgates (skandha), the notion
of"characteristics" (lakfal'Jtl)
is brought into the analysis of elements (dhatu}. Though the
term
"characteristic" (Pali lakRhaf!a) occurs in the
eady discourses, there it is not used
in the rnetaphysical sense in which it carne to be empłoyed
by the Sarvastivada
school. For ·the Sarvastivada, a characteristic (lak,a„a)
represented the changing
.aspect of an entity (dhtlf'l1t4), while self-nature
(svabhiiva) stood for the un·
· changing and eternal aspect. This particular notion of
"charactetistic" needs to
be kept in rniod when analysing the cootents of Chapter V.
A "characteristic" is cvaluated here in relation
to an existent (bhiva) which
posscsses self-nature (svabhava). For the Sarvastivaclins,
this existent was a
dharma. Hence, very often we find Kumarajfva utilizing the
tecmfa (= dharma), in its restricted sense, to render bhava(yu), which is an
indication that he
too was aware of the nature of the concept analysed by
Nagarjuna. Nagarjuna's
major endeavor hece is to demonstrate the difficulties that
ar.ise when speaking .
ofcharact.eristics (lak,a11a) in relatioo to eternaJ or
absolute existence (bh411a} as
well as nihilistic non-existencc (abhava).40 THB PHU.OSOPHY
OF TiłE MIDDLE WAy
This analysjs becomes all the more 'important because of the
way bhava and
abhava are treated hece. Nagarjuna's condusion is sigi:iificant:
"Those people
of łitde inrelligence who perceive the existence (t11tilva)
as we11 as the nonexistencc (nastii-va) of existents (bhava) do not perceive
the peaceful appeasement of the object (dratfavya)"(V.8).
In .the Buddhist text:S, including the Karika, we read more
often about the
· appeasement of obscssion (prapaflcopasama). However, for
the first time,
Nigarjuna introduces the nocion of the appeasement of the
"object"
(dra1tavyopaiama). Why?
It was mencioned eadier that the Buddha's ruscourse oo the
aggregates (skandha) was incended to refuce the nocion of a spiritual self
(atman) and the
discourse on ełemencs (dhatu) was meant to reject the notion
of.a materiał self
or eteroal matter. If this supposition is correct, we have
no difficulty in
understanding the reasons fot Nigatjuna's introduction of
the idea of appeasing the object. The objects of perception associated with the
first five sense
faculties a.re materia!. If the Materialists wece looking
for a self(atman) in matter and the Sarvascivadins wece looking fór .a
seJf-narure (svabhava) in the
same, the best advice a oon-substantialist like Nigarjuoa
could give such pe~
ple is to "vaporize or liquify" the object, and
avoid grasping afcer ie. For Nigarjuna, there was no difference becween
self(atman) and self-nature (svabhava).
While they carry the same philosophical impUcatioos, their
praccical consequences are also similar, in that both lead to grasping and,
therefore, suffering.
Abandoning grasping (upadana) for the object, one elin1inates
the
metaphysical beliefs pettaining to eternal existence
("stitva) and oihilistic nonexistence (nastat1111). Hence the emphasis on
che appeasement of the object. lndeed, "the appeasement of the
object" (drartavyopafama) is the means by
. which one can realize the ''oon-substantiatity of
phenomena" (dharmanairii.tmya) and it does not mean the ełiminatioo of the
object.
Unleśs one were to keep in mind this particular cootext in
which Nagarjuna
was emphasizing the "appeasement of the object,"
ie would be easy to assume
that here Nigarjuna was justifyiog idealism
(11ijfiana11ada). Candr~rci's comments, unfortunately, lead to such unwarranted
condusioos.n
6. Lust (raga). The Buddha coosidered lust (raga) to be the
cause of most of the
llls of life, the worst of these being bondage. Freedom
(niroaf!a) was th'us defined
as absence of Just (vairagya). Not ooly did he speak of!ust
and absence of Iust,
he also often spoke of people who are lustful (rakta) and
free from lust
(virakta). Yet, all such statements were made with no
assumpcion of a co.ocealed
substaoce (svabhava) or of a mysterious spiricual or
materia! personality. The
analyscs offaculties (indriya), aggregates (skandh4) , and
elements (dhatu) were
. .intended to demonstrate rhe futility of such assumptions.
However. the Sar-INTRODUCTION 41
vascivadins conceived of a su.bstaoce in every element,
while the Sautrantikas
posited a mysterious personality. Therefore, it became
necessacy for Nagarjuna
to examine the concepts of lust (raga) as wełl as the lustful
(rakta). A varicty of
unsatisfactory implicatioos tbat arise out of the
SarVastivada and Sautriiotika
interpretations is clearly presented in Chapter VI, with the
cooclusion: "Tuus,
with or without the lustful, !ust is not established. Like
lusr, aJI things. with or
without [accompanirnents], arc not established."
Once again, we sboułd not focget the fact chat the dharmas
referred to herc
are those that were recognized by the Buddhist
metaphysicians, not the empirical phenomcna as defined by the Buddha and the
earJy Buddhists.
7. Conditioned(saft"krta). The carly discourses
referred to three characteristics
of the conditioncd (sa1{Jskrta). 76 Tbese wece arising
(ul/iiida), change of what
has come to endurc (Jthitasya anyath'iil11a), and ceasing
(vyaya). In a similiar
discourse, a definition of the "uncooditioned"
(aiaf!Jskrta) is providcd and, in
this case, it is said chat the three characteristics
mentiooed above arc not evident. It was, tberefore, easy for some of the later
·auddhists to Jeap to the
conclusion rhac the "uncooditloned" is aJso
uncaused or independent
(apralityasatnutpanna). This, evidentły, was the intention
of the Sarvastivada
commcntator, Ya.Somiua, when he stated thar the terms
''conditioned"
(sar.Mkrta) and "dependent" (prafityasamutpanna)
are synonyms.n Yet, fcom
other statements in the discourses, it is elear that this
was not the case. For example, white the threc teims 11ni&ca (impermanent),
Ifl?!Ukrta (conditioned),
and pralilyasam111panna (dependent) occur togethcr (though
not as
synonyms), co explain the naturc of the wotld ,11 , of their
negativc forms onJy
abhuta and asa'!Joskrta (together with t1Jala, and akrta1?)
arc used to
characte1·1ze nirvana. The negative form
ofpra!ityaiamutpanna does not occur.
For this reasoo, it can be maintaincd that the term
saftUkrta has the specific
meaning of"dispositiooally conditioned," and is
not idencicaJ in meaning with
the term prafflya1a11'11tpan11a ("dependent").
Not only did the Buddhist mctapbysicians ignore this subde
distinction and
considered the concepts of "conditioned" and
''dependent'' as being identicaJ,
they also explained the "conditioned" in terms of
their metaphysicaJ notions of
substam.:e and theit speculative notion of temporality
referred to carlier. Nagarjuna's Ieogtby chapter oo the subject of "The
Conditioned'' (Sal'!Mkrta, VII)
draws out all the implicatioos·of such metaphysics.
Mter rejecting the metapbysicaJly conceived notions of
arising (utp1ida) and
along with ie all other related concepts such as "the
present arising'' (ut·
padyamiina) and "non-arising'' (an11tpada) , comparing
all of them to the nocions of "the moved" (gata), "the not
moved" (aga/a), and "the presenc moving" (gamyamiina)(Vll.14)
which he had previously criticized. Nagarjuna42 TuE PHILOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE W
AY
mak.es a vety significant statement at Vll.16:
"Whatever that comes to be
dependently, that is inherently peaceful. Thecefore, chat
which is presently
arising as wełł as arising itself arc peaceful."
In the fiest place, hece thece is no denia1 of arising
(utp'iida) or that which
is presently arising (utpadyamtina). By implication, there
is no denial of cessatioo (vyaya) either. Sccondly, there is no denia1 of
"dependent arising''
(prafiyasam'utpada) or that which is dependently arisen
(prafftya yad yad
bhavalt). On the contcary, there is a very significant
assertion: "Whatever is
dependently ariseo is inherently peaceful." Explaining
the "elements" (dhatu)
in a previous chaptet (V), Nagarjuna has shown how the
belief in ett:cnal existence (astitva, bh'iiva) and nihilistic non-cxistence
(n'iistitva, abhava) lead to
the unfortunate consequences such as grasping (upadiina)
and, thecefore, suffering (dul/kha). The avoidance of such pcrspectives and the
adoption of the
view that things arise and pass away dependently (prafftya)
were considered by
the Buddha and the early Buddhists as well as Nagarjuna as
being "łnherently
peaceful" (s·vabha11atal/ śiinla'f!").
The significaoce ofthe use ofthe term sflabliiifla in the
above context should
not go unnoticed. The term wabha11a as weU as its adverbia!
use, s11abhato asti,
especially when qualifying existence, was condemned by
Nagarjuna
throughout the work. However, in the present verse he was
willing to use this
very same term in an adjectival sense, qualifying śanta
(peaceful).
The concepts of "the conditioned" and "the
unconditioned'', perceived in
terms of substancial cxistcnce, arc rejected herc, and the
notions of arising,
ducacion, and ceasing, similacly conceived, arc also
abaodoned as beiog illusory.
8. Action and agent (karma-k11mka). While "depenaently
arisen (pratTtytJJamutpanna) phenomcna imply a process of natura1 occurence
"uncondfrioned by dispositiooaJ teodencies1' (tJJaf!Jskrta) on the part of
human
beings, "dispositiooally conditioned"
(s(J1(Zskrta) pbenomena are the .results of
human deliberations (saf!Zskiira) or accions (karma). For
this reason, after clari:-
fying the notions 9fthe "conditioned" and the
"unconditioned," it was natu.tal
for Nagarjuna to take a look at the notions of action
(karma) and agent
(k"iirt1ka). If these two wete found to be real in a
substantialist sense, theo the
lengthy analysis of "conditioned" phenomeoa in the
previous t.hapter would
appear faulty. .
Therefore, Nagarjuna begins with a substa.ncial agent (sadbhuta
kiiraka) who
performs a substantia11y existing action (sadbhuta karma)
and his analysis
demonstrates chat such an agent as well as such an action,
in face, logicailylead
to a denial of action (kriy'ii), agent (kartr) as well as a
cause (kiiraf/a).lNTRODUCflON 43
Verse Vlll.5 represents an u nequivocal assertion on the
part of Na.garjuoa
rhat such a substantialist view not only leads to the denial
of action, etc., but
also co an.abandoning of discrimlnations and distinctions
such as good (dht1rma) and bad (adha-rma) that are so relevant to the Buddha's
conception offruits
(phala) of life, both worldly ( = heavenly, svarga) and
ultimate ( = freedom
from suffering, mok[a). Not only the goał or fruit of life,
butaJso the pach that
leads thereto or all the accions that produce such fruits,
would thereby be
rendered useless or meaningless (nairarJhakyaf!J). -. · ·
The statement at Vlll.12 that both action and agent arc
dependentły
(pralitya) acisen and that there is oo other perceivable
mannec in which these
could be' estabłished (nanyat paśjiimaf? siddhikaraf!af!J)
stands as an eloquent
testimony to Nagatjuna's vindication of the empirical
standp.oint of the Buddha and of earły Buddhism.
'
9. Antecedent stale (of the self) (purva). If there were to
be no subscantial ac:
cioo and agent, exc:ept the empirically gjven action and
agent which are the
results of dependence, ho\V is it that metaphysiciańs carne
to assume the existence of such an eteroal self or persooality?
Io Chapter IX, Nagarjuoa uodertakes to show how the beliefin
a pecmanent
and eternal entity arises as a result of the recognition of
the exiscence of a person.ality prior (purva) to his experieoces such as
seeing, heariog, and feelings
(IX.1). In other words, the Buddhist metaphysicians, foUowiog
a method
similar to tbat adopted by Descartes in Western phiJosophy,
were positjng a
substantiaJ eatity and theu p.rocecding to attriburc the
funccions ofseeing and
hearing to tbat entity. It is hard to believe that a
philosopher like Nagarjuna
was unaware that the Buddha's notion of non-substaotiality
(anat1114n) was the
direct result of his rejeccion of such a perspective, vety
clearly expressed by the
Buddha in a passage in the Sutta-nipata: "Let bim'
destroy the eocire root of
obsession, [oamely, the belief) 'I think, [therefore] I
am," (mantii asm"itz). 80
This indeed is an unequivocaJ rejectioo of the ucogito ergo
sum" (1114ntfi
asmz) wbich contrihuted to the substantialist thought of the
Upani/ads as well
as later Indian thought. Nagarjuna's arguments shows how
self-destructive
such an assertioo is. The implication ofthis assertion, as
Nagarjuna perceives, is
that such a personality has to be separated from the
experieoces that emerge
subsequently. Nagarjuoa wants to know how sucha personałity
could be made
known (parjfJapyate) independent of such experiences (IX.3)
thus implying
that the sum (aham a.rmz) is tlependenc. If rhese
experiences can be separated
from the personałity, it follows that they could occur eveo
witbout sucha persooałity (IX,4).
Having explained cettain ocher implications of this
metaphysical position, aJJ
of which he considers to be uosatisfactory, Nagarjuna
maiotains tbac with44 THE PHILOSÓPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
regard to such a personality the concepts of existence and
non-existence are not
validly applicable.
10. Fire andfuel (agritndhana). The futility of employing
the example of the
fire (agnt) and fueł (indhana) in order to ilłustrate the
relationship between a
substantial action and a substantial agent is shown in
Chapter X. It is indeed
the. most important metaphor used by the substantialists to
establish the conception of a metaphysical person. The manner in which che
Pudgalavadias
utilized this metaphor is explained .in detail by Vasubandhu
in the final
chap ter ofhis Abhidharmakośa-bh'?i!Ja (see annotation on
Chapter X). Finally
he refuses to recognize those who admit the reality of a
self(atman, pudgala) as
weU as those who uphold discrete substaorial entities
(bhava), as people who
are conversant with the true meaning of the Buddha's
teachings (X.16). It is
elear that the reference herc is not to the non-Buddhist
metaphysicians, but
rather to the Buddhist metaphysidans who claimed themselves
to be the tt:ue
interpreters of the Buddha-word, oamely the Sautrantikas (
=pudgąlavadins)
and the Sarvastivadins ( =svabhavavadins).
11. Prior andposterior ends (p'iirv'iiparako{t). The
refutation of the prior existence of a substantial being or entity would stili
leave open the question
regard.ing the beginning and end of things. Speculations
regarding the beginning (purva-koti) wd the finał end (apara-koµ) have occupied
the atteation of
phiJosophers from the dawn of bistory. These speculatioas
have given risc to a
wide variety of beliefs, one of which is the substantial
cxistence ofa being (such
as God) or an ultimate entity (such as pricnordial maner,
pr~rti, sometimes
referred to as svabhava).81 Realizing the epistemological
problems involved in
these speculations, the Buddha refraioed from mak.ing an.y
state01ents regard~
ing such issues.
Chapter XI ,is iątended to explain the Buddha's attitude
towards such ques·
tions.. Nagarjuna was aware that the Buddha refused to make
any statements
about the prior end of the life-process. Hence his
statement: "The Great Sage
has dedared that the prior end of the life-process is not
known" (XI. I).
However, the Sanskritization of the Prakrit cerm anamalagga
(= "inconceivable
is rhe beginnmg") as t1na11aiiigra ( = "wirhout
beginning and end") had already
appeared in the Buddhist texts that Nagarjuna was familiar
with.82 Taking this
lattet version of the Buddha's statemeot, Nagarjuna
maintains that there is
neither a beginning nor an end, whereas the Buddha's own
statement perta.ined to the epistemologica1 difficulties.
Yet, Nagarjuoa's ingeouity was such that he was able co
indicate the Jogical
difficu1ties involved in any denial of either the beginning
or the end. For he
finds that "no middle can be conceived of chat which is
without beginning orINnoouCTioN 45
end" (XI. 2). Because of such logical difficulties, he
maintains that prior and
posterior as well as sjmultaneous srates (ofSPf!l-s'iira)
arc not appropriate, These
logkal difficulties arise primarily becauc entities are
conceived of in. a rather
substantialist way. Thus, ifbirth were to be considered as
being prior to old age
Comments
Post a Comment
7000