Trung Luan(4)
"everything exists" (sarvam astt) in .the form of
substance (svabhava). Nagarjuna is simply allowing that metaphysicał qucstion
to be setded by the usc of
ihe fourfołd proposicions tbat negate cach other.
Indeed, this is not presented as the "teaching" or
"message'' (śiisana) of the
Buddba, as Inada seems to understand. Quite on the contraty,
it is an "admonition'' or "advice" (anufiina) in regard to the
manner in which spccułation
about "everything'' can be resolved, nameły, by
detnoristrating the inevitable
self-contcadictions. In other words, he is stadng that the
question regarding
"everything" cannot be settłed by aoy form of
4iscussion, a view clearly expressed by the Budcłha in his famous
"Discoutse on Everything;, (Sabba-sutt11, sec
commentary on IX.3), which Nagarjuna was probabły,
conversant with.
9. Apara.pratyay4'f!Z śanltJ'f!Z prapańcair aprapancita'f{I,
nirvika/pam an'iinartham etat tattvasya lakfatJa'f!Z.
lndependently realized, peaceful, un'obsessed by obsessions,
without
discriminations and a vańery of meanings: such is the
charactedstic of
truth.
MKV(P) p.372; MKV(V( p. 158.
This is one·ofthe most iJllportant statcments ofNagarjuna, quoted
often byhis
dassical as welł as modern interpreters. The most receot
translatioo and inter-ExAMINATION OF SELF 271
pretttion comes from !nada and, as such, it could be
consider~d a digcst of the
existing vicws. Hence, it is appropriate to quote Inada's
rendering of this verse
in full. lt reads as follows:
Non-conditionally rclated to any cntity, quiscent,
nonconceptuafucd by conceptual play, non-discriminative and nondiffercntiated.
Thcsc arc the charactcristics of reality (i.c., dcscriptive of one who has
gained the Buddhist truth) (p.115).
The term apara-pratyaya is herc taken to mean a special kind
of rclation that
trarucends any form of empirical conditionality. Śiinta
signifies "quicscence," a
quicscence resulting from the avoidance ofany cooceptuality,
probably the sort
of pcace and quiet experienced by one who has temporarily
stoppcd the func- .
cioning of the six sense facultics by reaching the state of
cessation (nirodhasamapatti, or sanńa-11edayita-nirodha). lt is where the
dicbotomy of subject
and object is compJetcly dissolved (nir-11ikalpa) and where
the variegated expedences of the world, the variety of meanings or fruits
(n'iinartha), is
climinated. Truth, in such a context, cannot be very
different from that of
either the Upanifads or the Vedanta. lt is the flushing out
of all conceprual
thinking (citta-vrtti-nirodha), thereby transforming the
empirical expecience
into one of absolute, ułtimate truth or reality.
However, a glance at the "Discourse to Katyayana,"
the primary source for
Nigarjuna's formulation of the "middle way," will
reveal the untenability of
such an explanation.
Even though the verse seems to desccibe the characteristics
of truth or reality
(tattvasya lalt1af!t1f!J), every preceding scatement points
to the means by which a
conccprioo of cruth is arrived at. Hence, it is one of the
most important
scarements on epistemology. The most salient fearures of
this epistemolgoy acc
already clearly embodied in the Buddha's discourse to
K.atyayana, presented in
the form ofan answer to the question 'as to what "right
view" (samma-dittht) is.
The concencs of the verse can be analysed in the light of
this discourse in the
following manner.
The term apara-pratyaya does not refer ro a uuth chat is
non-condicionally
rclated to any entity. Rather, it explaios the manner in
which koowledge
(n'ii11a) is attained by one who has „right view''
(samma-diftht). After rejectiog
the metaphysical views penaiolng to permanent existence
(atlhifii) as well as
the belief in a permanent and substantial personal entity
(alla .. . rne). a
belicf that will require the testimony ofsome ocher person
who cłaims to know
the absolute bcginning of things, the empiricist Buddha
daimed that
knowledge (of one who has right view) ~curs withouc having
to dcpend upon
anorher person (aparf!-·Pa&cay'ii flaf!am evassa ettha
holi, S 2. 17). Ir is272 THE PHtlOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
knowledge for which one does not have to depend upon
another, primarily
because it pertains to arising and ceasing of empi.deal
phenomena. It involves
personal vcrification. a verlfication that can be
accomplished by someooe
before one l:iegins to formulate any right view.
Man's search for a permanent entity, white he is equipped
with limited
epistemological resources, leaves him with unresolved questions.
He continues
co doubt. H·e is constantly perplexed and croubled. Looking
for permanence,
he misses the empirically given. The ,search for the unseen
"beauty queen"
(janapada-kaljiinT, D 1.193; M 2.40) makes him forget the
immediatley relevaot questions (M 2.40). As such, he has no peace of mind.
How.everI ifhe were
to direct his attention to what is immediately given, .and
understand the
human predicament in its context without being ioquisitive
abouc
metaphysical entities (dukkham eva uppa1/amana'f!t uppa1jati
dukkha??i niru/
jhamana?!J nirujjhatiti na kańkhati 114 vicikicchatt;
ibid.), his mind would be
peaceful (Siinta_'f!l). The Buddha, in one of his very
famous scatements, insisted
that when a reflecting person understands the arising and
ceasing of
phenomena, all his doubts disappear (Ud 1). Such peace of
mind is achieved,
not by ignoring what is relevaot in the human cootext, bur
by igooring the irrelevant and irresolvable metaphysical issues.
Such a state of peace (flintt) cannot be achieved so long as
one is bound by
·one's prejudices (11piiyup'iidiinabhinivesa-vinibandho,
ibid.,) This is the
"obsession'' (prapańca) chat Nagarjuna is referring to
in the present cootext.
The discourse to Kat.yayana has no reference to any
conceptuał proliferation.
How such obsession~ have further stre.ngthened and
encouraged the search
for ułtimate truths, contriburing to indiscriminate
discrimioations,- soch as
those of existence and non-existence - (bh'iiva-ab.h.ava) .
or self--narure and other-
'narure (s11abhava-p11rabha11a), has akeady been explained
by Nagarjuna. These
are the disctiminations that are to be avoided in the search
for truth. Nirvikalpa.refers to the absence ofsuch discrimioations.
A pluralistic view of the world is not incompatible with
dependent arising
(pralityasamulpada). Pluralism in the context of dependent
arising doespot
imply the existence ofself-contradictory truths. It oeed not
necessarily lead' to a
oorion of an Absolute that transcends such
self-contradictory truths. The
critedon for deciding what is true io the cotllext of
dependent arisiog is consequence or fruit (artha). When the Buddha maintained
that "truth is one; chere
is no second" (eka'f!t hi sacca'f!t na dulijam aflhi,
Sn 88'1), he was certaioły
referring to this pragmatic criterion of truth based upon
the notion of dependent arising, not an absolute truth that uaoscends all forms
of duality and
plurality. Nagarjuna's characterization of truth as
"not having a v.ariety of
meanings" (ańiinariha'l(Z) reflects more the Buddha's owo
concepcion of truth.
To summarize, the conception of truth and the
epistemołogical means on
the basis of which it is formulated all point to the face
that the truth under con-EXAMINATION OF SEl..F 273
sideration is the "dependendy arisen"
(prafityasamutpanna). The principle of
dependent arising (pratfty4Samutptida) is merely the
expression of the manner
in which "dependently arisen" phenomena are
explained . They are rwo sides of
the same coin. ·
Yet, as reiterated befote. the greatest misunderstandings
created by the
metap'hysicians were in regard to "dependently ariseo
phenomena"
(prafityast1mutpanna-dharma). Therefore, after examining the
epistemoJogical
means by which the conception of truth "as dependently
arisen" is arrived at,
Nagarjuna, in the verse thac folJows immediately„ takes up
the metaphysical
ioterpretations of the concept of dependence.
10. Parfitya yad yad bhavati na hi t?ivat lad eva tat1
na canyad api tat tasmtin nocchinnaf!t niipi śaśala'f!J-.
Whatever that arises depencling upon whatever, that is not
identical nor
clifferent from it. Therefore, it is neither annihilated nor
eternal.
MKV(P) p. 375; MKV(V) p.150.
Whatever is arisen dependent upon (pratftya) another, that
is, the dependencly
arisen (prafityasamutpanna). is not appropriately expJained
in terms of identity
or difference. As empahsi.zed so often by Niigarjuna,
absoJute identity involves
permane.nce and absolute difference implies annihilation.
Dependent arising is
the middle way adopted by the Buddha in eluc'idating change
and causation.
11. Anekdrtharr1- ananartham anucchedam aśaśvata'f!J-,
etat tal lokanathanii'f!t buddhaniif(J fiisanamrta~.
That is without a variety of mean.ings or one single
rneaning, it is not annih.ihlcion nor i~ it eternal. Such, it is reminisced, is
the immottal message
of the Buddhas, the patrons of the world.
MKV(P) p.377: MKV(V) p.160.274 THE PHILoSOPHY OFTIIE MrooLE
WAY
The metaphysics of identity or ofdifference, of one or
ofmany. of permanence
or of annihilation, n1ay be provcd or not provcd. So far the
cvidcnce has not
becn found thac would providc justifu::ation for any such
notions. The only
known cvidcncc poioes co che f~cc that things arc changing
and arc depcodently
arisen. Such change and dependent arising do not fali wichin
the duality ofone
or many. of anni.hjlation or permaneoce. Dependent arising
is what has bcen
koown so far. Unlcss a raclical change occurs in the
conscicution of things, this
dependent arising will continue co be. Such is che immorcal
ceaching of the
Buddha.
This, agUn, is Nagarjuna's rcflection on the cpiscemology
ofdependent arisiog . .
12. Sambuddhan'iimanulpiide śiiivalii/niif!l punaf? kfaye,
jfłiinaf!l prateyka-buddh'iin'iim asaf!Ut1rg'iil ptavartale.
Whcn the fully enlightencd oncs do not appcar; on the warung
of
disciplcs; the wisdom of the sełf-cnligbtcncd ones procccds
without
association.
MKV(P) p.378; MKV(V) p.161
The Buddha's ceachings were perpccuated by a long line of
disciples (śravaka).
lf that lineage were to be interrupted, stili ie is possible
for his teachings to
reappear. Nagarjuna was probabły aware of the metaphor of
che "ancient city"
(nagar11) whose discovery is compared to the discovery of
"dependent arising"
by the histori~ Buddha himself (S 2.104-107; Tsa 12.5
[T11irho 2.80b]).
Therefore, concradicting many a cradition chac depended
heavily on an uobroken concinuity as the primary source of the knowledge of che
Buddha's
ceaching, Nagatjuna is herc maińtaining thac such widsom
(iflana) can occur
cvcn without any concact or association (a.saf!J.sargal)
chrough the selfcnłighccned ones (pratyeka-buddha).CHAP'fER
NINETEEN
Examination of Time
(Kala-parTk!a)
1. Pratyutpanno 'niigataś ca yady afilam apek,ya hi,
prtJtyutpanno 'n1igalaf ca kale 'lite bh1J11qy1Jti.
Ifthe present and the future exist contingent upon the past,
,then the pre~
sent and the future would be in the past time.
2. Pratyutpanno
'niigalaś ca na stas t(Jlrapunar yadi,
pratyutpanno
'niigataś ca sy'iitiim, kathaf!J 11pek,ya tam,.
Again, if the present and the future were not to exist therein
[i.e., in.the
past], how could the present an,d the future be contingent
upon that?
MKV(P) pp.382-383; MKV(V) p. 163.
As mencioned at XVII.14, the conception of time was an
imponant factor in
the explanation of the fruits of action (kllrma-phala). All actions
do not bear
fruit immediately. Indeed, the problems were magnified by
the Buddha's
·recognition of.the possibility of the survival of the human
pcrso.nality through
countlcss łives. The Abhidharn1a łists four categories of
karma in terms of their
fruitioning, ałJ of which can be trac;ed back to the
discourses th~mselves. The
four categorics arc as fołlows: (i). kąrma ·that fruitions
immediately~or in the present life (dit1ha-dhamma-11ed4nzya); (ii) kuma that
fruitions in the next life
(upapa;ja-11ed4nlya); (iii) karma·that fruitions in some
after life (apartipariy11-
vedanlya); and (iv) karma that·produces no fruitioning
(ahosi-kamma)(Vism
p.601). Tbe use of the metapbor of "the imperishable
promi$.$Oty norc'' by
Nagarjuna was necessitated by the fact chat some karmas
ptoduce consequeoces
on a subsequent occasion. .
Thus, the conception of time becomes invariably bound up
with the notion
of karma. As such, whatever metaphysicaJ speculations that
emerged with the
27.~276 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
doctrine of karma, such as those mentioned at XVII. 7·10,
also carne to be
assodated with the concepcion of time. Analysing time as a
separate enticy, the
metaphysicians assumed that if there were to be any mutuaJ
relaciooship between the present and the future on the one band and the past on
the other,
then, since they are distinct entities, the present and the
future wiU have to be
inherent in the past. In ocher words, the past produces the
present and future
from within itself. This is the identity version ofcausation
(s11atotpattz). A fur.
cher implication of chis is th~t if one knows the past, one
also knows with ab·
soluce cenaincy what the present and the future would be.
These, indeed,
reprcsent some of the basie speculations of the
Sarvastivadins.
3. Anapek,ya
punal/ siddhir 11afi1a'!l vidyale tayol},
pr11tyutpa11110
'11aga1af ca lasmiit kalo na vidyate.
Moreover, non-contingent upon the past, their [i.e. of the
present and
future] establishment is not evident. Therefore, neither a
present nor a
future time is evident.
MKV(P) p. 383; M.KV(V) p.163.
The present verse embodies Nagarjuna's criticism of the
ootion of cime referred
to in XIX.1·2. Taken away from tharcootext, this will appear
co be a compJete
rejection of the very notion of rimc. However, Nagarjuna's
cdticism pertains
only to the cootingencc (apek{a) uoderstood in the light of
a theoty of inherence. On a previous occasion (X .-8-12), Nagarjuna has
convincingly
demonstratcd the difficulties involved in explainiog
conti~gence or reJativity in
the context of theories of ideotity (which is also implied
in inherence) and dif.
ference.
Nagarjuna's argument seems to.rcad as follows:
1. Majorpremiss:
The present and the future arc not scen to be cstablished
non·
contingent upon the past.
2. Middle term:
Contingeoce of the present and the future on the past
impLies
the substan tial existeoce of the present and the future in
the
past, which is not evident.EXAMINATION OP TTME
3. Conclu1ion:
Therefore, the present and the future, as substantiaJ entities,
do not exist.
277
Ignoring the middle term, so clearły _defined at XIX.1-2,
Nigarjuna's condusion will appear to be an absolute rejection of time. lt wouJd
then read as
follows:
I . Pint premisJ:
The present and the future are not contingeot upon the past.
2. Secondpremiu:
The present and the future arc not non-contingent upon the
past.
3. Minor premi.u:
The present and the future cannot be both contingent and
non-cootingent upon the past.
4. Conclusion:
The present and the future do not exist.
4. Etenaiv'iiva.ri/(tlu dvau krame'!a panvartakau,
uttamadhama-madhjiitlin ekatv'ii'rlif!t1 ca lak/ayet.
Following the same method, che remaining two pcriods of
[time] as well
as related concepts such as the highest, the lowest and the
middJe, and
also identity, etc. should be characteńzed.
MKV(P) p.384; MKV(V) p . 164-.
Nigujuna is insistiog that the same argument be applied to
the concept of the
present in relation to the past and future, and to the
future in relatioo to the
past and present. In addition, he maintains that this
analysis can be extended
to similar concepts like the highest, the łowest, the
middle, etc. In all chese
cases, the metaphysicaJ issues emerge as a result of the
abso/ute distinctions that
are being made. Such absolutc distinccions arc being ofren
made in logical
analyses, and are oot supporced by empirical evidence. Time,
aJ experienced ,
cannot be analysed into three water-tight 'Compartmeots as
past, present, and278 THE,PHILOSOPHY OP TiłE MIDDLE WAY
'
future. (See Introduction, for an explanation of the
experienced time by a
modern psychologist.)
5. Niistito grhyate kii/al? sthitaf? kilo na 11idyale,
yo grhyetagrl:iitaf ca kii/4'7 prajnapyate kathaf!J.
A non-static time is ,iot observed. A static time is not
evident. Even ifthe
unobserved time were to be obse.rved, how can it be made
knówn?
MKV(Pj p.385; MKV(V) p.165.
A non-static time is a tempoial flux. It is what the
ioterpreters of the
Abhidharma referred to as the "flowing present"
(santatipaccuppańna, DhsA
421), where the future cootinues to flow into the past
througb the present. Any
attempt to grasp it would be futile, for by the time the
attemp~ is.made the
present has disappeared into the past. In order to grast>
it one has to stop the
flow. Hence the metaphysicians recógriized a static moment
(sthitt~k/a'!a) .
Nagarjuna has already analysed the .implications of such
t.heories in Chapter
VII. Thus, time understood in terms of distinct momentary
entities could not
account for experience. This metaphysical theory viewed the
present as the
momentary present (k.haf!a-paccuppanna, loc,cit.). Even if
the non-graspable
time were to be grasped, Nag~rjuna's question is: "How
can it be made
known?'' The; empiricist is. therefore, lcft with a specious
time (prob;ibly an
addha-paccuppanna). lt is specious because, when aoy
attemptis made to
gra.sp it independent of temporal events, it vanishes like a
mirage. ft cannot be
made knowa. by any means. Absolute time mak:es oo sense for
Nagarjuna.
6. Bhavaf!' prafity{I k.alai cet kalo bha.11ad rte kuta//, .
na ca k.aicana bhava 'sti kuta/? kalo bhavt!yati.
lf it is assumed that time exists depencling upon an
existent, how can
therc be time without an existcnt? No existent whatsoev.er
is found to exist. Whcf<' can tim.e be?
MKV(P) p.387; MKV(V) pp.165-16~ ,IExAMINATION OP 'nM1! 279
An cxistent (bhi11a), since it represcnts a metaphysical
encity baving its own
nature (s11abhiva), has already becn rejected by Nigarjuna.
Time (u/a) denied
by bim is an absolute time. lt Is time that is real as momenta.cy
entities (k/a'!a)
·or something that is flccting (ianta11) on its own. In the
present verse, Nigiirjuna is maintainiog that two independent encicies- an
cxistcnt (bhii11a) and
time (u/a)-cannot be dependent upon one another. If they are
dependent
upon one another (bhi11tlf'!l pralitya ulaś &et), then
there cannot be time independent -of an existent. An existent as such is
non-exisrcnt. Whence can
there be time? This is a rejection not oftempora! phenomena,
but onJy of time
andphenomenaas well as their mutuał dependence so long as
they arc perceived as independent entities.CHAPTER
TWEN1Y
Examination of Harmony
(Samagn-parz k!a)
1. Hetof ca pratyay'finiir.n ca ilimag1yii;ayate yadi,
phalam asti ca samagryaf!l iiimagrjii1ayate kathaf!'.
lf the cffect were to arise Crom a harmony ofcause and
conditions, and if
it wcre to exist in the ruumony, how can it atisc from the
hacmony?
2. Hetof ca pratyayanaf!J ca samagrfii jiiyate yadi,
phalaf!' nasti ca iiimgryaf!' J1imagryii jiiyate kathaf!l.
Ifthe effect were to arise fcom a harmony ofcause and
conditions andifir
wcre not to exist in the harmony, how can it arisc from the
harmony?
MKV(P) p.391; MKV(v,J p.168.
The term uscd in the carly discourscs for "assemblage''
is sangali (M
1.111-112). For example, the eye, the visible form, and
visual consciousncss arc
said to co~e together (sangatt) in contact (ph(Msa). Herc,
the eye, visible form,
and visual coosciousness arc compatiblc factors, and not
incompatiblc.
However, as evcnts carne to be distioguishcd in the
Abhidharma, the intccprctcrs of the Abhidharma had to be concerned moce with
"harmony''
(iiimagii) chan with simple "assemblage" (1ańgatt)
. The concep tion of "harmony" thus carne to atuact Nigacjuna's
attention, even though he will return
to the notioo of "assemblage;. later on in tbis
chapter.
Nigarjuna's anerhpt at the beginoing of this chapter is to
examinc the con·
ccption of harmony and to pccvent any metaphysical
interpretation of it.
Metaphysical speculacions wece further advanced by the
S:uvastivada distinction berween cause (helu) and coodicioo (pralyaya). This
lattec discinction,
supponed by the Sarvastivada conception of self-nacure
(s11abha11a),
culminated in the idea of self-causacioo (111ata u1pattt).
280EXAMINATION OF H A.RMONY 281
For this reason, in the very first verse, Nagarjuna takes up
three ideas: (i) harmony, (ii) distinction betweeo cause and condicions, and
(iii) the arising of an
eff.ectfrom a harmony of cause and cooditions. (Note
Nagarjuna's use ofhelu
in the singular and pralyaya in the plural.)
Nagarjuna's critidsm is mainly directed at the idea of
self-causation. If the
fruit arises from the harmony (siimagrya, abJacive case) of
a cause and a set of
cooditions (helo!/ pratyayanaf!Z ca), then it is already
existent in che ham1ony
(samagry'iif!Z, locacive case). H ow then can it arise from
the harmony
(1amagrya)? The causal process presenced in this manner
implies che idencicy
between "harmooy of cause and conditions" and the
fruit or eff.ect that arises
from it. The ideotity theory of causatioo was already
criticized in Chapter I.
Similarly, as stated atXX.2, if the fruit or effect atising
ftom such a harmony
were not to be in the harmony, chat is, if the cffect is
different from the harmony, it can never arise from that harmony. This is a
criticism of the nonidentity theory of causacion discussed in Chapter I. These
two vecses, therefore,
state the difficulties involved in accepting theories of
identicy and difference.
3. Hetoś ca pratyayanaf!Z ca Iamagryam asati cel pha/af!Z,
grhyeta nanu iiimagryaf!Z iiimagryiif'(Z ca na grhyate.
Ifit is assumed chat the effect exists in the harmony of
cause and conditions, should it not be observed i.n the hatmony? Howcver, it is
not
observcd in the haunony.
4. Helol ca pralyay'iin'iif!Z ca Iamagry'iif'(Z n'ii1ti cet
phala1!1-
hetavaf? pratyayaś ca Jyur ahetu-pratyayaif? ItJ'fn'iil/.
If the cffect were not to exist in the harmony of cause and
conditions,
thcn the cause and conditions would be comparable co
non-cause and
non-conditions. '
MKV(P)
pp.392·393; MKV(V) p.169. ·
lf the identity theory is valid, rhen the fruit could be
observed (grhyela) in the
harmony itself, eveo before it is produced through such
harmony. However,
Nagarjuna assumes chat ie is not observed or grasped .in
this manner. Once284 THE PHILOSQPHY OF TI-lB MJDOLE W AY
become the transformation of the cause, then itfollows that
tbere is a rebirth of a cuase that was already bom.
MKV(P) p.396; MKV(V) p.17L
Among the variety of causes that were formulated to account
for a continuous effect (nif:;anda-pha/a) are complementary (sabhaga) ·and
universal
(sarvatraga) causes (Akb p .94). Explaincd in the light of
the theory of
moments, a universal cause would mean the contiouous acising
of the same
cause in order to account for the cootinuous effect. The
continuous effect
(ni.fyan4a-phala) thus turns out to be a cransformacioo
(sarp,krama11a) of che
cause (helu). Nagarjuna refuse:i to recognize the rebirch of
the same cause that
has ceased.
10. ]anqyet phalam utpanna?(l. niruddho 'sthaf!'gatal/
katharp,,
tz!thann api katha~ hetuf? phalena janayed vrtal/.
How can a cause that has ceased, has reached its end, give
rise to an effect
that is already arisen? How can a cause, even though
enduńng, produce
an effect, when it is sepatated from the latter?
M,KV(P) p.397; MKV(ll) p .171.
Throughout the present analysis we have indicaced that the
philosophical
rnethod adopted in the Abhidharma did not create any
metaphysical problems
until the interpreters adopted a theory of moments that were
foilowed by
theories of identity and difference. The vadety of causes
(hetu) and conditions
(pratyaya) , even though not presented in such detail and in
identicaJ terminology in the discourses, is not incompatible with the teachings
embodied
therein. However, even a cwsory glance at the manner in
which the interpreters of the Abhidharma struggled with these different causes
and conditions
. {see AK cbapter ii; Akb pp.38-tlO) is sufficient to
indicate the magnitude of
tne probtems they were faced with.
Nagatjuna concinues his analysis showing how a cause that
has ceased (nirurldha) or one that remains (tt!fhan), yet is distinct from the
effect (phalena
vrtaf?), could never give rise to an effect.EXAMlNĄTION OF
HARMONY
11 . Atliii11rta'1 phalenasau katarm1jjanayedphala'f!J,
na hy adurva 11a dr!f11a 11a hetur janayaJe phalart1.
What causc, evenif it wcre not separated from the effect,
will give rise to
the effect? A cause does not produce an effect eitber
impercepcibly or
pccccpribly.
M.KV(P) pp.398-399; MKV(V) p.1 72.
285
When the analytical process was carried to its extreme, many
evenrs, whicb
under norma! cootexts would not have been quescioned , c:une
to be doubced.
For example, inscead of a reJaced event, analysis produced
two: a relarion and
an event. Wheo the norma! empiricist criceria wece adopted
in the Jatter case,
one was compelled to assume chat the relation is not
perccived in che same way
as the evenr is perceived. The metaphysician was thus
compeUed to insist upon
the subscantial existence of the relatioo. "Birth is
the arising of whac is to ~e
born and this does not take place wichout causes and
conditioos," so says the
Abhidharmakofa (janyaJya Janik.ii 1atir na hetu-pratyayair
vina, ii.49). The
bhii1ya on this passage concinues to argue about che narure
of this "birth"
(jatt), insisring that the genetive case (!a/{ht) (as io che
sracement, "arising of
what is to be boro") makes no sense if birtb (jiitz) is
not perceived in the same
way as "that which is to be boro'' (Janiki.i) is
perceptible. The Sautrantika
Vasubandhu argues against this position saying chat
"óumbers, Hmits, distinction, union, analysis, ochcrness, sameoess"
are recognized as reals (salwa) in
the speculatioos of the herctics (llrthakara), and chat
these arc oecded only to
establish the knowłedge(but/dht) of the reality of"the
one, the dual, the great.
·the individuated, the uniced, the separated, the other, the
same, etc." To illustrate his point of view. he refers to the example of
"the union of fo1m"
(iiipaJya sa<f!Jyoga) and maincains that the generive
ca~e indicates the ownnature (svabhava) of"form." However, in his owo
Sautrantika view ie is a merc
designacion (pr(ljflaph~matram, Akb p .79).
Ie is this conttoversy 'rega.rding the reality or urueality
of numbers, conjunctions, disjuoctioos, etc. (a concroversy thac has contioucd
to plague
philosophers in the modern world) that Nigarjuna is
referring to in the present
verse when he uses the terms rlr!fva (seen) and adr11va
(unseeo).
12. Niifftmya hy affJena phalasya saha he111na,
naj'iitena na jiitena sa1!Jgatir1atu vidyate.,286 THE
PHILOSOPl-tY OF11l1l MIDDLE W AY
Incłeed, the assemblage of a past effect with a past or a
future or a present
cause is not evident.
13. Na jatasya hy a1atena phalasya saha hetun1i,
1iiifftena na1atena saf?Zgatirjiitu 11idyate.
Indeed, an assemblage of the present effect with a furure or
a past or a
present cause is not evident.
14. Niijiitasya hij'ątena phalasya J(lha hetuna,
niijiitena na n(#fena Sll'f'!Jgatirfiitu 11idyate.
Indeed, as assemblage of the future effect :with a present
or a future ot a
past cause is not evident.
MKV(P) pp.400-401 ; MKV(V) pp.172-1 73 .
After analysing the conceptioo of "harmony"
(i1imagfi), Nagatjuna now retums
to "the eadier notion of "assemblage"
(saf?Zgatt)(see commcnts ón X:X.1). The
notion of assemblage may not have caused philosophicaJ
problems for the early
Buddhists who adópted an empiricist theory of change and
causation . But, for
Nagarjuna, the coaceptioa of assemblage, like the aotion of
harmony , does
not work, so long as it is associated wich the metaphysical
conception of time.
Vasubandhu , as a Sautrantika, himself raises the more
radicaJ questlon as to
how the mind (1!l4nas) chat has alreądy ceased cąn assemble
with future and
present concepts (dhaffl!a) and mental consciousness
(mano-11ijf1ana) in order
to produce contact (Akb p. 143, manindriyasya punar
niruddhasy'iinagalavarta1nanabhjii??Z dharma-rnanovijń1in1ibhy1i'f'!J
katha1'?1- sa'f'!Jnipataf?). He then
refe,rs to a variety of insights (bhedar!f. gata buddhayaf?)
of different teachers,
and the controversy appears to be too complicated. He
dismisses them saying:
"Enough of this argument" (ala1'?1- prasangena).
Nagarjuna's reluctance to accept any one of these views is, therefore, the
result ofhis realizatioo that they
are all metaphysical views not allowing for any definite
answers or solutions.
15. Asatjii'f?Z sa'f'!Jgatau hetuf? kathaf!J janayate
phala?'(l,
saly41'?1- saf?Zgatau hetuf? katha'f'!J janayate p
hala'f'!J.EXAMINATION OF H ARMONY
When an assemblage does not exist, how can a cause produce
an effect?
When an assemblage exists, how can a cause produce an
effect?
MKV(P) pp.401-402 ; MKV(V)p .173
287
Here the causc (hel'll) is defined in terms of assemblage
(Jaf?/,gatt) which is
either existent (Jat) or non-existcnt (a.rat). A cause
defined in such a way turns
out to be substantialist or non-subsranrialisc. The former
implies permanence
and the lattcr, annihilacion. Nagarjuna rejects boch.
16. Hel'llf? phalena fUnyai cet kathaf?Z janayate phaiaf?Z,
hetul?
phalenafunyai cet kathar?t janayate phalar?t.
lf it is assumed that the cause is empty ofan effect, how
ran ie produce an
effect? If it is assumed thac the cause is not empty ofan
effect, how can ie
produce an effect?
MKV(P) p.402; MKV(V) p.173.
Turning atound, Nagarjuna now takes up che concepcion of the
effecc or fruit
(phala). If che cause is empty (Junya) of che effecc, it can
never produce an effect. Neither is it appropriate co assume that the effect is
produced by the cause
if it is already in the causę, hence nor empty (afunyar?t)
of the effecr.
17. Phalar?t
notpatsyate 'Junya1n aśUnyar?t na nirotJyate,
aniruddha,n
anutpannam aśUnyarrt tad bhavzjyati.
A non-empry effen will not arise; a non-empcy effect will
not ce-.tSe. For,
the non-ceased and non-ariseh will also be the non-en1pty.
MKV(P) p.402: 1HKV(V) p. 17-i.
This verse should clarify the meaning of the famous terms
atnruddharri ("nonceased") and anutpanna1?1 ("non-ariscn")
morc rhan any ocher scatement of288 THE Pl-OLOSOPHY OF TI-IE MIDDLE wAy
Nagarjuna. Whatever phenomenon (dharma) is characterized by
Nagarjuoa as
"empcy" (śunya) is without self-nature. 1f
something possesses a self-nature,
chen it is not empty (aśunya). As such, it can neither cease
nor arise (anirodham
anutpadaf!t), Thus, an effect or fruir that is not empty and
therefore is possessed of self-nature will nor arise (notpatsyate) nor cease
(na flirotsyate) ,
18. Katham utptTtsyate śunyarrz katharri śUnJll'f!Z
nirotJyate,
funyam apy aniruddharp. tad anutpannarp prt1Sajyate.
How will the empty atise and bow will the empty cease?
lfsomething is
empty, it follows that it is non-ceased and non-atisen.
MKV(P) p.403; MKV(V) p .174.
Taken by itself, this verse can be used to justify the view
that accotding to
Nagarjuna "emptiness" (sunyaf(i) is the ułtimate
truth beyond all forms of
description. Hence the negative d~scription:
"non-ceased'' (ant'rttddha'f!Z) and
"non-arisen" (anutpanna'f!Z).
However, considered along with XX.17, whkh rcjects the
notioo of identity
presented by the Sarvastivadins as self-nature (.rvabhava).
which according to
Nagarjuna is "oon-empty'' (afunya), what is referred co
as "empry" (śUnya) in
the pi:eseot verse is mo,re apptopriately understood as a
reference to the nonidentity theory of the Saucrantikas. It may be remembered
that the first Buddbist school to deny the Sarvastivada ·theo.ty of self-nature
was the Sautrantika
school. How che Sautrantika theory of "emptiness'' or
''absence of substaoce"
(nil/-svabhava) and their theoty of "momeotary
destruction" (kfaf!a-bhanga)
Jcd to a denial of both arising and ceasing has already been
pointed out (VIl.17
ff.).
As such, the present stacement of Nagarjuna, following upon
his refutation
of ideotity, must involve a rejection of difference. the rwo
extremes that he has
pe(Sistencly criticized. In other words, che Sarvastivada
and Sautrantika
theories both rendcc acising and ceasing mcaningless.
19. Hetol? phalasya caikatva'f!Z na hij111ii,papadyate1
hetol/ phalasya canyatvaflZ na hijat'Upapadyate,EXAMINATION
OP HARMONY
The identity ofcausc and effcct is indecd not appropriatc.
The difference
becwcen causc and cffect is indeed not appropriatc.
20. Ekat11e phala-hetvol/ sjiid aikyaf'!Z janaka-janyayof?,
Prthaktve phala-hel11ol; sjiit lu/yo hetur ahetuna.
ff thcre were to be identity of cause and cffcct, thcn thcre
would be
onencss of produccr and the producc. lf there werc to be
differcncc betwccn cause and effect, thcn the cause would be cqual to a
non-cause.
21. Phalaf'!Z svabhiiva-sadbhutaf'!Z kif!l hetur janayi/yati,
pha/af!l s11abhiivasadbhulaf'!Z kt?p hetur janayi,jali.
How is it chat a causc will producc an cffect which comes to
be on its own
naturc? How is it that a cause will produce an effect which
docs not come
to be on its own nature?
MKV(P) pp.403-404; MKV(J1 p.174.
289
The impłicacions of the theories of idcntiry and difference
discussed at
XX. 17-18 are further elaboraced in these t:htee verse.
22. Na cajanayamiinasya hetutvam upapadyate,
hetulvanupapattau ca phaktf'!Z kasya bhavi-ryatz:
Moreover, the causa! efficacy of something that is not
producing is not
appropriate. In the abscnce of causa! cfficacy, co what will
the cffcct
belong?
(MKV(P) p.405 ; MKV(V) p. 17).
Identiry and difference are thus shown co miłitate against
noc merely arising,290 THC: PHILOSOPHY OFTHE MIDDLE WAY
bu t also causal or dependent arising. Causa! efficacy
(hetut114f!J) is rendered
mcaningless if there were to be no production, chat is, if
the arising of an effect
cannot be accounted for by a cause, which is the result of
the Sarvastivada and
Sautrantika theories. If causaJ efficacy cannot be accounted
for. how can one
speak of an effect or fruit? ·
23. Na ca pratyaya-hetunam iyavz atmanam anatmanii,
ya samagfi
janayate sa kathaf!J janayet phala1!t.
Whatever harmony of causes and conditions there is, ie is
noc produced
by itself or by another. ff so, how can it produce an
effect?
MKV(P) p.406: MKV(V) p. 175.
After producing an exhauscive analysis of the relationship
between a cause
(helu) and fruit or effect (phala), Nagarjuna returns to the
question with
which he began che chapter, the harmony of causes and
condfrions. Once
again, rcfuting the identity and non-idencity theories, he
insists that whatcvcr
harmony there is, ft is not produced by the causes and
conditions cither from
within rhemselves (atmana = svabhavala) or from outside
(anatmana =
para1af?). Wben harmony cannot be explained in any ofthese
two ways, chen it
is not possible ro assume chat an effect can arise from a
harmooy so expJ.ained.
24. Nasamagfi-krta1!} phala'f!l nasamagii-krtaf!J phala'f!l,
a.rti pratyaya-samagfi kuta eva phalaf{Z vina.
The effect is not made by the harmony, nor is it not made by
a harmony.
Where iodeed can there be a harmony of condirions wichout an
effect.
MKV(P) pp.406-407; MKV(V) p.176.
The effect is not produced by a harmony of causes and
condicions explained in
the above mann er. Nor is ie produced by a non-harmony.
Nagarjuna's finaJEXAMINATION OF HARMONY 291
qucstion is: Where can chere be a harmony without a fruic or
effect? This fioal
conclusioo need not be understood as a deniaJ of fruit or
effect. On the contrary, ie can be the assertion of a pragmatist who insists
that chete canoot be a
harmony of causes and conditions without a fruir or
effecr.CHAPTER
TWENTYONE
Examination of Occurrence and Dissolution
(Sa'f(Jbhava-vibhava-partkffi)
1. Vina 1111 Jaha va 11asti vibhaval; J111?Zbhave11a
""'~
vina va Jaha va
nasti saf'!Zbhava/J vibh11ve1111 vai.
Dis.1olution docs not exi.st either without or with
occuuence. Occurrencc
does not exist either without or with dissolution.
2. Bh1111t!yati kathaf'!Z 11iima 11ibha11a'1 Jatr1bha11a1(l
flina,
vinaiva janma maraf!a'fl 11ibha110 nodbha11af!Z
11in"ii.
How can there be dissolution without occunence, death
without birth,
dissolution without uprising?
MKV(P) pp.410.411 ; M.KV(V) p.178. ·
The terms Sllf!lbhava and vibhava need to be cransJated
keeping in mind the
purpose of this secrion. lt is an attempt on the part of
Nagarjuna co cxplain the
life-proccss (saf!Mara) or the human pcrsonality without resorting
to a theory of
self or soul (iitman1 pudgala) cooside1ed to be eternal. As
mentioncd earlier,
this whole section is devoted to the cstablishing of the
idea of nonsubsrantiality of the human person (pudgala-nairatmya)..This has to
be achiev,
cd not onJy by showing the untenabilicy of the theory of
permancnce or eternalism , but also of a conccption of annibilationism.
Thus, in this particular chapcer satr1bhava, in the sense of
ocCUirence, pcrtains to the "birth" (janma) of a human being
conditioned by various factors,
without any underlying permanent entity passing from one
life to another.
Vibhava, in the sense of dissołution . mcaos "death''
(mara11a), and herc there'is
no implication of compłetc annihilation. In the
life-proccss, binb is thus not
the absolute beginning, nor is „death the absołute end.
292EXAMINATION OF 0 CCURR!lNCE AND D ISSOLl!TION' 293
The first two verscs deny the occurrence of death wichout
(t1inii) binh or at
the same time (saha).Just as much as death docs not occur
without birth, there
is no up-rising (udbhava) witbout dissolution (vibhtJva).
This is an empirical,
rather than a logical, analysis of birth and death. A
rationalist can argue that
"all human beings arc not monal,'' for everyone who has
becn born has not
died. Such a rational argument did not prcvent the Buddha
from acccpting
mortality as a fact of life. For him, the evidencc lies in
the fact that so fu all
human being who have died had been born. However, this does
not lead the
Buddha to assert the metaphysical view that death is
inherent ~ bitth.
3. Sam.bha11enai11a 11ibha11a'1 katha?(' saha bha11i1yati,
na janma-maraf!a?!J caiva?(' tulya-kiila??Z hi 11idyate.
How can there be dWolution ałong with occurrence? Indeed,
simultaneous binh and death arc similarly not evi.dent.
Jl;U(V{P) p.411 ;
JUJ(V(V) p.178.
This is an explicit rejection of che metaphysical view chat
death is inherent in
binh. lf the life-proccss (sa?('..riira) werc to be
understood as a seties of momentary existences (sa11Jtana, sa'f!'talt), as the Saucrantikas
believed, theo the sceds
ofdeath should occur at the very moment of birth. This
logical explanation was
not accep~able to che empiricist Nligarjuna.
4. Bhavqyali katha'f!' nama It1'f!'bha110 vibht1114f'!t
vina,
anityalii hi bhave!u na kadiitin na vidyate.
How can there be occurrence without dissolution, for the
impermanenre
in existences is never not cvident.
'MKV(P) p.412;_MKV(V) p.178
Occurrencc (sa'!Jbha1111), as an absolutely new beginning.
is rejccted herc, when
Nagarjuna affirms that without dissolution occurrence does
not cake place.294 THE PHrr.OSOPH\' OF THE MIDDLE WAY
lndeed, the discourse to Katyayana utilized the cmpirical
argument that the
belicf in a permaoent entity is abandoned wben one perceives
the cessation of
the world (loka-nirodhaf!J ... yathabhufaf?1- sammappanflaya
passato yiiloke
atthita sii na hotz). Nigarjuna's argument herc is not that
"there is another
realm or aspect of beingwhich peopłe havc always overloo~ed.
Thisis the realm
or aspect ofbhiiva, [which] refers to the truły dynamie
worldly existcnce" (as !nada seems to assumc, sec p.125). Rather, it is a
rejection of bhava, piimarily
because impermanence (anityatfi) is incompatible with bhava,
which impłies
permanence. In fact, Nigarjuna was probably aware that the Buddha
bad
always employed the term bhava to expłain the process
of"bccoming," instead
of the absuact term bhiva. Indeed bhiva, or its more
resuicted form svabhava,
is equivałent to astitva (attht'tii) and more often
Nagarjuna understood the
term in that sense.
5, Sa?'(Jbhavo vibhavenaiva kathaf!l saba bhavi/yflti,
na janma- marafłlZf!' ctiiva tulya-kalaf!l hi vidyate.
How can occurrence be evident ałong with dissolution?
Indeed,
simułtaneoos birth and death are similarly not evident.
At XXi.3, Nigarjuna ąuestioned the feasibility of asserting
that death occurs
together with (saha) birth. In the present verse, he is
questioning ' the validity of
asserting the occurrence of birth together with (s11ha)
death. In other wofds, he
is questioniog the feasibility of asserting an invariable
connection between
death and rebinh, an iovariable connectioo that is never
asserted by the Budcłha. Io fact, what the Buddha asserted was that a dying
person, depending
upon conditions, can be reborn. An invaribfo relacionship betweeo
death and
rcbirth was admitted only by the substantialists.
6. Sahinyonyena
1ii siddhir vininyonyena va yayoi;,
na vidyate tayol,
siddhil( kath11n nu khalu vidyate.EXAMJNAIION OP 0 CCURRENCE AND D JSSOLUTJON
'fhe occurrence of things, either together or separateły ,
is not evjdent: lf
so, how can their establishment be evident?
MKV(P) p.4l5 ; MKV(V) p. 180.
29)
This cooclusion ofNagarjuna is related to his criricisms in
the previous verses.
He is simply questioning the metaphysical assertioos relating
to occurrence and
dissołution , birth and death.
7. lqayasya St11{1bha110 niisti nfikfayasyasti
Stl'f?'Jbhaval/,
k!t1Jfl5ya vibhavo niisti vibhavo nak1ayasya ca.
Occurrence of that which is waning does not exist, nor is
there occurrence
of that whicb is not waning. Dissolution of that which is
waning does not
exist, nor is there dissołution of the not waning.
MKV(P) p.415 ; MKV(V) p.180.
The term k!aya was used in the Buddhjsr texrs in the cootext
where warung or
compJete extinction is implied. Whereas the term nirodha
could mean ce.asing
that coułd be followed by arising (utpada) and, as such,
they could be used as
comp lementaries to explain change and impennanence as well
as dependent
arising, the term k!aya had no such complementary term
except irs negation,
a-k!aya, which impJies permanence. For t:his reason,
Nigarjuna was able to
maintain chat there is neither absolute cessation (k!aya)
nor perrnanence
(a-k!aya) of both occurrence (sa?'(lbhava) and djssolution
(vibhava),
8. Sa'f?'Jbhavo vibhavaf cai11a vina bhavaf?Z na 11idyate,
sa?'(lbhava?!Z vibhat1a7!1- oaiva 111'14 bh4110 na 11tdyate.
Without an cxistent, occurrence as weU as clissolution arc
not evident,
Wicbout occurrence as well as clissolution, an existent is
not evident."
296 TuE PHllOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W Ay
9. St1f!Jbht111011ibhavaśc11i1111 n11 śunyasyopapadyate,
It1f!Jbht1flo tJtbha11aś caiva nafUnyasopapadyate,
Either occunence or d.issolution of the empty is not
appropńate. Either
occurrence or d.issolution of the non-empty is also not appropriate.
lO. Sa'f!Zbhavo 11ibht111aś caiva naika ity upapadyate,
Itlf?Jbhavo 11ibha11aś ctlitJa na nanety upapadyate.
lt is not appropriate to assume tha.t occurrencc and
d.issolution are identical. lt is not appropriate to assume that occucrence and
d.issolution arc
diffcrcnt.
MKV(P) pp.416-418; MKV(l1 pp. 180-181.
lt is probab1y the use of the term bhava at XXl.8 that Jed
!nada to assume chat
it represents a unique realm ofexistence recognized by
Nigarjuna. However, if
we arc to keep in mind the two metaphysical schoołs-
Sarvastivada and
Sautrlintika-and their metaphysical doctrines of identity
and difference, it is
possible to interpret the statement in verse 8 as wcll as
the two verses chat follow
as straightforward criticisms of these two schools.
For example, a Sautriincika who denies a bhiva or .wabhava
can maintain
that occurrence and dissolution can take plac:e without a
permanent entity
(bhava, s11abha11a). Occurrence and dissolution woułd then
mean the absence
of continuity. Nagarjuna denjes this.
On the conuary, a 52.rvascivadin can maintain thar a bha11a
oc wabhava can
exist without occurrcnce and dissolution, and this would
account for continuity
but negate difference. Tbis too is rejected by Nagarjuna.
Similarly, occucrence and dissolution arc incompatible with
the "empty''
(fUnya), as understood by a Sauuancika, or the
"non-empty" (afUnya) as ex.-
plained by the Sarvastivadin (see XX.16-18).
Furthermore, occurrence and dissolution arc neither
identicał (naika) nor dif·
ferent {niini) in a metaphysical sense.ExAMINATlON OF 0
CCURR.ENCE AND D ISSOLUTlON
11. Drśyate saf!JbhavaJ cai11a vibhavaJ cai11a te bhavett
drśyate saf!lbhavaJ caiva mohad vibhava e11a ca.
lt may occur to yon chat both occurrcnce and dissolution are
seen. How·
cvcr, both occurrence and dissolution arc scen only through
confusion.
MKV(P) p.419;,MKV(v,) p .181.
297
It would be a folly to assume that occurrcnce and
dissolution arc perceived
(driyate). Neither the Buddha nor Nagarjuna would be willing
to assert this.
Occurrence and dissołution in themselves are not perceivabłe
. They are seeo onJy in rełation to phenomcna that occur and dissolve. The
metaphysicaJ issues.
that arose during Niigarjuna's time as a result of the
cxtremist aoaJysis of
phenomena 1nto cvents and relations have ałready been
referred tp (see
XX.11).
12. Na bhaiiajjayate bhavo bhiivo 'bhavan na/iiyate,
nabhavaj1ayate 'bhavo 'bhavo bhavan na;ayate.
An existe.nt does not arise from an existent; neither does
an existent arisc
from a non-existent. A non-cxistent does not acise from a
non-existcnt;
neither does a non-existent arise from an existen't.
13. Na svato j'iiyate bhaval; parato naiva jayate,
na wataf? parataJ caiva;ayate jiiyate kutaf?.
An existent does not arise from iuelf, or from another or
from both itself
and anothcr. Whcnce can it then arise?
M.KV(P) pp.419-421; M.KV(v,) p .182.298 THE PHILOSOPHYOFTHE
MIDDLE WAY
Bhiiva and abhava referred to herc may be compared with the
sat and 11.fat in
the pre-Buddhist Indian philosophy. The unresolvable metaphysical
questioos
that plagued Indian philosophy for centuries, ąuestions such
as "Did existence
(sat) arise from non-existence (t11at)?" 01 ·vice
versa, have once again been in~
ttoduced into Buddhist thought by the Sarvastivadins and the
Sautrantikas.
The idencity and oon-idencity th.eories of causation,
theories of self-causacion
and exteroaJ causation, and many other metaphysical views
thatemerged in theBuddhist uadicion are repeatedly mentioned and rejected by
Nagacjuoa.
14. Bhavam.abhyupapannasya śaśvatoccheda-darfana??Z,
prasajyate sa bhavo hi nitya 'nityo 'tha va bhavet.
For him who is engrossed in existence, eternatism or
annihilarionism will
necessarily follow, for he would assume tbat it is either
permanent or impermanent.
MKV(P) p.421; MKV{V) pp.182- 183.
Nigarjuna is here presentiog the inevitable conclusions chat
a person involved
in·speculacions relacing to bhiiva will reach. If the bhava
is assumed to be perrnanent , he will end up with a notion of eternalism. lf.
on the contrary, the
bhava is looked upóo as beiog impecmanent, then he will
assert annihilation.
lt may be noted that the Sarvastivadins who were involved in
the nocion of
bhfiva, carne up with the bdief in an eternal self-nature
(1vabhava) or
substaoce (drr;vya). The same involvement led them to assume
the momentary
destruction (kfa11a-bhańga) of impermanent qualities or
characteristics of
bhi11fJ.
15. Bhava1n abhyupapannasya naivocchedo na śafvattt1rt,
udaya-vyaya-sa'l'(tt?ina// phala-hetvor bhavaf? sa hi.
[On the contrary,] for him who is engrossed in existence.
there would be
neither annihilationism nor eternalism, for, indeed ,
becoming is the
senes of uprising and ceasing of cause and
effert.EXAMINATION OF 0 CCURRENCli AND DISSO[UUON
16. Udaya-·vyaya-sa'f(tliinal? phala-hetvor bhaval; sa cel,
vyayasyapunarutpatter hetucchedaf? prasajyate.
lfie is assumed that becoming is che series of uprising and
ceasing of the
cause and effecc, tben with the cepeated non-arising of thac
which ceases,
it will follow that there will be annirulation of the cause.
MKV(P) pp.422-423; MKV(V) p.183.
299
The Saucrantika position was no moce differeot. They assumed
chat bhava is
oone other than bhava, the process of becorning represented
by the series
(sarpt'iina) of arising and ceasiog of effect and cause
(phala-hetvol?) As such ,
they believed chat cheir coocepcion of ex.istence docs not
come under either
eternalism or annihilationism.
Howeve.r, Nagarjuna has a different perception. He 3:-SSumes
that if the process of'becoming (bhava) is analysed into a series of arisi'ng
and ceasing of effect
and cause, as the Saurrantikas did, one is compelled to
recognize che nonrebirch (a-puJ'lllT-utpattt) of chat whicb bas ceased, and
there would be compłete annibiłacion of the c.ause. This is simiłar to the
argument used at XXI. 7.
17. SadbhavaJya svabha11ena nasadbhavaś ca yujyate,
nirva11a-kale coccheda~ praśa111'iid bhava-sarptatef?.
The non-existence of thacwhich possesses existence lit tttmS
ofsetf-nature
is noc appropriate. [On the contrary,J at the time of
fceedom, there will
be annihilation as a result of the appeasement of the stream
of becom.ing.
MKV(P) pp.423-424; MKV(V) pp.183-184.
Nagarjuoa's attcncion is now direcced at the Sauvaotika view
, for it is chat
whfrh finally contribu ted to the "personalist
theory" (p11dgala-vada) of the
Yatslputriyas. The Sauuintika will dismiss the Sarvastivada
view, insisting
that there is no way in which nif'll'ii11a can be cxplained
in terms of their nocion
of self-narure (svabhat•a) , especially because whac is
really cJÓsting (sadbhava)
oo its own (svabhavena) cannot become a non-cxiscent
(asadbhava).300 THE PH!LOSOPHY OF THE MIODLE WAY
However, the Sautrantika will say that as a result of the
appeasement of the
sedes ofbecoming (bha11a-saf!Jfat1), there is annihilation
at the tltne ofnirva„a.
Having stated this position, Nigjrjuna proceeds to analyse
its implications.
18. Carame na niruddhe ca prathttmo yujyate bhavaf?,
carame nanimddhe ca prathamo yujyate bhavaf?.
It is not propec to assume that thcre is first becoming whcn
the last has
ceased. Nor is it proper to assume that thete is first
becoming when the
last has not ceased.
MKV(P) p.425; MKV(V) p.184.
The Sautrantika tbeory of a series of momentary existences
is under investigation here. As meotioned before, the Sauuancikas were often
faced with the
problem of explaining arising (utpida). Thus, Nagarjuna
argues that the first
(moment of) becoming (prathamo bhava4) cannot occur when the
last (carama)
has ceased, for there will be nothing·to give rise to the
former. This is what was
referred to as the cessation of the cause (hetuccheda) at
XXI.16. The other
alternative is to assume tbat the enticy of the last moment
has not ceased
(aniruddha), and this, of course, makes it difficult for the
first becoming to occur at all.
19. Nirudhyaniiine carame pr11tha1no yadijiiyate,
nirudhyamiina ekaf? syaj1aya1nano 'jJaro bhavet.
If the fust were to be born when the kst is ceasing, then
that which is
ceasing would be one and that which is being boin would be
another.
MKV(P) p.426; MKV(V} 184.
Assum'.e that the first becoming occurs at the time wheo the
last is ceasing
(nirudhyamana). NQ:garjuna insists that, in that case, whac
is ceasing is oneEXAMINATION OP 0CCURRENCE AND DISSOLUTION 301
thing and what is arising is somcthlng complctcJy diffcrent
(aparo). Nagarjuna
is herc referring to the implications of the theory of
mo.menrs, namely, the
recognition of absolute discinccions.
20. Na cen nt'1Jdhyamanaś ca j'iiyamiinai ca yujyate,
iiirdha1p, ca mnyate ye1u leju skandhe!U1ayate.
Ii it is assetted th.at the ceasing is also the being boro,
this would not be
proper. For, in th.at.case1 whatever that is born in
rełation to the aggrcgates, would also be dying at the same time.
MKV(P) p.426; M.KV(V,J p.185.
Furcher complications will arise if it is assumed chat
something chat ceases is
aJso arising. Nagarjuna is not prcpared to acccpt such an
occurrence because
this would m can the simułtancous death and birth of the
aggtegates.
Thcrefore, an occurrence is not explained by a scrictly
momentary theory of cxistence advocated by the Saucrancikas.
21. Evaf!l fri!v api kale!u na yuklii bhava-saf!ltatil?,
tn!u ka/e!U ya na.stiiii k.athaf!I bhava-SPT(Jlatil?.
Thus, the stream of becoming is not proper in the context of
the three
pcńods of time. How can there be a s.tream ofbecoming th.at
does not aist during the three periods of time?
MKV(P) p.427; MKV(V) p .185.
The conclusion is inevitable that the series of becoming
(bhava·Sllf?llah) is not
appropriately explaiocd in terms ofthe three pcriods of
time, a concept which ,
as shown in the previous chaptcr, is not empirically
grounded .CHAPTER
TWENTYTWO
·Examination of the Tathagata
(Tathagata-pafik.ra)
l . Skandha na n'iinya~ s~t1ndhebhyo n'iiJ?!Jin skandh'fi na
tefu sal;,
tathagataf? skandhav'iin na kata1110 'tra tathagatal;.
The tathiigata is neither che ag.gregates noc different from
them. The aggcegates are notin him; nor is be in the~ggregates . H e is not
possessed of
the aggregates. In such a context, who is a tathagata?
2. Buddhaf? .fkandhan upadiiya yadi nasti svabhii11ataf?,
rvabhavataś ca yo n'iisti kuta!? sa parabhavt1taf?.
lfa Buddha were co be dependent upon the aggregates, he does
not exist
in tenns ofself-nature. He who does not exist in terms
ofself;nature, how
can he exist in terms of othec na~re ?
MKV(P) pp.432-436; MKV(V) pp.187- 189.
ln addicion co some of the terms used by the Buddha to refer
to his owo
achievements, his disdpJes used a vast array of epithets in
extolling his virtues.
It is significant to noce that none of these epithets caused
so much
misunderscanding as the one under discussion in the preseot
chapter. narriely,
tathagata. lt seems chat the very cooceptioo of tathagata
iovited
misundetstanding.
l"he term can be rendeced inro English as
"thus-gone" (tathii-gata) . The
conception of one who has "rhu>-gone" immed
iateły brings to mind the idea of
an ''agent'' (sec Chaptcr 11). lt was. thefefore, ioevitable
tliat when questions
relaring to rhe "destiny'' of r.he enlightened one were
raisttd. they were always
ralsed in relation to a tath1ig11ta.
30~EXAMlNATION OF TATHAGllTA 303
Nagarjuna was aware that questions pertaining not only to
the final desciny,
but also to the nature of the living sa.int were raiscd
during rhe Buddha's day. A
discussion between Sariputta and a monk named Yamaka, who
had enten:a.ined rhe belief rhat a lathagala is annihilated after death (param
maraf!a) is
repocced in rhe Saf!'yutla-niliiiya (S 3.109-115; Tsa 5.2
(Tairho 2.30c-3lcl).
Reading the first part of this discussion, one gcts the
impression that Sariputta
was 'ieluctant to identify the tatliiigala with the five
aggregates or to distinguish
the tath'iigata from the aggregatcs. On rhe basis of this,
it is possible to come to
the condusions, rhat rhe tathagala is linguiscically
cranscendeot.
However, if the discussioo is followed to the very end, one
can clearly sec rhat
such a conclusion is not warranted. For Sariputta is not
willing to admit a
talhagala in an absolute sense (saccato thetato), comparable
to the
metaphysical "self'' (a/man) that was considered to be
pcrmaoent and eteroal.
Indeed, toward the end ofrhe discussion, Sariputta movcs
from the conceprion
oftalh'iigata to the notion of"self' (atta) and refuscs
to admit a self rhat is identical with or different from the aggregates.
Nagarjuna, as if he had read this discoursc:, begins the
present chapter in an
idencical way, first ma.inta.ining that tłle tath'iigata is
neither identical nor different from the aggregates, and then proceeding to
questioo the existeocc or
non-existence of the talhagata after death. As in che
Sa'1pyulta passage, Nagarjuna immediately qu,alifies his rcfereoq:: to ,the
living tathagata, insisting that
the tath'iigata or the buddha under invęscigation is one
possessed ofself-nature
(s11abha11a) and beoce similar to the nodon of "self'
(a~ta) rejectcd by Saripuna.
Nagarjuna thereupQn uses his f'amous argumcnc that if the
tathagata is not
found in cerms of self-nature, he cannot either be found in
terms of ochernature (para-bh'ii11a).
3. Pralitya para-bh'iivaf!' yal/_ so 'natmety upapadyate,
yai canatm'ii sa ca kathaf!' bha11i;ya1i tath'iigataf?.
He who is dependent upon other narure would appcopriatelf be
without
self. Yet, how can he who is without self be a tathiigata?
MKV(P) p .437; MKV(V) p.189.
If self-oature (s11abh'ii11a) wece co be equivaJent co self
(atman) as an enticy in304 'THE PH!LOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
it.self, tben whaccver is of "other-nature"
(para-bhiiva) will be "no-self'
(aniitma). "No-self' in this parcicular sense, which implies
absolute difference,
i.s not acceptable to Nagarjuna, for ie i.s a recognition of
a difference between a
tathigata and the psycbophysical pcrsonalicy.
4. 'fadi niisti svabhii11aś ca para-bhavafl kathaf{Z bhavel,
svabha11a-parabha11abhyaf{Z
rte kal; sa tath'iigalal/.
lfthece exists no sclf-nature, how couJd thcrc be
other-nature? Without
both self-nature and other-n.ature, who is this tathiigata?
MKV(P) p.437; MKV(V} p .190.
The idea that if there were to be no self-oaturc
other-nature too would not be
evidcnt was already emphasized at I.3. A third metaphysical
alte.?nacive that
uacscends both self-narure and other-natuie is herc denied.
·
5. Skandhan yady 11nupadiiya bhavel kaicil tathagatal/,
sa idiin"im upiidadyad upadiiya tato bhavet.
lf there were to be a tathligata because of non-graspiog on
to the aggrcptes, he should still depend upon them in the present. As such he
will be dependent.
MKV(P} p.438; MKV(V) p. 190.
In the early di.scourses, a person in bondage and therefore
in a state of suffering
(dukkha) is explained in terms of the five aggregates of
grasping (upadiinakkhandha) . A person who is freed is said to be withbuc
gta.sping (anupadiina),
buc not wfrhout the aggregates. The gerund upadiiya was used
in the discourscs
to express two different meanings, namdy, (i) ''clinging
to" (sec an-upadiiya,
Vin l.14; A 1.162; 4.290, etc.) and (ii) "depcoding
upon" (D l.205, kii/an ca
I'"""Jafl ca upadiiya). lt was onJy in the
farmer sense that a person was said roEXAMINATION OF TA11iAGJ\TA 30S
be freed from the agg~egates, not jo the latter sense. Yet,
with the development ofsubstantialism, that is, when a freed person carne to be
looked upon as
being totally different from the one in bondage, cach having
his own nature
(.wabhi11a)(see Chapter XXV), the freed one was pcrceived
not only as one not
gr25ping (anupidiiya) on to the aggreg:ites, but also as one
who is independent
of the aggregates. lt is this subsrantialist interpretation
chat Nagatjuna is
criticizing when he points out chat ifa tathagata were to
exist without grasping
on to the aggregatcs (skandhan anupadiiya), he will still be
dependent upon
(11padadyad) tbem ac the prcsent time (idiinl'?I), that is,
as long as he is aJive.
Nigatjuna was thus going back to the Buddha's owo definicion
ofa freed one.
6. Skandhan capy anupadiiya nasti kaścit tathagataf?,
yaf ca niisty anupadiiya sa upidiisyate kathaf!J.
There exists no tathiigata independent of the aggtegates.
How can he
who does not cxist depcndentły be graspcd?
MKV(P) P.438; MKV(V) p.190.
Nigarjuna seems co be using the passive vcry upadiisyate in
an
epistcmologicaJ sense. In the previous verse. he maintained
thac a living
tathagata should be dependent upon the aggregatcs, even
thougb he docs not
grasp on to them . Herc Nagarjuna is re-asserting the same
position, wheo he
says: "There exists no tathagata who is jndependcnc of
the aggregates." The
reason for this is that such an independent tathagata, being
a mctaphysical entity like the atman, cannoc be grasped or known.
7. Na bhavaty anupadattam upadiina'!' ca ki'!'cana,
na c"ftsti nirupiJdiJnaf? kathrJf'!ICrJna tathagalaf?.
There is no sphere of non-grasping, nor is rhere something
as grasping.
Neither is there someone who is without grasping. How can
there be a
tathiigata?
MKV(P) p.439; MKV(P) p.190.306 THE PHJLOSOPHY OF THE MIODLE
WA't
The metaphysical speculacions regarcling identity and
differcncc (svabhava,
parabha11a) leave the dependent or the gcasped (up'iidatta),
depeodeoce or
grasping (up'iidiina) as well as the one who is free or independent
(nirupadiinaf?). wichout any basis. How can there be a
tath'iigata?The fact that
it is only an explaoation in terms ofidenticy and difference
that is rejected herc
is dcarly inclicaced in the verse that folJows.
8. TatJ11'iinyatven11 yo nlirli mrgyamiif!aś ca pancadh'ii,
upiidiinena sa katha~ prajflapyate tath'iigataf?.
He who, sought for in the fivefold manner, docs not exist in
the form ofa
different idcntity, how can tbar tathagata be made known
throogh
grasping?
MKV(P) p.439' MKV(V) p.190.
The substancialiast explanation of a tath'iigata would imply
that he has completely uaosformed himself in to a different entity, chat is, a
tathagata having
his own-nature (wabh'iiva) with no relatiooship to the
person in bondage .
However, examining the fivefold aggregates, no such encity
can be dis<:overed.
Such a tath'iigata cannot be explained in terms of
dependeoce (upadiinena).
Thus, the conceptioo of depeodence (up'iidiina) is
incompatible witłi both
idcoticy and difference. What is denied herc is neither
dependence nor a
tath'iigata, but merely the mctaphysical approaches co both
dependence and
tath'iigala.
lnstead of rranslating tatt11a and anyatva and as idencity
and diliereoce, we
bave rendered che phrase as "different idenity"
since it occurs in the singular.
9. Yad aprdam uptliinatp tal wabhavan na vidyate,
s11abh'ii11ataś ca yan nasti kuliJJ tat parabhavatal}.
This grasping is not foond in terms of self-narure. How can
that which
does not exist in terms of self-namre come 10 be in terms of
othcr-natwc.?
MKV(P) pp.439-440; MKV(J1 p. 191.ExAM1NATI0NoF TAm°AcATA 307
Just as much as a tathagata cannot be e.xplaioed
satisfactorily by rełying upon a
theory of.identity (111abha11a) or difference (parabhiva),
eveo so grasping itself
(upadiina) cannot be found in terms bf self-oature or other
oature. In other
words, ie woułd not be appropriate to cxplain grasping as an
inevicable act or
tendency in human beings.
10. Evarrz fUnyam upadiinam upadiita ca sarvafaf?,
prajnapyale, ca fUnyena ka1harrz funytlJ 1a1hiiga1af?.
Thus, grasping and gra.spec arc empty in every way. How can
an cmpty
tathagata be made known by somcthing that is empty?
MKV(P) pp.440-441 ; MKV(V) p.191 .
Thus, grasping as well as the one who grasps are empcy in
every possible way.
They are devoid of aoy substance.
For the substantialist, the lalhagala as well as the
aggregates have substance
or owo-.nature, even though they arc clifferent from·one
another. The substantialist can cxplain the tathigata, whose self-narure
(svabhiva) is freedom, contrasting him with the one who is in bondage as a
result of his being a "graspcr"
(upadiitr) and whose nature is discina (para) from that of
the tathagata.
However, witb Nagarjuna's deniaJ of self-narure, thar sharp
dichotomy aJso is
dissolved. Hence Nagarjuna's insiscence chat an empty
tathagata cannot be
made koown in relation to an equally empty ''grasper"
(upidiitr) or "grasping"
(upadiina) referred to in the previous verse.
11 . ŚU.nyam iti na vaktavyam Qfunyam iii va bhavet,
u6hayarrz nobhaya-f!J celi prajnapty artha'J?'J tu kathyate.
"Empty," "non-empty," "both'' or
"neither"- thcse should not be
dedared. lt is expressed only for the,purpos·e of
communication.
MKV(P) p.444; MKV(V) pp.192-193.
Note again the use of the·tli-formula. Nagarjuna is rejecting
any theonzing308 iHE PHllOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
rcgarding either the "empty"·or the
"non-empty" or both or neither. Neither
the cmpty nor the non··Cmpty should be ceificd. These terms
arc used onJy for
the sake of communicating or exprcssing an cxpe.rience
which, being dependent (prmtyasamutpanna), has no static self-narure
(svabhava), and as such
canooi: be demarcated and reified. The subtle difference
between vaktavya
("should be declared") and kathyate ("is
spoken of, isexpressed!') should not go
unnoticed. For Nagarjuna, dedaration ·and expression a.re
two differcnt ac·
tivities, the former caJling for unqucscioiled acceptance, a
sort of cacegorical
1
imperative, the laner.lcaving room for modificatioo
depending upon the contcxt.
. This stacemeot of Nagarjuna is better understood in the
light of the analysis
of conceptS provided by a modern philosopher like William
James who
recognizes a pragmatic view of language and truth, in
contrast to substantialist
philosophers like Plato for whom "concepts" arc
the incorruptible reals.
,
12. Siifvafiifiiśvatiidy atra kutal? rante calu!faya??J,
antananfiidi capy
atra kuta/? ś'iinte catu1faya??J.
HÓw can the tettalemma of e,ternal, non-eternal, etc., be in
the peaceful?
·How can the tetralemma of finite, infinite, etc., be in the
peaceful?
Mk1/(P-) p.446; MKV(V) p.194.
~
Siinta is.an appeased one. It is the tathagata who has
appeased the dispositions,
'obsessions as we11 as the object (sec comments oo V.8). For
him, ·the fourfold
metaphysical alternacives eicher cegarding the duration of
phenomena such as
erernality (śaś11ata) and oon-eteroality (aśiiśvata) or
regarding the extent of
phenomena such as the finite (anta) and the infinite
(ananta) do not exist. He
has stopped brooding over the past and ruoning after the
future.
13. Yena griiho grhrtas tu ghano 's5ti tathagtrtaf?,
niis5ti sa vikalpayan nirortasyiipi kalpayet.
Discriminating on the bas.is of grasp.ing or the grasped,
and firmly in-EJw.łJNATION OF TA m AGATA
sisting that a tathilgata "exists" or "does
not exist," a person would think
similarty even of one who has ceased.
MKf/(P) p.447; MKV(V) p.194 .
309
The Buddha's reasons for the rejection of the notion of
tath'iigata in the
Sa11Jyutta passage refcrred to above (see comments on
XXII.1-2) are clearly emphasized by Nagarjuna. The Buddha rejected a
tath"(igata bccause his existence
was asserted in a real and absołuce sense (saccato thetato):
When Nagarjuna
spcaks ofa dogmacie grasping (gt'1ih11) on to something as
the real or substantial
(ghana) existence or non-existence (asfiti . . . niisfitt)
ofthe tathagata, he was
expressing the sentiments similar to those of the Buddha.
Fu!thennore, arguing in a.sim.ilarway as the Buddha did, Nagarjuna maintaińs
that the same sort
of substantiałist specułations lead to the views regarding
the existence and non'-
existence of the tath'iigata even after his death.
Hece chere is no denial of a talhag4ta, but only of a
substantial entity. The
verse tbat follows is unequivocal in this regard.
14. Svabhavataś ca :fUnye 's1nif?IŚ cinfii naivopapadyate,
para'f{l nirodhad bhavati buddho na bhavatiti.Va.
When he is empty in terms ofself-nature, the thought that
the Buddha
exists or does no~ exist after death is not approptiate.
MK.V(P) p .447; MKV(flj p.194.
Hete the term asmin, in the locative absołute construction
(asmin s11abbii11ataf
ca f unye), refers to the t11tliiigatt1. Ifthe tpthiigata
who is alivejs,empty of selfnature, then it ~not appropriate to assume that he
exists or does not exist after
death. lt is only the substantialist thinking (cintii) that
leads to the
metaphysical quescions which wece left undedared (avyakrta)
by the Buddha.
15. Prapancayanti
ye buddha'f{l prapańcafitam 4vyaja7[1,
te prapa11cah4taf? s(lf't)e na paiyanti tath'iigata'f{l.310
THE PHILOSOPHY OF THB MIDDl.li WAY
Those who geo.erate obsessions with greac regacd to the
Bpddha who has
gone beyond obsessions and is constant, all of them,
impaired by obsessions, do not perceive the tathiigata.
MKV(P) p.448; MKV(V) p.19~ .
Here we radically differ from the prevailing cxplanations
that prapańca means
thought distinct from reality (see !nada, p . 135). Having
rejected the moce
widespread view that Buddhisrn recognizes an
"unspeakable" (a11acya) and "indefinabJe" (anirvacanlya)
truth or reality (tattva) , which Jeads co the above iqterpretatioo
ofprapaf!_ca, we have reodered the term as "obsessioo.'' .
The Buddha remains ałoof from obsessions
(prapańcali'ta"!t) . As such, he is
not understoocł or grasped by those who are obsessed. A
person who is obsessed
with the idea of identity will understand the Buddha in a
way .different from
·one who is obsessed with the idea of difference. One wilJ
say that he "exists"
(astt) and the othec will insist that he "does nor
exist'' (niistt).
The Buddha who has overcome such ''obsessions" is
"not so variable"
(a11yaya?fl) . His perceptions are not variable in the same
way as those of the
unenłightened ones who are dominated by obsessions.
Nagarjuna could not
have been unaware of the defin:ition of the Buddha as
"one who has become
stable and ste;JY'• (fhita1'{1- ane1jappatlaf!l, A 3.3 77;
fhita7?1 ciltaf!Z, S 5.74).
The term a11yaya in the present coutext expresśes the same
idea of stability and
steadfasroess achieved by a Buddha. This is not to assume
his permanent ex-
1St • eoce.
16. Tatliiigalo yat s11abh'ii11t,M tat s11abh'ii11am idaf!I
jagat,
tathagato nil/s11abha110 n'i'1s11qbha11am idaT!l jagat.
Whatever is the self-naturc of the tathiigata, thac is also
the self-nature of
the universe. The tathiigata is devoid ofself-nature. This
universe is also
dcvoid of self-nature.
MKV(P) pp.448-449; MKV{V) p.195.
The first statement of Nagarjuna may be takeo to mean thac
there is a self-
. nature of the tathigata which is identical with ~hat of
the universe. This wduld
be justification for the belief in a permanent entity wh.ich
is identical witb the
reality of the universe, comparable to the atman and brahman
of the HinduEXAMlNATION OP TAmAGATA 311
uadition. However, Nagatjuna irnmediatdy sounds the warning
that there is
noc such self-nature either in the lalliiigata or in the
universe. Trus would mean
that non-substantiality (nairiitmya) applies not only to the
individual (pudgala
= tathagakl) buc also co all phenomena (dharma =
jagat).CHAPTER
TwENTY THREE
Examination of Perversions
(Viparyasa-pank!a)
1. Sa~alpa-prabht1110 rago d11efo mohtli ca kathyate,
śubh'ii1ubha-viparyaiiin sa1{tbhavt1nti prafitya hi.
Lust, hatred, and confusion are said have thougł}tas their
source. Perversions regatding the plea.sant and the unpleasant arise depending
upon
these.
MKV(P) p.451; MKV(V) p.197.
Followiog upon a discussion of the tathagata in reJation to
the world, a discussion thac avoided absolute identicy and ab$olute difference,
Nagarjuoa rakes
up the questioo regarding perversions (11iparyasa) which
makes a difference between a person in bondagc and one: who is freed.
The four perversions are discussed by the Buddha at
Anguttara 2.52. Tbey
pertain to percepcions (saflflti), thoughts (citta), and
views (diftht). Perversion
(vipalliisa) of perceptioo or thought or view occurs with
the identification of
t. the impermaoeot with the permaoent (anicce niccan tt) ,
11. the not unsatisfactory with the unsatisfactory (aduk.khe
dukkhan h),
UL the non·substantial with the substantial (anattani alta
ti),
and
1v. the unpleasant with the pleasant (tliubhe śubhan lt).
It is important to noce that perversion ii is.based upon
perversion i, and
perversion iv is based upon perversion iii. While
perversions li and iv relate to
subjective attitudes, perversions i and iii arc cognitive in
nature.
The rccognition of subjective perversions (i.e. ii and iv)
does not mean that
those experieoces 1eląting to whith pervcrsions arise do nor
exist. lndeed, experiences of the płeasant (śubha = man'iipa) and unpłcasanc
(aśubha =
312EXAMINATION Ol' PERVERSIONS 313
amanapa) sensations occur even in the enlightened ones
(Iti11uttaka 38). Perversion is the wrong identification of these exp~riences .
However, the same cannot
be said of the cognitive peNersioos, for the Buddba would be
reluctant to
assume that there is an experience corresponding to
something that is either
permanent or substaotiaL
For Nagarjuna, perversions ii and lv arc not due to purely
inteUectual or
cognitive incapacity on the part of the indlvidual. Tbey are
due more to the
subjective elements dominating thoughts sur.h as lust and
hatred, wbicb acise
along witb thoughts (sa1{Zkalpa-prabhavo). even though these
lattcr are not
part of the wodd ofexperience. Th.is explanation of
Nagarjuna is based upon a
passage in the St11(1yulla wherein the Buddha identifies
desire (kQ,ma) with
thoughts of lust (sa1{Zkappa-rag4) without confusing it with
whatever is
beautiful (citrint) in the world (sec S 2.22; Tsa 48.20
[Taisho 2.345b]}.
As such, itis not surprfai.ng to see Nagarjuna beginnibg his
analysis with the
last of the perversions, namely, the identification of the
pleasant with the
unplcasant (a.śubhe śubhan Jt), a subjective perversion that
is based upon the
cognitive.confusion
(i.e., anattaniatfii tz). Nagarjuna was probably interested
in beginning his analysis with the subjective perversion
because the metaphysicians, who carried che analytical process beyond its
limit, bad difficulty in accounting for the emergence ofsensations such as the
pleasant and the unpleasant.
2. Subhiśubha-viparyaiiin saf!Jbht111antiprafitya ye,
te svabha11a11 na
11idyante tasmiit kleśa na tatl'llataf?.
Whatever perversions of the pleasant and the unpleasant that
occur
dependendy arc not evident in terms of self-nature. Therefore,
the
defiłements acc not in themselves.
MKV(P) p.453; MKV(V) p.197.
The perversions of the pleasant and the unpleasant are
dependcntly arisen. As
mentioned before, they are tht products of 1ust and hatred;
they arise within
the individual. For this tea,son, they are not found in
themselves (na
s11abhavataf?). Whatever defilments (.kleśa) occur as a
result of such perversions
ćannot be pa.et of the expetiemced world. Rather they
related to the way in
which the world is·perceived by.the individual. lt is ooly
in this sense that they
are looked upon as being unrcal (na.tattvata'f?).314 Thra
PHlLOSOPttY OF THE MIODLE W AY
3. Atmano 'JtittJa-n{istit11e na krJtha'f?Ztc aa sidhyatal;,
lam vinastitva-nastilve kleSiin'li'f?J sidhyatal; katha'f!'.
The existence or the non-existence of the self is not
established in any
way. Without that, how can the existence or the
non-existence of
defilemenu bć-·established?
MKV(P) p.453; MKV(V) p.198 .
The perversión regarding what is pleasant and unpleasant has
been traced back
to the pecversion whcre the non-substantial (anatman) is
.identificd with che
substancial (atman). The substantial and the
non-substantial, in the eyes of the
mctaphysiciari, pertain to existence (flJtitva) and
non-cxistence (n'1isti111a)
respectively (see V.8; XV. 71 11). The discourse to
Katyayana .rejects both thesc
views as being metaphysi1=al.
Nagarjuna is herc insisting that neithc.r the 6cistence not
the oon-existence
of a metaphysical self can be proved. lf there were to be no
such self, then the
defilcments associated with such a self also cannot exist.
In the absence of a
substantial self, ifonly the defilernents wece to exist,
then they should have selfexistence, which was an idea denied at XXIII.2. Tuus,
neither the substantial
existence ofa self noc the substantial existence
ofdefilrnents can be established.
4. KllIJacidt/ hi
bhavanfime kiesa!? sa ca na .ridhyati,
kaścid aho 11in1i ki'f?Z(;it s411ti k/eSii na kasyacit.
These defilements, indeed, bclong to someone. Yet, such a
person is not
cstablished. In other words, in the absence of anyone, these
defiłments
seem ło exist without belonging to anyonc.
MKV(P) p-453; MKV(V? p. 198.
Not onJy are the defilments not established as substantiał
elements, they can·
not be proved to exist even as attributes. If defilements
are considcred as
belonging to someone(.kaścia) who issubstantially existing.
the abscoc~ofsuch
a substantial entity would mean the absence of de(llemcnrs
as attr.ibutes.Ex.AMlNATION OF PERVERSIONS
5. SvaA'iiya-dr1#11a1 kleśiil? k/ifte santi na pancadha,
waliaya-dr1!i11at kii/ta'!' kleie1v api na pancadha.
The defilments arc like the view of one's own personality.
Within the
defiłed, they arc not found in the fivefold way . The
defiled is like the
view of one's own personality, for even within the
defilements it is not
found in the fivefold way.
MKV(P) p.454; MKV(V? p. 198.
315
This is a ńutber cdcicism of the substantialist notions of
"defilemenrs" (klefa)
as well as of the "defiled" (k.li$1<1). Such
substantialist perspectives arc comparable to the views regarding an
"embodied person" (111ak.aya-dr1/1), who is
not obtainabłe when that personality is analysed into the
five aggregates.
6. Svabhavato na vidyante fubhaiubha-11iparyajiil/,
prafitya k.atamiin kfefiil? iubhafubha-viparyayan.
The pcrvecsioN regarding the pleasanc and the unpleasant arc
not evident from the standpoint of sełf-nature. Depending upon which
perversions of the pleasant and the unpleasant are these defilements?
MKV(P) p.455 ; M.KV(V) p. 199.
Just as much as botb the deft.lements (k.leia) and the
defiled (k.li;Fa) arc not evident in substantial form, so are the perversions
that give rise co dcfiłements .
Tbey too arc not fouod in aoy substantial way. The question
theo is: What is
the nature of the perverson relating to the pleasant and the
unpleasant depending upon wbich defilements are said co arise?
Here there is no denial of perversions nor the deftlements.
What has been
quescioneq is only the way in which theso are
cooceptualized.
7. Rupa-fabrla-rasa-sparf'ii gandha dharm'iiś ea
11Z{ilidha~,
vas/fJ ragasya dve/aJya mohasya ca vikalpyale.316 THE
PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
Material form, sound, taste, touch, smeU and concepts- these
are
discriminatcd as the sixfold foundations of lust, hatred,
and confusion.
MKV(P) p.456; MKV(V) p.199.
Analysing !ust, hatred, and coofusion in terms of the four
perversions, it may
be maintained that Just and hatred arc subjective attitudes,
while confusion
refers to the cognitive aspect of understanding (sec
com.ments on XX1lI. I),
even though the cognitive and artirudinal aspects are
dependent upon one
another. The present statement of Nagarjuoa implies the
dependence of the
attirudinal as well as the cognitive aspects ofexperience
upon the sixfold objects
of sense experiencc.
8. Rupa-fabda·rll.fa-spari"ii gandha dharmaś ca
kevaliif?,
gandharvanagarak"iir7i maficz~svapna-sa?rt,nibhaf?. ·
Material form, sound, taste, touch smell as well as
concepts-all these are
comparable to the city of the gandharvas and resemble
mir.ages and
dreams.
MKV(P) p.457; MKV(V} pp.199·200.
The similes of the "dreamH (svapna) and the "city
of the gandharvas"
(gandharva-nagttra) have already been employed, a.long with
•:ilJusion"
(maya), to refute the substantialist cxplanation of the
dispositionally concłitioned phenorncna (sa??ZskrtaXsee VII. 34). The six
objects of experience referred to at XXIII. 7 arc indeed dispasitionally
conditioned. They arc not objects
that arc found in themselves (s11abh411ataf?). Nor arc they
absoluteły noneXJstent.
9. AśubhtTf{I va
fubhaf(t vapi kutas teru bhavi[yati,
maya-puru!a-kalpe!U pratibimba-sametu ca.ExAMINATION OF
PERVERSIO"NS
How can the pleasant and the unpleasant come to be in people
who are
fabrications of illusion or who are comparable to mirror
images?
MKV(P) p.458; MKV(V) p.200.
317
What Nagarjuna has been criticizingso far is a
substantiałist theoi:y ofthe pleasant and the unpleasaot (svabhtii/alo , ..
fubhaJubha11iparyayan XXIII.6).
His argument in the prescnt verse is directed against the
belief that such
substantial expeticnces can occur in thoughts of hwnan
beings who are
themselves non-substa11tial, and who a.ce comparable to
mirror images or reflections (see commentary on :XVII.31-32).
10. Anapek!ya :fubhaf!Z nti.rti afubhaf!Z prajńapayemahi,
yatprafitya fubha'f!t tasmtic chubhaf!Z naivopapadyate.
We make known that the unpleasant does not exist without
being conti,ngent upon the pleasant, and that the pleasant, in its turo, is
dependent upon that [i.e. the ®pleasant]. The.refote, the pleasant [in itself]
is
not appropriate.
1I'. AnapekfyiiJubhaf!Z ntisti :fubhaf!l prajfJapayemahi,
yatprafityaśubhaf!Z ta.rmad aśubhaf!Z naiva vidyate.
We make known that the pleasant does not exi$t without being
contingent upon the unpleasant, and that the unpleasant, in its turo. is
dependent upon that [i.e., the płeasant] . Therefore, the
unpleasant [in
itself] is not evident.
MKV(P) pp.458-459; MKV(V? p ,200.
This is a elear refutation of the substancialist views of
both the pleasant and the318 THE PHJLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
unplcasant. Nagarjuna insists that thcy ace dependent upon
one another. Thcy
arc not independent experiences wherc one is repłaced by
another, as in the
case of the theory of"attainmcnt" (praptz) and
"oon-auainment" (apraptt)(see
comments on .XVI.10, XXIV.32).
12. Avidyamiine ca fubhe kuto rago bhavi,yah~
aśUbhe avidyamiine ca kuto dvefo bhavifyali.
When the pleasant is not evident, whence can there be lust?
Wben the
unpleasant is not cvident, whence can there be hatred?
MKV(P) p.459; MKV(V) p.201.
Io addition to being mutuaHy dependent, the plcasant and the
unpleasant provide a foundation for the subjective tcndencies such as lust and
hatred. Thus,
lust would be non-ex.isrent if the pleasanc were not
cvident. Similarly, hacred
would be non-ex.istent, if the unpłeasant wece not evideot.
This, indeed, is the
conclusion of the Sa'f!'yutta passage referred to at
XXIII.1. In that context, the
Buddha was not denying the pleasant and the unpleasant
expericnces in the
world. He was simply insisting chat when such experiences
occur a wise man
resuainrs his ycarning (chanda) for it.
13. Anitye nityam ity evaf'!J yadi graho viparyayaf?,
nanilya1p virlyate funye kulo graho viparyayaf?.
Iftbere were to be grasping on to the view, "Wbat is
impermanent is permanent," then there is perversion. The impcrmancnt is
not evident in the
contcxt of the empty. How can there be grasping or
pecversion?
MKV(P) p.460; MKV(V) p.201.
So far Nagarjuna has endeavored to show thac the perversion
regarding the
pleasant and the unpleasant is che result of a cognicive
confusion which led to
che belicf in a substance ot self (atman). Wich the present
statement, Nagar-Exl.MINATION OF PERVERSIONS 319
juna begins co analyse the conception of impermanence
(11nity11) in order to explain che lathagata's cognitive uoderstanding of the
world of experieoce. This
understanding enables the tathagata co eliminate the
perversion relating to
happiness and sufferlng.
Herc, the perversion pertains to grasping of the impermanent
a:s the perma·
nent. lfso, the perspectivc in wbich the lalhagata looks at
the world should be
one of impermanence. Unforcunatcly, the notion of
impermanence chat
dominated the Buddhist tradition during Nagarjuna's day was
more a
metaphysical one (see commentaries on Chapter Vll) than an
einpirical one.
For the metaphysician, the absence of permanence implied the
reality of the
momeocary. Nagacjuna rightly believes that as much as
grasping after permanence is a perversion. so is grasping after the reality of
the momentary ( =
k1an.1'lla). The deoial of permanence does not commit
oneself to the ocher ex·
cceme of momentary.destruction (k/an.a-bhańa). Emptiness
(śunyafii) does not
imply any such momentariness. ·
14. Anitye nityarn ity eva~ yadi graho viparyayaf?,
anityam i~y api gr'iihaf? śiinye kif{J na viparyayaf?.
lf gcasping on to the view, "What is impermanent is
pecmaoent," is
perversion, how is it that even the grasping after che view,
"What is e1npty is impermanent," does not constitute a perversion?
MKV(P) p.462: MJ...'V(V) p.202 .
It is possible for someone to raise the quescion as to
whether grasping after the
empry would irself be a perversion, just as much as grasping
after che permanenr or the impermanent would consritute perversioos. Nagarjuna
is herc raising this question and chen proceeds to answer it in the following
verse.
15. Yena grhr;ah' yo grliho grahTt'ii yac ca grhyate,
"paśantani saniiitJi tasmad gi?iho na vidydttte.
That througb which there is grasping, whatever grasping
there ~. the320 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W/\.Y
grasper as well as that which is grasped - all these are
appeased.
Therefore, no gcasping is evident.
MKV(P) p.465; MKV(V} p.20.3„
The middle path enunciated in the discoutse to Kacyayana
avoided the two extremes relating to philosophical understanding and
explanation. This was
achieved thro1Jgh che appeasement of dispositions and the
elimination of
grasping. Because of non-grasping, all che metaphysical
qucstions relating to
the faculcies (yena grh11iit1), the proces.s of
understanding (griiha), the person
involved in such understanding (grahtfii) as well as the
object of uąderstanding
(yac ca grhyate), come to be appeased. The appeased one
(fanta) does not continuc to taise questions or doubts beyor.d a certain limit,
not because he knows
evetything nor bccause he does not care to know, but because
he is aware of the
conflicts generated by any pursuit of koowledge that gocs
beyond experience.
The facr chat grasping for emptiness can conscitute a sort
of petversion
(f'iinyatii dr1tz) has alrea.dy been e.xplained by Nagarjuna
(XIU.8). This does
not mean that t he very conception of emptiness is
invalidated in the same way
as the conceptS of permaoence and momentariness would be
invalidated, The
reason ff!r this is thar the notions of permanence and substance
as wełl as of
niomentarioess arc not empirically grounded compared with
dependent aiising, non-substantiality, or emptiness. Both the Buddha and
Nagarjuna would
categorize the formcr under wrong thoughts (mithya
sa1?Jka/pa), while tbey
would consider the latter as right or appropriate thoughts
(saf!Jyak saf!Jka/pa,.
ka/pana yatra yojyate, XVll. 13), The verse thar follows
should be understood
in such a conteXC. This· indeed is the finał conclusion of
Nagarjuna in the
Kiirika (sec
XXVII.30).
16. Avidyamiine
grahe ca mithfii va sa1nyag eva va,
bh11ved viparyayaf? kasya bhavet kasyaviparyaya/i.
When grasping; wrongly or rightły, is not evident, for whom
woułd the.re
be perversion and for whom woułd chere be non-perversion?
MKV(P) p.466; MKV(V) p.204.EXAMINATION OP PERVERSLONS 32l
With grasping gone, whether it be for the right thing or the
wrong thing, the
enlightened one does not involved himself in any
substancialist thinking
rdating to perversion or non-perversion. This is the state
of the saint who has
anained freedom from grasping (anupiidaya vimuktt).
17. Na capi vipafftasya sarrzbhavanti viparyayaf?,
na capy t1vipantasya 1ambha11anti viparyayaf?.
Perver.sions do not occut to one who is ałready subjected to
pcrversion.
Pervcrsions do not occur to one who has not been subjected
to pcrvers1ons.
.
18. Na 11iparyasyamiint1$ya sarrzbhat1anti t1iparyayal/,
1111rJrfasva 111ayaf!Z kasya sa1(Zbha11anti viparyayaf?.
PerveISions do not occur to one who is being subjected to
pcrversioru.
Reflect on your own! To whom will the pervcrsions occur?
MKV(P) p.467: MKV(V) p.204.
Upon reaching sucha łevel of morał and intellectual
development (as referred
to in the previous verse), one does not get involved in
mecaphyskał spcculations such as whether pcrversions arise in one who is
a1ready afflicted by pcrversions, or not afflktcd , or is being afflicated. The
speculation thac is avoided
pertains not only to the past and the future buc also the
present. As such he
avoids the m·etaphysics discussed in Chapter Il. When
perveisioos themselves
are not per~eived as being substantial, how can one consider
a perverse person
as a substantial entity.
f9. Anutpannii katharrz nii1114 bhavi,yanti viparyayaf?,
11iparyayef11 a1atesu 11iparyayg-galfli? kuta/?.
How coułd there be non-ariscn pcn;ersi~ns? When perversions
are noc322 THE P!łllOSOPHY OFTHE MIDDLE W AY
bom, whencc can there be a person who is subjccted to
perversions?
MKV(P) pp.467-468; MKV(V) p.20).
Picking up the argument from the previous verse, Nigarjuna
is bere specifically
rejeccing the substantiałist ootions of perversions as well
as persons who arc
pervcrse. lf perversions are substancial or having
self-narure (s11abha11a), they
cannot be considered as arisen (utpanna). When they are
non-arisen or unborn
(ajata), there cannot be a person in whom these would arise,
for they cannot
serve as attribuces.
20. Na svato /iiyate blia11af? parato naiva jiyate,
na s11ataf? parataś ceti viparyaya-.gata/t kutal/.
An existent does not arise from itsełf, nor does it arise
from another, nor
both itsełfand other. Ifso, whence can tbere be a person who
is subject to
pcrversions?
MKVP) p.468; MKV(V) p.205.
This verse, which is not available in KumlirajTva's
translation, represents Uł application of the analysis ofsubstancial existence
(bhava) in Chapter I to the problems of a substantial petsoo or eotity. It is
aJmost identical with XXl.13.
21. A Jmi ca luci nityaf!Z ca sukhaf!Z ca yadi vidyate,
atmii ca luci nityaf'!l ca sukhaf!Z ca na 111paryayaf!.
If either the self, the pleasant, the permanent, or the
happy is evident,
then neither the self, the pleasant, the pcrmanent, nór the
happy constitutes a pcrversion.
MKV(P) p.468; MKV(V) p.205.
Nagarjuna began his examinacion of pcrversions (11iparyasa)
utilizing rhe sameEXAMJNATION OF PF.RVERSIONS 323
terms used br the Buddha at A 2.52. In the preseot verse, he
adopts a slightly
different terminology in referring to the perversions.
Instead of fubha and
aśubha, he uses the p~ of terms śuci and .aśuci. and instead
ofadukkha be has
sukha. This latter terminology was indeed utilized by che
interpreters of
Abrudharma when discussiog the perversions (see Akb p.286).
As such, it is a
elear indication that N:igarjuna was conversant withg the
early discourses as
much as he was familiar with the Abhidharma commenrarial
Hterature.
Nagarjuna's argument in the present verse coułd lead tp
misunderstanding
unless it is seen in the context of his previous sta.cements
abouc the perversions,
expecially at XXIII.20. lf the self, the pleasant, the
petmanenc, and the happy
arc evidenc as selfexistent entitzes, chen, indeed, they do
oot constitute perversions. Unfortunately, Inada's uanslation does not seem to
bring out this strong
sense of "exist" that Nagarjuna is implyicig here.
22. Niit11Jii ca fuci nitya?!I- ca -sukha'f!J ca yadi
vidyate,
anal1nii 'śucy anitya'f!J ca naiva du-1/Aha?!I- ca vidyate.
Ifneither the self, the p~easant, the permanent1 nor the
happy is notevident, chen neitbec the non-self, the unpleasant, the
impermanent, nor .
the $nffering would also be evident.
MKV(P) p.469; MKV(V) p.205 .
Having rejected the substanciał existc;nce of the four
perversions, Nagarjµna is
·here emphasiziog their relarivicy. 1-ł.owever, relativicy
in this context need not
be understood as applying in an identical way to all the
four perversions. As
pointed out earlier (see comments on XXIU.1), the four
perversioos deal with
rwo different categoties, the cognitive and che attirudinal.
The fact thar
anatman and anitya are conceptually related to atman and
nitya does_not mean
that the latter are cognitivcly bascd. They arc relative
only at the .cooceptual
leveł . On the contrary, fuci and aiuci as wełl as sukha and
du/?kha arc part of
experiern;e, even though chere coułd be confusioo regarding
theit identificadon.
23. Evaf'{Z nirudhyate 'vidya r1iparyaya-nirodhanat1
avidjiiya?!I- tJiruddhayaf'{Z sa'f!JSkaradya?!I-
nirudhyate.324 THE PHILOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE W/\Y
Thus, with the cessation of pcrversions, ignorance ceases.
When ignorance has ceased, the disposition.s, etc. come to cease.
ltfKV(P) p.469; M.KV(V) p.206.
The distinctioo betwcen the two kinds of perversions
meotiooed earJier
(XXlll.t ,2i) seems to be juscified by the.present
sratement. Wben the perversions cease, the immediate resułt wouJd be the
ccssatioo of ignorance (a11idyQ).
This would pcn.ain to the more cognitivc pcrversions (i and
iii). The cessation
of igoorancc would aJso mean the cessacion of the
perversions relatiog to
dispositions; that is, pcrversions ii and iv.
24. Yadi bhutal/ 111abha11ena klefal/ keiidd hi lllZJyflcit,
kfllh.11rt1 n'iima prg/:iiyeran kall 111abh'ii11art1
prahasyati.
lf, indeed, certain dcfile!bents ofsomeonc have come to bt:
un the basis
of sclf-naturc, how could they be rclinquished? Who cver
cou1d relinquish self-nature?.
25 . Y.ady abhutal/ svabhavena k/efal? kecidd hi lllZJyaciJ,
kathaf?Z fiiima pral:iiyeran ko 'sadbh'iiva?!J prahasyati.
lf, indced, ccnain dcfilcments of someooe havc not come to
be on the
basis of self-oature, how could they be relinquisbed? Who
ever could
rclinquish non-existence?
'
MKV(P) p.471; MKV(V) pp.206-207.
Nagarjuna's conclusion in this chapter is that the
dcfilemeots (kleśa) , whicb arc
the rcsults of the pcrvetsions discussed abovc, cannot be
elim.inated, and ,
therefoce, there could be no lalh'iigata, if the.se
defilements are łooked upon as
being either substanciaJ; i.e,, something that has come to
be (bhuta) havingEXAMINATION OF PERVERSIONS 32~
self-narure (s"Vabhiiva) or oon-substantial, i.e.,
sotnething that has not come to
be (abhuta) because of ics having no real nature
(asadbhava). In either case,
there can be no abandoning of defiłeroe.nts and hence the
achievement of the
state of tatliiigata.CHAPTER ·
TwEN1YFOUR
'
Examination of the Noble Truths
(Arya-satya-parzkfa)
1. Yadi śunjam ida'f{Z sqrvam rtc/ayo niirti na vyayql{,
caJun{iitn iirya-satyanam abhaPas te prasa/yate.
Ifall tbis is empty, then the.re exists no uprising and
ceasing. Theseimply
the non-existence of the four noble truths.
MA'V(P) p.475 ; MKV(V) p .209.
Nagarjuna's discussion of the four trutbs was an inevitable
consequence of his
analysis of perversions (Chaptet XX.lll) which, in its turo,
was occasioned by·a
need to explain the perspeccive of a tathagata
(ChapterXXII). The foUI uuths
refer to the problem of suffering, the subject matter of two
of the perversions,
namely, mistaking the unpleasant for the pleasant
(aśubheiubhan tt) and nonsuffecing for the suffering (aduf?khe dul{khan tt).
Verses 1-6 In the pr~ent chapter pose one major problem
faced by the Buddhist (or even by the non.Buddhist) in explaining suffering
(duf?kha) and,
therefore, the fout noble truths, when placed in the context
of "emptiness"
(fiinyata). Th~ important questions arc: Who are these
Buddhists (or nonBuddhists)? Why arc they .faced with such a problem? .The
answers to these
questions 'ate found in the Abhidharmakofa-bliii1ya of
Vasubandhu.
Vasubandhu refers to a theory proposed by some: "Thete
indeed is no feeling
of happiness" (nasty eva sukha vedana) and
"Evetything is suffering or unsatlsfactory" (duf?khaiva tu
sarva'f!Z)(Akb p.330). There is very Little doubt that t.his
interpretacion of the Buddha's teaching emerged with and was
continued until
modern times by thinkecs and scbolars belonging to the
Brahmanical tradition.
By ignoring a simple yet extremely imponant pronoun (namely,
idaf{Z, ''this"),
the Brahmanical interpreters transformed the Buddha's
teaching from an em·
pirical to an ab~ołutistic system. Thus, the Buddha's
scatement: saroam ida'f{Z
dul(khaf?' ("all this is suffering'') turns out to be
an unquaLified universal statement: saroa'f{Z duf?kha'f!Z ("everything i:s
suffcring''). Similarly, a specific statement such as sunyam idaf!'J saroa'f{Z
("all tłi.is is empty") turns out to be another
326EXAMlNATlON OF 1HE NOBLE Thurus 327
absolutisti<:: one, sunyaf(t sarvatp ("everything is
empry," a problematic not
noticed by Inada, p. 144). I
Threatened by such a problematic situation, the Buddhist
metaphysicians
wete driven to the extreme position of asse.tting absolute
forms of happiness,
when they insisted: "Happy feelings do indeed ex1st in
terms of unique
charactcr" ((IJty eva s-11alakfa11atal/ suk.ha vedanii,
Akb p.331}. Yet, realizłng
that the Buddha did oot prcsent the world as a ''bed
ofroses," they were compelled to admit that there. arc eonie experiences
that arc inherently unsatisfactory (S11abhti11enai11a duf?kha, ibid., p .329).
Thus, not realizing that this was all due to a Brahmanical
misreading of the
Buddha's discowses and assuming that there is a genuine
problem, the Buddhist metaphysicians carne to admit both suffering or
unsatisfactoriness
(duf?k.ha) and happiness (suk.ha) as substantially existing.
Instead ofcorrectiog
the Brałimanical misreading, they struggled for an
explanation:
When [the Buddha] declared: 'Ooe should perceive happy
feelings as suffering,' [i.e. , che perception of one who has ełiminated
the perversions,] both [hap~incss and suffering] arc
available
thercin. Happiness is inherently so, because there is
pleasantness..
However, eventually there is suffering, because ofits
chaoging and
impeananent nature. When that [feeling] is perceived as hap·
piness, it contributes to enlightenment, through its
enjoyment.
Wheo it is perceived as suffering. it leads to release, by
being non·
attached to it. (Akb p.331, Yad uktaf(t "sukh'ii
11edanii dul;khe ti
dra/(a11ye 1' li
ubhayaf(t tasyam asti. Sukhat11a?tt ca svabhavato
ma1ilipat11iit,
duf?ka?tJ ca paryaya~o 11ipari111imanitya-dharmat11iit.
Sit tu suk.ha.to
drfyamana buddhaya kalpate, tad asviidamz.t,
duf?khato drfyam1in'i!_ mokfaya k.alpate, tad 11alragyad
tli)
The substance·tt~rminology in the above passage should. make
it cleat as to
which Buddhist school wa5 presenting tbis·eicplanacion.
There seems to be no
quescion that it was authored by the Sarvastivadins. Thus,
it was their desire to
uphold the cónception of substance that made them
uncomfortable with the
notioo of "the empty" (śUnya) . The
substantialists were prepared to wrestle
with the conceptions of substance and causation and, as
shown earlier, they
produced substantialist theories of causatioo. However, they
could not do the
same with the concepcion. of "the empty" (śUnya) ,
even though "emptlness"
itself may be amenable to such substantia1ist
interpretations (see XXIV.14).
It is in order to highlight this problem that Nagatjuna
begins the chap.ter
with a reference to "the empty'' (funya, as in
y,adiśiinyam idaf(t saroaf(t) .rather
than to the abstract conception of "emptiness"
(ftinyalii}. In Nagarjuna's328 Tu1ł PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W/\Y
mind, to preserve the non-subscantialist and
non-absoJucistic standpoint of the
Buddha, what needs to be restored is "the empty"
rather chan "empciness.''
because the latter is dependent upon the former, whereas any
emphasis on the
latter could wipe out the former, as it happened in the case
of' the absolutists
and the substantialists. In presencing che metaphysicians
dilemma in this man·
ner, Nigarjuna was more concerned with the mistake of his
Buddhist counter·
pans than with the misreadings of the Buddhist texts by the
Brahamincal
chinkers. For this reason, he makes no reference to Such
misreadings as "sarva'f!t
sunya'f!t. , "
2. Parijna ca praliii'!'f!t ca bhli11an'ii .r'iikfikarma ca,
caturtiiim iirya-saJyiinam abha11iin nopapadyate.
In che absence of the four noble truchs, uoderstanding,
relinquishing,
cuJtivation, and reali~tion will not be appropriate.
MKV(P) p.477; ll'!KV(V) p.210.
Understanding (parijn'ii) pertains to the first of the four
noble truths, namely,
chat suffering exists. Rclinquishiog (prah'ii1'!a) refers to
the second, narody, the
cause of suffering, which is explained as craving (tr!t{ii).
Realization (i?ik#karma) applies to the third, namely, the state of freedom
from suffeting, which is
nirvana. Cultivation or practice (bha11ana) involves the
fourth, namely, the path
leadiog to the cessation of suffering.
3. Tad ab/iiiv'iin na vidyante caw'iiry iirya-pl>a/iini
ca,
phaliibhave phalasthii no na santi pratipannak'iif?.
In the absense of this [fourfold activity], the four noble
fruits would .not
be evident. In the absence of the fruitś, neither those who
have attained
the fruits nor those who have reached the·way [to ~uch
attainment] exist.
MKV(P) p.477: MKV(V) p.210..
· The non-absolutiscic standpoiot of eady Buddhism is
clearly embodjed in theEXAMlNATION OF THE NOBLE TRUTHS 329
doctrine of the four fru.its (arya-phtlla) . Even though
freedom without grasping
(anupadii vimuktz) is sometimes referred to as the one goal
(ek4y11na), yet a
deliberate attempt to assert degrees of attainments where
some arc considered
to be inferior to others is conspicuously absent, Like the
relay of chariots
(rathavinlta), one segment of the path is as imporcaat as
the other,
''dispassion" (vairagya) being one dominant attitude
permeating all segments.
This has an imporcant bearingon the concepcion of ttuth to
be discussed soon.
4. Saf!lgho
n'ihti na cet santi te 'f!tm puru!a-pudgaliif?,
abhaviit carya-satyanaf!I saddharmo 'pi na vidyate.
If the eight types of individuals do not exist, tbere will
be 110 congregation. From the non-existence of the noble trnchs, the true
doctcine would
ałso not be evident.
MKV(P) p.478; MKV(V) p.210.
Inada was probably assuming that cet refers to thought
(citta) when he
translaced pan of the first line as "the eight
aspiracions of men do not exist,"
whereas it could be more ~ppropriatdy read as a cooditional
particie.
The assoc.iation of the ttue doct.tine (sad-dharma)with the
fout noble truths
(tiry11-1a1y11) to a point whe:te the abse.oce of th,e
łatter implies the non-existenc~
of the former should nacurally raise questions regarding the
more popular
assigoment of doctrines to the var.ious sehools where the
four noble truths are
assign~d to the . so-called H~nayana with the superior
Mahayana having
somethiog more to offer, Such an assignroent. becomes really
questiooable
when a greac Mahayana thinker like Nagarjuna himself admits
of such a cor·
relation (XXIV.30).
This equation is also signlficant for another very important
reason: Dharma,
as ''teaching" also means a "statement" of
doctrine. Some modern linguistic
philosophers would prefer to use the term "truth"
primarily. in referring to
statements rather than to facts. Sad-dharma, .identified
with truth, seems to accommodate such a perspective. ·
S. Dharme casati sa'!l-ghe.ca kathaf'!l buddho bhavifyt#'i,
evaf!J. tnf!y api ratnani bru11lir1111f pratibadhase.330 THE
PH!LOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
6. funyaliif(Z phaltrsadbh'iivam adharmaf!l dharmam eva ca,
sarva-sa'{Z11ya1111har'iif!Jf ca laukikan pratibadhase.
Whcn the doctrinc and the coogregarion arc non-existent, how
can there
be an cnlightcncd one? Spcaking in this .manner about
cmptiness, you
contradict the thrce jewels, as wcll as the reality of the
fruits, both good
and bad, and all such worldly convenrions.
MKV(P) pp.478-489; MKV(V) 210-213.
At this point the metaphysidan brings up the notion
of"emp tiness" (1unydta).
For him, emptiness is a problem, not because of any othcr
reason, but because
it implies "the emp ty" (finya), and this latter
lcaves no room for substantial existence (sad-bh'iiva) of the fruits (artha) of
both good and bad as well as alJ the
worldly conventions-.
Inada's transłation of dharma and adharma as propeł and
improper acts is a
couective to his earlier rendering of these rwo cerms as
factor and non-factor at
Vlll.5. However, his rranslation of saf!J11ya11ahiira as
somcthing additional to
dharma and adharma can be quc:stioned in the light of the
use of vyavahara at
XVII.24, wherc a similar, but not idential, set of
categories (pu11y11-p'lipa,
"merit and demerit") is referred to as
vyavah'iira. Jndeed, this particular use of
the term 11y1111ah'iira ( = Illf!lV[lt) will throw much
light on an undc:rstandiog of
the distinction becween the ewo truths discussed at XXIV.8.
7. Atra bmmal; iunyatiiyfif(Z na tvaf(Z 11etsi prayojanam.,
iunyaliif!J iunyalllrthaf!J ca talli etJam. vihanyase.
We say that you do not comprehend the purpose of emptiness.
As such,
you ar-: tormcnted by emptiness and the meaning of
emptincss.
MKV(P) p.490; ltfKV(V) p.213.
Looking at the nacure of the objections raised by the
Buddhist metaphysiciaru
against the notion of "emptiness," Nigarjuna is
insisring chat they do not
undersund "the purpose of emptiness,"
(iunyat'iiyam. prayojanaftZ). Does rhis
mean chat "emptiness'' has a functional or pragmatic
vaJue, rather than beiogEXAMINATION OF THE NOBIJi TRllrHS 331
an absolute concept? Does it need to be substantiated by
"the empty," rather
than merely substantiating "the empty." Which is
more important, "the empty'' or "emptiness," or arc they of
equal importance? if "the empty" is considered to be important,
"emptiness" would be a merc idea with no grounding
in experience. Ifthe ''emptincss'' is looked upon as being
important, the empty
would ruro out to be a fabrication. If both arc considered to
be equaUy important, there could be circularity in re~oning based upon them.
However, ifthe
empty is considered to be the basis of experiencc, and
emptiness is derived
frorn chat cxperience, this Jatter could be provisional and
remain to be corrected in terms of future experience. In such a case, the
circularity involved in
arguing about tbem could be easily ełiminated. ln the next
three verses, Nigarjuna proceeds to provide very specific answers to most of
these questions.
8. Dve satye samupaśritya buddliiinfi'T{Z dharma deśana,
loka-.sa'f?Jvrli-satya'f?J ca.stttya?'p ca paramarthatal;.
The teaching of the doctrine by the Buddhas is based upon
two truths:
tnith relating to woddly convention and truth in terms of
ultimate fruit.
MKV(P) p.492; MKV(fl) lp.214.
This has turned out to be one of two most discussed verses
in Nagacjuna's
Kiin'/ca. Modern disquisitions on the conception of two
truths could perhaps fili
severa! substantiaJ volumes. Instead of plodding over
trodden ground, the preseot discussion will be confined to a comparison of the
conception of two tnlths
in early Budcłhism and the metaphysical vetsion presented by
the interpreters
of the Abhidharma, with a view to clacifying Nagarjuna's
position.
Nagarjuna's version will be ex:amined in the light of the
problems posed at the
beginning of the pi:esent chapter, as wełl as his refcrence
to woddly conventions
in the previous chapters.
In the Su1ta-nipat41 the Buddha condemned any arcempt to
uphold a view
(di!!ht) as the u!timate (paramaT?J)(Sn 796ff.). Refusing to
recognize any
knowledge of "things as they really.a.re," and
ma.king a more sober claim to
knowJedge of "things as they have come to be';
(yathabhuta), the Buddha was
reluctant to accept any notion ofparamattha as
"ultimate reality." Instead, he
claimed to know "the dependently ariseo"
(pa(iccasamuppanna) and, on that
basis.• formulaced the cooceptioo of ''dependent
arising" (pa{iccasamt1ppada).
In such a context, it was more n1eaningfuł for him to speak
ofattha (Sk. artha)332 THE PHJLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
and paramattha (Sk. paramartha) in the sense of fruit,
consequence, or result
( = phala, as in s'iimańfJa-phala, "the fruit of
reduseship"). Tbus, a good action is one that is fruitful
(attha-sa1?,Zhita) and a bad, unfruitfuł (an-atthasa?phita). ·
The Buddha also recognized that views about good and bad,
puricy and impurity, are in most cases relative convencions (Sn 878-894).
According to the
same text,'good (kusala) and bad (akusala) are conventions
that vary depending
upon contexts (sammutiyo puthujja, Sn 897). These are che
ways of the world
(loka), often charactecized as sam1nut1~ 11ohara (D 3.232)
or panfJatti (S
4.39-40). However, there is no indication that, sioce these
are relative conventions, the Buddha advocaced the transcendence of both good
and bad.
Having defined the good as the ftuitfuł, the Buddha
characterized the
ultimate good :as the ultimatelyfruitfu!. The termparamattha
was thus used to
refer to the "ultimate fruit'' rathet than ''u.ltimace
realicy." Sammuti and
paramattha are therefore oot two contrasting truths.
Theformer is a mixed bag,
while the latter represents the ultim.ate ideal. As a result
ofanaining nibbiina.
which is the complete eradication of lust (raga), hatred
(dosa), and confusion
(moha), the Buddha found himself enjoying an ultlmate fruit,
withour hurting
hirnself or others (na attantapo na parantapo, D 3.232).
Parama.ttha thus
becomes the mora.I ideal as reflected in the Buddha's own
att.ainment df
freedom and happiness.
The theory of dependent arising (pra!f.ccasamuppada)
expla.ining the
phenomena that arc dependently arisen (paficcasamuppanna)
thus accommodates the four truths as well as the two truths. All ttuths being
pragmatic,
there is herc no place for an "absolµte or ultimate
reality." The Buddha's
epistemological scandpoint does not allow for such
speculations.
This, howevec, was not the case with the metaphysicians. lt
is significant to
noce tbat when the Buddhist metaphysidans were faced with
the problem of
reconciling the four truths with their conception ,of
substance (s11abha11a), they
were compelled to fall back on the conception of two truths
(Akb p.33).
Howcver, their interpretation of the, two truths is totaHy
different from the
Buddha's and, in fact, seems to be contrary to it. Here
again, Vasubandhu is
our source.
As a Sauttantika metaphysician, Vasubandhu refers to the two
truths (satya)
and surreptitiously moves on to a discussion of existents
(sat): sa?fZvrtt~sat and
paramiirtha·sat (A,łb p.334). He tbeo provides two examples to
illustrate the
. nature of saf!lvrti-sat. The fust is a 'pot' (ghatą) .
There canoot be knowłedge of
a pot when it is broken ioto pieces. The second is water
(ambu). Water is not
knowa independent of the knowledge of "form"
(riJpa). Contrasted with these
two is knowłedge of theparamartha-sat. 'Materia! form'
(ritpa) is an example of
such existeoce. Io this case, wheo an object is broken down
inro its ułcimaceły
irreducible elemenrs, namely, ;uoms (paramii1'Ju), there is
knowłcdge of the
"unique narure" (s11abhava = s11a/ak!a1Ja?) of
such acoms. For the metaphysi-ExAMJNAT!ON OF IHE N OBIE TRUTHS 333
cian, that unique nature, whether it is called svabha11a qt
s11alakfa'la, has ałways
remained an epistemological enigma.
This interpretation of the two truths is totalły abseot
either in the earły
discourses or in the canonical Abhidharma. In the so-called
Theravada ttadition, it appears for the first time in the ooo-canonicaJ tcxts
(Mi/n 160), coouibutiog, as it did in the case of the Sarviiscivada and
Sautraocika schools, to
insoluble problems such as the duality of mind and matter.
Vasubandhu's
statement of the two uuths- .raf(lvrti and paramiirtha-in
the above contcxt,
where he was r~cordiog the interpretation of the Sauuiintika
view, remains in
sharp contrast to the spirit of the Buddha's teachlng on
"noo-substantialism."
This shouJd certainJy provide an interestiog background to
the analysis of
Nigarjuna's owo version of the two cruths.
9. Ye 'nayor na vijananti 11ibhagaf!I- .ratyayad11ayof?,
te tatt11af(l na
vijananti gambhiraf(l buddha-ślisane.
Those who do not un'derstand the distinction becween these
two truths do
not understand the profound troth embodied in the Buddha's
mcssagc.
MKV(P) p.494: MKV(V) p.215.
Niigarjuna is, of course, criticizing his opponents for not
understandiog the
Buddha's rnessage. If so, Niigarjuna's owo explanacion of
tbese two trud~
should not come anywhere close to the one discussed by
Vasubandhu, according to which the .raf(l11(ti reprcsents a merc designac:ion,
not an ultimate reality
or paramiirtha. It is an ootologkal speculatioo whkh is not
supported by the
Buddha's own conception of dependent arising.
10. Vyavah'llram anaśritya paramartho na defyate,
parav;.rrtham anagamya nirvaf!tlf!Z tiiidhigamyate.
Without relying upon convention, the ultimatc fruit is not
taught.
Without uoderstanding the: ultimate fruit, frecdom is not
attained.
MKV(P) p.494; MKV(V) p.216.THE PHILOSOPHY OFTHll MIDDLli WA
Y
Unless one is committed to upholding a theory of linguistic
or concepcual
transcendence of ultimate truth or reality, there seems to
be no reason to
restr:kt the use of the terms saift'11rti, vyavaharai or
prajńapti to refer primarily
to linguiscic convention. These terms cou1d and did stand
for any kind of conveotioń, whether it be llnguistic, social, political, mora!
, or religious. As menti.oned earlicr (sec comments on XXIV.8), all such
conventions are pragmacic
a.ud contextual. As such, trutb rclati.ng to them would also
be pragmatic and
C00textual.
The fact that in the two p.tevious instances when Nagarjuna
used the term
11ya11ah'{ira (XVll.24; _XXIV.6), he used it in the context
of a discussion of
morality, is of utmost significance. It is in this same
conteitt char the Buddha
used the ceon vohara (D 3.232 an(lriya-vohara == muiavada,
etc., and ariyavohara = musivlidii verama1fi, etc.) as well as the term
sammuti( = sa'f?1-vrtt~
Sn 897, 911). 'fhese, tberefore; arc the morał convencions
of the world (loka,
laukilut, sec XXIV.6) that are pragmatic, yet contextual.
Howevet, an ideał
mora! trutb caonot be suictly confined to a particular
context. It needs to be
mote universał and compteheosivc. This, indeed, was the
Kancian problem. If
Nagarjuoa was following the Buddha's solution to this
problem (see comments
on XXIV.7), he couJd not have ignored the pragmatic
component in the
universal morał principle formulated by the Buddha. A morał
law that is incapable of accommodating any exceptions can be uttcily useless
and even
hatrnful. As WilliamJames once remarked, "There is
ałways a pinch between
the ideał and the actual which can only be got through by
łeaving part of the
ideał bchind" ("Morał Philosophies and Morał
Philosophers," in Essays in
Prag1natiJm, ed. Albury Castell, New York: Hafner, 1948. p .
78). This is
because the ideał is an abstraction out of the coocrece and,
thetefore, needs to
be modified in the light of new concrete siruations.
Nagarjuna's statetnent "Without relying upon the
conventional, the
ultimate.fruit is not expressed" (vyavahara1n
aniiśn"tyaparamarlbo na deJyate),
expiains ooly a one-way relation, not a one-one
relationship. He is not saying:
"Without relying upon the ultimate fruit, the
conventional is not expressed."
Thus, he was rejecting a deontological morał principle cha•
provides an absolute source of all morał ideas with no concessions made for
individual or con-
. .
crete situations.
The second line emphasizes the need to have some
undetstanding of that
mora! principle before one could think of attaining freedom
(nir1iii11a).
However, it is possible to argue that this morał principle
issue:i out of the Buddha's attainment of nitvana, aod that without attai~g
nirvar,a one wiU noc be
in a position to understaod wbat chat principle means.
Neither the Buddha nor
Nagarjuna would advocate such a position. lf ooe wcre to
first attałą freedom
and then look for a morał ptinciple to account for ie, one
c.ould sometim~ end
up in wayward fand es, utop1as, aod ballucina:tions. for
this reasoo , .~oEXAMINAllON OFnrE NOBLE TRUTHS 335
underscanding of Jaf!Wrti (''worldly fruit, laukika artha)
and, depending upon
that, gaining some knowłedge ofparamartha ("ułtimate
fruit," lokuttara artha)
could serve as a guide for the attainment of freedom
(niniiit1a). In the
Thefigatha we come across an iostance where a disciple
claimed rhat he perceived che fauldess dhamma (addasat(' vira}a-f!l dhammat(')
and the path co
freedom, while she was still !eading a household life
(agarasmirp vasanfi 'ha11J).
Subsequently, she left the household life and attained
freedom from all
dcfiłcmenc.~ (Thig 97 ff.) . It is true that the Buddha
attained enlighcenment
and freedom by sheer accident. This is why he was reluccant
co·tecognize any
teachcr (see M 1.171). Yet, before preaching about ie.to co
the world , he spent
much time refleccing upon it, as a scientist continues to
verify a discovery he has
made befoce making ie public. Nagarjuna probably assumed
chat peopl.e could
have the beoefit ofthe Buddha's expcrience and not waste
time experimenting
with practices that ~he Buddha hirnself fouod to be fruitłess
(an-artha).
11. Vinaśayati
durdu(ii 1Unyalii manda'fTJedhasat(',
sarpo yatha
durgrmto vidya va du;prasadhita.
A wrongly perccived emptiness ruins a person of meager
intelligence. lt is
lilcc a snakc th:at is wrongly graspcd or knowledge that is
wrońgly
culrivared.
MA. 'V(P) p .495 ; .ł!KV(V) p.21 6.
Having explained the two truths, and establishing an
important relationship
between the conveotional and the ideał , the particular and
the universal.
Nagarjuna returns to the conception of "emptiness"
(Jiinyata) that gave rise to
the met.aphysicians' problems. The abstracr-conception of
emptincss (JUnyata,
reprcsenting an abstract noun}, derived from tbe experience
of "che cmpty"
(śunya), could be as destructive andfatal as a wrongly
grasped snake. How the·
emphasis oo the ideał and the universal to the utcer neglect
of the panicular ot
the situational has wrought hav~c can be known tl)r9~gh a
carcful and unbiased study of human bistory.
12. Ata.f ca pratyudii11rtta'!' cittarp deśayiluf!' munel/,
dharmatr1 mat11asytr dharmasya mandair duravagahalii-f!l.336
THE PHTLOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE WAY
Thus, the Sage's (the Buddha's) thought recoiled from
teachlng the doctńne having reflected upon the difficulty of undemanding the
doctrine
by peopłe of meager intelligence.
MKV(P) p.498: MKV(V) p.217.
This is a reference to the inddent related in the
"Oiscourse on the Noble
Qu~st" (AriyapariyeJana-sutta, M 1.167-168) where the
Buddba explains the
nature of his enlightenment as weU as the events immedia.rdy
preceding and
succeeding his attainment of enlighteomeor. Niigarjuna could
not have been
unawarc of the oature of the Buddha's eolighreoment as
described in this
discourse and also the reasons for the Buddha's reluctance
to preach the doc·
trine. The Buddha's statemcnt reads thus:
lt occurred to me monks: "This dhamma won by me is
deep, difficult to see, difficult to understaod, tranquil, excellent, beyond a
ptiori reasoning, subtle, intelligible to the learned. But
these
human bdngs arc delighting in obsessions (alaya)', delighted
by
obsessions, rejoicing in obsessions. So tbat for the human
beings
who are rejoicing in obsessions, delighted by obsessions and
rejoicing in obsessions, this were a mattec difficult to see, that is to say,
dependent arising. This too were a matter difficult to sec,
that
is to say, the appeasement of all dispositioos. the
renunciation of all
auachmeot, the waning of craving, the absence of lust,
cessation,
freedom. But ifI wete to tcach the dhamma and others were
not to
understand me, that would be a weariness to me. that would
be a
vexation to me.' (M 1.167)
This passage should dispel any doubts regarding the ·naru:re
ofthe Buddha's
reasons for his ini~ial reluctance co preach. le was noc
because of any intellectual
incapacity on the parr of the human beings, but mostly
because of the emotional difficulties chey would have in brcaking away frorn
the accepted theories
in which they have fouod safety and comfott, a sort of
'mooring' (alaya),
especiaHy in accepting a less absolutistic and fundament?Jly
non-substantialist
(anatta) philosophy and a way of life. As iodicated above,
the phrase used by
the Buddha to refer to the attitude of the human beings is
alaya-ratii
("delighcing in alaya," where alaya is derived
from 4 + Vli implying some
sort of mooring or obsession). Alaya represents an obsession
for not only the
pleasure~ of sense, but aJso ideas, dogmas, theories,
etc.EXAMINATION Of THE N OBI.E Th.UTHS
13. SUnyafiiyam
adhilaya??t yaf!t puna'1 kurute bha11an,
dofa-prasańgo
nasmakaf!t sa fiinye nopapadyate.
Furthermore, if you wece generate any obsession with regard
to emptiness, the accompanying error is not ours. Thac [obsession] is not
appropriate in the context of the empty.
MKV(P) pA99; MKV(V) p.21 7.
337
A.dhilaya has been rendered as "repeatedly
refuced" (Inada, p.147). However,
the term is more closely related co alaya (see commentary
onXXIV. 12) utilized
by the Buddha to refer to emotiooal attachment or obsession
for views. Nagarjuna seems to be saying .chat the metaphysicians are generally
fascinaced by
clear-cut and well-formed theories, abscract concepts, which
they rcvere as
divine, while the concrete percepts are looked \.\pon as
belonging to the brute
(see William James, Some Problems ofPhilosophy, p.34). This
paves che way
fot an extremely important statement by Nagarjuna regarding
śunyalii° a.ód
funya.
14. Sarvaf!t ca yujyate tasya śUnyata yasya yujyate,
sarvaf!t na
yujyate tasya fUnya??t yasya na yujyate.
Everything is pertinent for whom empriness is proper:
Everytbing is not pertinent for whorn the empty js not proper.
MKV(P) p.500; MKV(fl/ p.218.
This terse stacement of Nagarjuna, represencing an extremcły
valu_?.b~e assessment ofthe two concepcs of"emp tiness" (śunyata) and
"the empty" (funyaf!t),
can be comprehended only in t)le background of his previous
statement (X:XIV.13). Ie is a cricicism of the absołucistic aod substantiaJist
enterprise wherein
abstract concepts Jike "empciness" reccive a
divine status thercby becorning
compatibłe wich anything and everything in human experience,
like the
Platonie "forms". whcrcas any emphasis on the
concrete leaves everything .338 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
banging in the air. Plato's "forms" . Spinoza's
"substance", Vedanca "Brahman"
and Lao-czu's "Tao" - all these are fascinating
abstract concepts that fit in with
everything. Even if one does not have to movc on to the
ocher extrcme, as did
Hume with his "impressions". and the Sautrantikas
with tbeir "atoms"
(paramaf!u). any recognition givcn ro the concrcte, to
plwality, to the flux
tends to disrupt the sense ofsecurity one enjoys in a world
of abscractions. The
Sarvascivadins raised objections against ''the cmpty"
(fiinya)(XXIV. l-6) not
becaust there is an actual conflicc between the notion of
"the empty" and the
theory of four truths, but because the cooception of
"the empry" con.flicted
with their ootion of subsrance (s11abhava) which rhey were
holding on to with
great enthusiasm. The faule, as Nagarjuna points out in the
following verse, is
theirs.
15. Sa tva~ dofin
atmaniyan 11Jmasu paripatayan,
aśvam
evabhim"1ah sann aśam evasi 11ismrtah.
. . . .
You, acuibuting your own errors to us, ace like one who has
mounted his horse
and confused about it.
MKV(P) p.502; A1KV(V) p. 218.
As mentioned previously (sec commenrs on XXIV.14), the
problem faced by
the Buddhist metaphysicians was in regard to reconciling
"the empty" (funja)
with che four noble truths. This was because they were
explaining the four
truths in relation to the oorion of substance (svabhava) and
the notion of
subsrance d early cooflicted with the concept of "the
empty." lf Nagarjuna had
mercly reJied upon the abstra.cc concept of
"empciness'1' (fUnyafii), ignoring
"the cmpty" (fiinja) , the Buddhist metaphysicians
w<Śuh:ł not have run into
difficułti es, for "cmpciness," being the abstract
concept could easily be reconciled with the notioo of subscance. As such, the
p.coblem was created by the
metaphysicians when they emphasized the non-empirical
"substance'' to the
ncglect of the empirical phenomena, as is dearly evident
from Nagarjuna's
statement that follows. Nagarjuna was, therefore, reminding
them thac they
wece riding their owo horse wichout reaJizing it.
16. Svabha11'(itlyadi bhav'iina~ sad-bhavam anupaśyasi,
ahętu-pratyay'iin bhiva~ 1vam evaf?Z sati paiyasi.EXAM!NATION
OF THE NOBLE TRUTH·s
Ifyou pccceive che exisrence of the existents in terms
ofself-nature, then
you will also perceive these existents as non-causa!
conditions.
MKV(P) p.502: MKV(V} p.219.
339
For Nagarjuna, any existcnt is a causally conditioned
existcnt. Such an existent
is clearly imcompatible with a self-nature or substance, che
łat ter being permancnt and etefual by definition. This would mean that
Nagarjuna's conception
of "cmptioess" (funyata) does not partake of any
such characreriscics. Eveo
though "empriness" and "sclf-nature" are
borh abstractions from conctete experiences, Nagarjuna woułd continue to
maintaio the pcimacy ofsuch concrete
expericnces, which are "che empty," and insist
that "emptiness" is dependent
upon "the empty." while the meraphysicians would
consider sclf-nature to be
independent, thereby divorcing it from the concrete.
17. KJirya'f!l ca karar,at?J C111°11a kanara?'!'
kara'f!tlf?J krifit?J,
utp1ida'f!l ca nzrodhat?J ca phalaf!J ca pratilfiidhase;
You will also contradict [the norions of] effccc, cause,
agent, pctfoanance
of action, activity, arising, ceasing, as weU as fruit.
MKV(P) p.503: MKV(V} p.21 9,
How the recogrunon of self-narure (svabhava) contra4icts all
forms of empiricaJ knowledge, knowledge recognized by the Buddha relating to
dependent
arising, morał behavior (karma), and responsi biłity
(karma-phala), has already
been explained in detai l in the numerous chapters that
precede. Herc Nagarjuna is simply summarizing all his conclusions.
18. Yal; parfi1yasamu1p{idqf? funyat1it?J laf!' praca/qmahe,
s1i prajnaptir upadiiya pratipat sai1Ja madhyami.
We state tbat whate"er is dependent arising, tfult is
emptiness. Trun is
dependent upon convcntion. That itsclf is the middle path.
MKV(P) p.503; MKV(V) p.219.340 T"HE PHllOSOPHY OF TiłE
MIDDLE wAV
Thece see.ms to be no other staccmcnt of Nagacjuna more
conuovecsiaJ than
this one. An cntirc school of Chinese Buddhism emerged as a
rcsulc of the intcrprctatioo (or misintcrpretation) of this verse, [sec Hajime
Nakamura, "Tbc
Middle Way and the Empcincss View," Journal of Buddhist
Philosophy, ed.
Richard S. Y. Chi. (Indiana University, Bloomingtoo ,
Indiana,) l
(1984):81-1 ll].
In the first line, Nagarjuna is prescnting an equation:
Dependent arising
(pralityasamutpada) is "emptincss" (fUnyata).
Jnada's rendering of this line is
an improvement on Nakamura's, since che lactcr assumes that
herc there is a
reference to the evcnts (op. cit. , p.81), racher tban the
principle in terms of
whicb the events arc explained. As emphasizcd earlier,
"dependent arising"
and "emptiness" arc abstract concepts derived from
concretc empirical evcnts,
"the dcpendently arisen"
G"ralitya.ramutpanna) and "the cmpty" (1iinya)
respcctivcly. Unless this relationship between the abstract
and the concrete is
clearly obscrved , the incerpretacion of the second line of
the verse will remain
for evcr obscure , as scems to have happened since Nagarjuna
composed this
ueat1se.
The second line refers to the middle patb (madhyama
pratipat). The question is: In wbat way cao dependent arising and empciness,
which arc
synonymous, represent a middle path? The answer to this
question is in the
statement , sa prajnaptir upadiiya.
If this phrase wece to be transłated as, "It is a
provisional oame" (Inada,
p. 148) or as "That is a temporary dcsignation"
(Nakamura, p.81 ), which arc
standard uanslacions offered by most schołars, chen in che
explanacioo of
dependent arising and emptincss one will be committed either
to an extreme
form of oominalism or a sirniliarlyextremisc absolutism. Io
such a case, dependent arising or emptincss would either be a mere descripcion
wich no basis ln
cognitive expcricnce or it would be an cxperience that is
ineffabk. The former
alternacivc would conflict wich everything Nagarjuna was
trying to esrablish,
narody, the reality of atising and ceasing, of human
behavior, etc.
(XXIV16-l7). The latcer alternative would rendcr any
philosophic.al enterprise
meaninglcss and would uodermine Nagarjuna's asscrtioo ac
XXIV. 10.
Taking Jaf?Z11fh: 11ya11ah"iira, and prajiiapti as
synonyms, as was intended by
the Buddha bimself (D 3.202), and considering the contexts
in which Naga rjuna was using the terms saf?Zvrti and 11ya11ahara (XVlI.24;
XVTV.6,8)- namely, in relation to discussions ofworldly conventions, the most
importaot among
them being good and bad, dhartnalariharma (and this sense is
caprured by Inada' s own translatioo of saf?Zvrti and 11yavahara, see p. 146)-
it would be more
appropriate to chacacterize both "dependent
arising" and "empciness" as being
the universal truths rather chan ahso/uJe truths. This would
mean that bothEXAMJNATION OF THE N OBLE TutrrHS 341
saf!Jvrti (and, therefore, 11ya11ahara and prajflaptt) and
paramartha arc
"thought conscructions" founded on experience. As
such, chey are not absolutely rea.I or absolucely unreaJ. This, then , wou.ld
be the midd.le position
(v1adhyama pratipat). Tb is middle path could be adopced in
understanding all
forms of experience, whether they be Lioguistic, social,
political, ·rnora1 , or
religious. Whiłe a1J convencions, whether chey be
situational (saf!Zvrti) or ideał
(para11Jiirtha), are expłained in terms of dependent
arising, the conceptioo of
"the empty'' (sunya) eliminates che absolutistic sting
at the level of the situational , and "empciness" does so ac che
level of the uoiversał. (See comments on
XXlV.19 that foJłows.)
19. Apraliya-samutpanno dharmaf? kafcin na vidyate,
yasmat /(ZJmad aiunyo hi dharmal/-kafcin na vidyate.
A thing chat is not dependently arisen is not evident. For
thac reason, a
thing that is non-empty is indeed not evident.
MKV(P) p .505; MKV(V) p.220.
After clarifying the oaturc of che universal cooventions,
Nagarjuoa recurns to
the situational. for it was this lacter chat caused problems
for the metaphysicians. The metaphysicians realized that "the dependently
arisen"
(pra/ity(ZJamutpanna), so long as it is considered to be
"the empty'' (fiinya),
conflicted wich their nocion ofsubscance (svabhava).
Therefore, they were looking for "the dependencly arisen" that is not
empty of substance.
However, for Nag:trjuna, substance (svabhava) is not
dependently arisen
(XV.2). A thing that is not depcndently arisen is not
evidenr. Thcrefore, a
substance is also noc evident. A substance bcing non-empty,
the absence of a
substance woułd mean the absence of the non-empty (a-fUnya).
This is a elear and unequivocaJ denial of substance
(svabhava), of the nonempty (a-funya) and of the in-dependent
(a-prafftyasamutpanna). and. the
assertion of the non-subscantial (nil/-svabhiiva), the empty
(sunya) and the
dcpcndently arisen (praffty~amutpanna). In the hope of being
an absolule
non-ahsolutist, if someone were to propose chat both
alternatives- svabhava
and nil/svabhava, aiunya and Junya, aprafftyasamulpanna and
prafityaramul·
panna- are crue (or false), the empiricistN:igarjuna,
following che Buddha (Sn342 THE PHJLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
884) would insist that only one of these ałternacivcs is
crue (ekaf{l hisaccaT(J).
and not the second (na dutiya'!J). This means chat neither
the Buddha nor
Nagarjuna could be characterized as absolutiscs.
However, if the two alternatives were to be two metaphysical
altcrnatives,
then both the Buddha and Nagarjuna would be compelled to
ncgacc them.
Takco out of context, wabhiiva and nzf/11111bhii11a could
appear as mccaphysicaJ
alternacives. So could a!unya and filnya. Yct,
apralitya.samutpanna and
pralitya.samutpanna, as understood by the Buddha and
Nigarjuna, could not
be easily coo-.:ened to metaphysiall alceroatives. The
reasoo for this is that the
termpralityasamutpanna, beiog a past parcic~ple, does not
refer strictly to any one
tempora! experience, whcther it bclo_ngs to the past,
present or future, nor does
it traoscend ternporality altogether. Whil_e it has a
present connotacion, it is not
divorccd from the pasc. lt i~ . therefore, a term most
appropriately used to
describe the events perceived by the Buddha through his
"knowiedge of things
as they have come to be" (yathabhuta-fiii'la) . lt
refers to the events experiencep
in the so-całled "spedous present" (see comments
on XIX.4).
lt is this empiricistprajnapti that servcs as a corrcctive
to any propos3.I which
would turn either pralityasaf!Jutpada or śunyata into an
absolute truth , ineffable and a-tempora!. lt is, indeed, the philosophical
middle path referred co at
XXIV. 18 and the Buddha's discourse to Karyayana.
20, Yady afunyam idatp. saroam udayo na.Ili na vyayal;,
catu"Jam
iiryasalyiiniim abha11as te pra.rajyate.
Ifall this is non-cmpty, there exists no uprising and ceasing.
Thcsc imply
the non-cxistencc of the four noble truths.
MKV(P) pp.505-)06; MKV(V) p.220.
By rescuing the philosophical middle pach from aoy
absolutistic or substantialist incerpretation, Nagarjuna has sec the foundation
for the explanation of
the Buddha's doctrine of che four noble truths. The facts of
arising and ceasing
arc central to the fouc noble uuchs. lf tbere ever has been
a permanenc enticy,
an encity that is noc empty of a subsrance. then dependence
as wdl as the four
noble truths would have been falsified. No such entity has
been discovered so
far. Hence the four truths have remained valid.Ex.J\MINATION
Ol' THE NOBLE TRUTHS
21. Aprafftya-samutpannaf!Z kuto duł/khat!' bhavir.Jati,
anityam uktaf!J dul,khaf!J hi :at sviibhiivye na vidyate.
How can there be suffering that is not dependently arisen?
Suffedng has,
indeed, bccn described as impermanent. As such, it is not
evident in
tcuns ofself-nature.
MKV(P) p.506; MKV(V) p.220.
Nigarjuna is herc: returnjng to the interpretation of
suffering by the substantialist metaphysicans (sec comments on XXIV.l), who
held that suffering exists
in terms of self-nature. He is reminding che metaphysicians
that the Buddha's
conception of suffering is founded not onły on the idea of
dependent arising
but also the notion of impermanence. Io face, the perversion
regarding the notion of impermanence is aJso the cause of che perversion
regarding the concepcion of suffering (sec comments on XXIII. l).
22. Svabhiivalo vidyamanaf!' Ju°r!J puna!? samude1yate,
tas1'!iiit samudayo n'iisti funyafiif!''P,r,atibadhatal/.
How can that which is evident ih ~euns of self-nature risc
again?
Therefore, for one who contradicts cmptiness, there exists
no [conception
of] arising.
M.KV(P) p .506; M.KV(V) p .221.
Throughout the treatise, Nigarjuna was refusing to recognize
that the conception of self-nature or substance leaves any room for the
recognition of arising
and ccasing. This was contcary to the attempr on the part of
the metaphysicians. Nigarjuna is herc insisring that the conception of arising
(samudaya)
makes no sense at all when applied to self-oature.
Self-nature is not something that comes and goes. lt is oot
20 occutreoce. lt
is thece for ever. As such. it contradicts the theory of
emptiness which is intendcd to explain the occuuencc of cvents. Empciness, as
ment:iooed earlier
(XXIV. 18), is synonymous with "dependent
arising."344 THE PHJ(QSOPHY OF THE MIDDll WAY
23. Na nirodhaf? 1vabhii11l!11a Jato duf?khasya vidyate,
1vabhavaparya11a1thaniin nirodhaf!t pratt'badhiise.
The cessation ofsuffering that exists in terms ofself-nacure
is not evidenr.
You conttadict ccssation by adhering to a notion of
self-nature,
MKV(P) p.507; MKV(V) p. 221.
Just as the notion of self-nature conuadiccs the idea of
arising, it also renders
che conception of cessacion meaningless. Note the cmphasis
on the present participle, santa (left untranslated by lnada, p. 149), used in
relation to duf?kha,
implying "suffering that exists" in terms
ofself-nacure. The notion of exiscence
defined in this manner has already been criticized by
Nagarjuna (1.6). In effect
Nagarjuna is saying thac the nocioo of exiscence (sat) may
be compatible with
che conception of self-oature, but ie is not appropriate io
the context of "chat
which has come to be" (bhuta).
24. Svabhavye sati m'iirgasya bhavanii nopapadyate,
ath'iisau bh'iivyate m1irgaf? 1viibhavya1?J te na vidyate.
When self-narure exists, the cuJtivation of the path is not
appropriace.
And i.f che path wece to be cultivated, tben no self-nature
associated with
it [i.e., the path] woułd be evident.
M.KV(P) p. 507; MKV(V) p.221.
The priociple of sclf-nature (svii.bhiivya, noce the use of
the absuact noun instead of svabhiiva) explaios the way in which self-nature
funcri~ns . !hus, if
somechings are assumed co have self-nature , whac is assumed
is that chings happen on cheir own (svo bhavo) without the support of anything
else. la tbis
sense, chey arc independent. If rhe pach (marga) Jeading to
che ccssacion of suffcring (duf?kha) were to be explained in cerms of self-narure,
ie means chac che
way will work out on its own , wichouc any effort on the
part of one who is expecced to cultivate it. If one is expected ro cułtivate
the pach, it means chat one
has to make an effort. Ie does not happen
auromatically.EXAMINATION OF 'rHE NOBIE TRUTI-łS
25. Yadii dul/ka'fP samudayo nzrodhaś ca na 11idyate1
miirgo duf?kha-ntrodhatvat k.atamal/ prapayz'!yati.
When suffering as well as its arising and ceasing are not
evident, through
the cessation of suffering where will the path lead to?
MKV(P) p.508i MKV(V) p.221.
345
Insisting upon the recognition of self-nature, the
metaphysicians were compelłed to deny the fact ofsuffering as well as its
arising and ceasing. lt would,
therefore, be meaningless to speak of a path leading to the
cessation of suffering. Substancialist speculation leaves only two
ałternatives: either there is cessatióo of suffering or there is no cessation
of suffering. If the fact is that there is .
cessacion ofsuffedng (dul;kha-nirod/;atva). thtre is no room
for a path. It happeos in any case. If the fact is that there is no cessation
ofsuffering, then it is
meaningless to think of a path. FaraJism being the
consequence of both standpoints, the notion of a path Jeading to any goal is
rendered uttetly meaningless.
26. Svabhavenapatijnanaf!' yadi tasya puna!/ kathaf!',
parijnanaf!' nanu kila svabliiivaf? samava.rthitalf.
lfnon-undetstanding is due to self-nature, how can one come
to possess
understanding subsequendy. Is it not the case that
self-nature is fu:ed?
MKV(P) p .508; MKV(V) p.222.
lnada's rendering of nanu kzla svabhavaf? samavasthital/ as
"self.nature, in·
deed, oever re.mains fixed," seems to be based upon a
rnisuoderstaoding of
the impon of the particie nanu which simiJly means: "is
it not the case that,"
rather chan a simplc negacion. If self-oarure is something
that "never re·
ma.ins ftxed," what we ate presented here is the
so-całled Spinozao solution
to the problem ofsubstance. Nagarjuna was not willing to
accept such an interpretation of self-nature, for if self-narure were
understood as changing,
the whole purpose of formulating the notion ofself-natute by
the substan-346 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
tialists would be defeated. Therefore, he was simply asking
the question; "Is
it not the case that self-narure is fixed?" He is, io
fact, insiscing that if ie ~~
not fixcd, ie is not a self-nature. A change of subst.aoce
was, io the eyes of
Nagarjuna, a self-conuadiction.
Hence he argues: If there is any inabili:cy to understand
suffering because
such ioability is inherent, is through self-pacure, then
there can never be ics
underscand:ing. Something chat is inherently uoknowable can
oever be
subsequently known. Thiś is the most telliog criticism of
self-nacure
(wabha1111) as it is employed in the explanation of the path
to freedom
(niniiif!a).
27. Praha„a-iiikfatk.ara'!e bliii1111na caivam eva te,
ptmjłfiivan na yujyante catv'iiry apiphaliini ca.
As in the case of understanding, this [i.e., the explanation
in terms of
self-oature] is not proper in relation to the activities of
relinquishing,
realizing as well as cultivating. And so would the four
fruits be [improper).
MKV(P) p.509; MKV(V) p.222
An uoderscanding (parijłfii) of the nature of suffering
(duf?kha) is a necessary
prerequisite for its relinquishing , the reaJizaciotJ of
freedom , and che cultivation of the path leading to freedom. In the previous
verse, Nagarjuna ex·
plained how a belief in self-nature would create
difficulties in explaining
understanding (parijmi) or its absence (apanjfia).
The same di.fficulries are associated with the explanation
of the relinquishing
(praha1'!t1) of suffering, the realization (s'iikfatkara11a)
of frc~dom and che
cultivation (bhivanii) of the path. To highlight these
difficulties, Nagarjuna
concentratcs on the fruits or consequeoces (phala).
28.
Svabhaveniidhigata'l'(t yaJ phala'l'(t tal puna!? kathar(t,
śakya1'(t
samadhigantu1'(t sy'iit svabhava'l'(t parigrh11ataf?.
How could it be possible for a person, who upholds a theory
of self-Exł.MINATlON OF THE N OBT.Jl TRUTHS
nature, to realize a fruit that bas already becn realized
through self-·
nature?
MKV(P) p . ~10; MKV(VJ p.222 .
347
A person betieving in self-oatwe aJso admits that a fruit is
obtained by that
means. lf a fruit has not been achieved through sdf-nature
it can never be
achieved in any ocher way. lt is an either/or situation.
Accept it as occurring on
its own or it will never occur. This is a substantiatist
view of frcedom (nirvaf!a ,
which will be taken up for detailed treatment by Nigarjuna
later on). This, indeed, is a fatalistic or a deterministic explanation of
causality. Either the effect
exists in the cause or it does not (see discussion of artha
[ = phala) at 1.6).
29. Phaliibhave phalaslha no na stfntipralipannaktil?,
saf?i.gho nas# na
cet santi te '1tau puntfa-pudgaliil?.
In tbe absence of the fnilts, tbere arc neither tbose who
have attained the
fruits nor those who have reached the way [to sucb
attainmeot]. If the
eight types of indivjduals do not exists, there will be no
congregation.
30 . Abh'?ivac carya-saty'iinaf!1- sadt/harmo 'pi na
vidyate,
dharme casati .sa1{'ghe ca kathl#(J- buddho bhavi$yati.
From the non-existeoce of the noble truths, the truc
doctrine would also
not be evident. In tbe absence of tbe doctrine and the
congregation, how
can there be an enlightened one?
MKV(P) p .)10; MKV(V) p.222.
Having shown that the explanation of the attainment of the
frui~ (phala) of
life is rendered i mpossible or meaningless by the adhetence
to the ootioo of
self-nature, Nagarjuna rurns the table on the
metaphysiciąns, showing them
how the denial of emptiness (iiinyatii), rather thąn itS
assertion, leads to a
denjaJ of all that they wece trying to explain.348 THE
PHILOSOPHY Ol' i HE MIDDLE WAY
31. Aprafilfiipi bodh~ ca la11a buddhaf? prasafyate,
aprafi1yapi buddhatiJ ca ta11a bodhif? pra.JajytTte.
Your [conceprion of the] enlightened one implies an
independent
enligbtenment. Also, your [conception of] enlightenment
implies an independent 'enlighcened one.
MKV(P) p.510; MKV(V) p.223.
Explained in terms ofself-narure, the enli~htened one would
be so irrcspeccive
of conditions (apratyaya). Similarly, enl]ghrenment would be
achieved irrespective of whether it is a person who makes an effort or not.
This substantialist cxplanation ofenlightenment and the eolightened one, in
terms chat arc
strictly naturalistic or deterministic, wou ld rendet the
activities of the one seeking enlighteoment and freedom utterly meaningless.
32. Yaf cabuddaf? svabhavena sa bodhaya gha{ann api,
na
bodhi.sat111a-caryayfi1!1 bodhi1!1 te 'dhigamifytTti.
Wh~oevet is by sclf-nature unenlightened, even though he
were to contend with enlightcnment, woold not attain enlightenment thtough a
career off a bodhlsattva.
MKV{P) p . 511~ MKV(V) p.223.
This is the one and only time Nagarjuna, the so-callcd pauon
of Mahayaoa,
rcfcrs to the way (caryQ) of a bodhi.sall11a. Yet, the kind
of criticism he is prcsenting herc offers no consolacion to those who accept
cercain docrrines of
popular Mahayana. Any substaotiaJist theory, according to
Nagarjuna's view,
militates against the ca.(eer ofa bodhisattva.
To uphold che view chat a person is by narure u ncnlightencd
is taotamount
to saying chat he can never attain the fruit of
eolighteruncnt and frecdom by
excrting himself. Sir:Qiłarly, to assert che view chat a
person is by narure
enlighccncd, is a potential buddha, or possesses a
bodht~citta, makes the attainmcot of enłightenm.ent meaningłess (XXIV.28) or
impossible.EXAMINATION OF THE N OBLE TRUTHS
This, indeed. is reminiscient of the long drawn controvcrsy
between the Sar4
vastivadins and the Sautrantikas regarding tbe oarure as wcU
as the functioning
of good (kusa/a = dharma) or bad (akusala = adharma)
thoughts (citta). The
metaphysical problems generated by an extremist analysis in
rclation to
phenomena in generał have been explained in Chapters I and
Il. The selfsame
metaphysical problems appeared in the explanatioo of moraJ
phenomeoa. The
Sarvastivada-Sautrantika controversy relating to the
"seed,s that arc of good
nature" (kusa/a-dharma-bija) reflects their iovolvement
in sucb mt"taphysical
1SSUCS.
The atomiscic (and, therefore, noo-empirical) analysis of
thought (citta) led
the metaphysicians to assume a sharp distinction not ooly
becween good
thoughts (kusala-cilta) and bad cho_ughts (t1kusala~citta),
but also betw~eo iodividual moments of thought in cach series. whether they be
of good thoughts
or bad thoughcs. As such, severa] questions carne to be
raised: How does one
good .thought moment givc risc to another similar thought
mąment? How can
two different thought moments, one which is good and the
ocher which is bad,
co-exist in one moment, especially when they are ·distinct
as light and darkness
(7iloka-Jamas, see Adv p .170)? If they cannot co-exist, how
can a bad thought
moment give rise to or be followed by a good thought? While
the Sarvascivadins urilized the cooceprions ofprapti and aprapli to explain the
manner of their occurrence, the Sautrantikas employed the notion ofseed (liija)
to
elucidate these problems.
The substantialist Sarvastivadins, who adhered to a oocion
of self-nature
(svabhava) were compdled to maintain thac cach vari~ry of
thought has its
own-nature, Yet, when they were called upon to explain the
occurrencc or nonoccurrence ofgood or bad choughts in an iodividual person's
stream of chought
(sa1{Jtana). they asswned that the non-attainment (apriiplt)
of one kind of
thought could make room for the accainmeot (pr7ipti) of
another kind . The
Sautrantikas, rejecting the noc:ion ofself-nature,
emphasized the idea of potentiality (Jaktt) exiscing in che form of seed
(bija). Thus, when a good thought
moment occurs, the bad tbought moment can remain latent
without
manifesc.ing itself. Tbus, we are left with two
potencialicies, one manifescing
itself when the other is not. The terms iak11: bija, and
11iisafla werc all
employed to cefer to such pocenciality.
A discioction carne to be admitted not ooly between good
(kusa/a) and bad
(akwala), but also among the good seeds themselves. Thus,
chere arc defiled
good secds (sairava-kusala-blja) ·and non-defilcd good seeds
(aniifrave-kusala-
/iija), the former accou.oting for worldly goodness and the
latter leading to
frccdom (11irva11a). These sceds werc considered to be
extrcmely subtłe
(susuk/ma) and remain uocor~pted or undestroyed (na
ramudghiila). They
were compared co gołd (kaflcana). A popular stacemenc runs
thus:350 THE PHllOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
I perceive his exuemely subtle seed of release lik~ a seam
of gold
coocealed in a deft ofelemeotal rocks. (Mo,~,fa-bzjam ahaf?I
hy asya
S1'st1k1mam upa/alqaye, dhtitu-p1i1fi'!a-vi11are niliam żva
kaflcanam,
Sakv p. 644, see alsoJaini, Ad11 Introduction, p.116.)
Even though this substantialist view is attributed to tłie
Buddha himself (see
Jaini, loc cit.) on the basis of the Buddha's statement
tigarding the "luminous
thought" (pabh(IJsar(,lf?Z citlaf?Z), we have already
provided evidence to the contrary (see Inuoduction), where thought is comp;ued
with "gold-ore" (iiita-!'Upa)
rather thao with gołd (suva1111a). As such, oeither..cJ.le
theory of the "seeds of
celease" (moksa-bija) nor of the "originally pure
mind" (prakrti-prabhtisvaracżtta), which is a predecessor, the Mahayana
notion of a bodhi-citta, can be
reconciled with the Buddha's conception of\
non-substanciality (anatta) or
Nagarjuna's view of "emptiness (śunyafii) . The present
statement of Nagarjuna is a elear rejection of the substantialist standpoiot of
the later interpreters,
which represents a recurrent desire to go back to a
pn'ttzordial source.
33. Na ca dharmam adharmaf?Z va kaścijjiitu kan/yatz~
kim afunyasya /<.arta11ya7(t svab6aval/ knyate na hi.
No one will, indeed, do good or bad. What could the
non-empty do?
foc, self-nature does not perform.
M.KV(P) p.511 ; MKV(v,i p.223.
Inada, once again. renders the terms dharma and adhamta as
factoJs and non~
factors of experience, thereby reacling moce ontołogy than
axiology inco the
statement of Nagarjuna. Ą substantialist ioterpretation of
good and bad a.llows
no room for their cultivation or performance. If someone; is
good in terms of
self-nature, he does not have to 'perform the good; ir is
simply there. SimiJarly
with bad. Self-nature (svabhava) implies absolute existence
(sad-bhava), not
occurrcnce (sa'f(tbhava, XXIV.22).
34. Vinii dh11rmam 11dhPrmll'f!Z ca pha/af!> pi t411fl
vidyate,
dhar~dharma-nimillaf!J "Ca pha"1'f(t lava na
vżdyale.EXA.MINATION OF THE N OBLE TRUTHS
As for you, the fruit would be evident even without good or
bad. Tbis
means that for you a fruit occasioned by good and bad would
not be evident.
MKV(P) p.512 ; MKV(V) p.223 .
351
The consequence of upholding a nocion ofself-narure in morał
philosophy are
explicated herc. If good and bad were to be explained in
terms of self-nature or
substance, then thete would be goodness and badness "in
themselves." These
woułd always be existent. A fruit, if it were ~o arise at
aU. from a good action
will ahvays be good and. as such , chere would be identity
of cause and effect
(sec Chapcer I). If a good action were to lead to a bad
consequence, ie wouJd
not matter at all, as ie is assumed to be the case with, for
example, "good-wiU."
This ootion of inrriosic good or bad would render the
concept of a cause (nimitta) almost meaningless.
35.
Dharmadharma-nimittatrt va yadi le vidyate phala.1?1,
dharmadharma-sa1nutpannam
aiunya1{' te ka1ha1{' phalatrt.
If, on the contrary, a fruit occasioned by good or bad is
evidcnt to you1
how can you maintain the fruit that has arisen from good or
bad to be [at
the samctimeJ non-empty?
J.1.KV(P) p.512; MKV(V) p.223 .
Thus, Nagarjuna insists that rnorał discourse and a
subsrancialist world-view arc
incompatible. If something is good by nacure, good in terms
of self-narure,
good in itself, chen it musc be always good. Ir cannot be
otherwise. Such an absolutistic theory will fail to accommodate some individual
or panicular siruations tbat arc in conflict with the theory, but which would
cectaioly be valid in
certain concexrs. This was a serious defect in the
absolutistic cheory. as explain·
ed by Nagarjuna in the following verse.
36. Sarva-sa1{'vyt111ah'iir'iif?1f ca laukiliiin
pratibiidha.re,
yaJ prafttyasamutp'iida-funyaliif!J pratibadhase.3~2 THE
PHlLOSOPHY OF TH E M IDOLE WAY
You will contradict all the worldly conventions when you
contradict the
empciness associated with dependent arising.
MKV(P) p.)13; A-fKV(V) p .224.
This, ooce again, bighlights the significant rełationship
betwcen worldly conventions, that arc siruatiooal or contexrual and the
prindple of dependent arising which, as explained earlier, is a univeĆsal. The
only way che universal can
accommodate the siruational is when the universal is not
looked upon as corresponding co an "ultimace reaLiry." The
subsrantialists who assumed that there
is an ultimace reaJiry, rherefore, were faced wich all the
insoluable mecaphysics.
Thus the actual function of emptiness is the ełiminarion of
this substancialist
sring (see commcnts on XXIV.18).
37. Na kartavya'f!J. bhavet ki7{1-cit anarabdha bhavet
kriyii,
karakal? sjiid akuniiirtalJ JUnyataf?Z pratibadhataf?.
For one who contradicts emptiness thece would be nothing
that ought to
be done; accivity would be uninitiated and an agent would be
nonacnng.
MKV(P) p.513; MKV(V) p.224.
The unfortunate consequences of upholding a subsrantialist
theory and denying empciness arc listed herc. lncerestingly, all of them
percain co human
behavior and moral responsibiliry. This says much abouc che
concerns of
Nagarjuna, who by popular acclaim is more a logician
primarily concerned with
language and truch and therefore with ułcimate reality ,
rather tban a mora!
philosopher iotecesred in axiołogy and, for thar reason,
emphasizing the conception of "u łtimate fruit." He is supposed to
have scorned aoy specułation
about human behavior (karma), wbat human behavior oughr ro
be (kartavya),
and who a responsibile human agent (kurvarJa) is.
In brief, a substantialist view leads co a denial of ~he
human element fu ncrional in this w.orłd, an element that is generally
described as "disposition"
(saT(lskara). Not only does it negate the world condicioned
by human disposirions (i.e., the saT(l.!krta), ie also denies any activiry and
creativiry in the natura!
world (sec XXIV.38 that follows).EXAMINATION OFTH!; NOBLE
TRUTH~
38. Afiitam aniruddhartt ca ku{astha11} ca bhavi!yati,
vicitr'iibhir avasthabhz}f svabhave rahita11} }agat.
In a substantialist view, the universe will be unborn,
oon-ceased, remainlng immutable and devoid of variegated states.
MKV(P) p.513; MKV(V) p.224 .
353
The assumption of a substance (svabhava) would depri.ve the
natura! world , the
world of dependent arising, of all che variety (vicitra) and
freshness and leave it
sterile and unproduccive. This, indeed, is the Buddha's
criticism of erernalism
(sassata-diffht) when he maintained t hat according to rhis
view the self and the
world are sterile, immovable, and remaining stable like a
pillar," (D J.14; S
3.202, 21 1, etc„ yatha sassato atta ca loko ca vanjho
ku{tiffho esikauhayz't{hito):
39.
Asarnpraptasya ca praptir duf?kha-paryanta-karma ca,
sarva-kleśa-praha17a11J. ca yady afunya11J. na vidyate.
If the non-empty [is evident], then reaching up to what has
not been
reached , the act oft'crminating suffeńng as well as the
reunquishing ofall
defilemenrs would not be evident.
MKV(P) p .51); MKV(V) p.225.
The substantialist view would oot onły negate the world
decermined by human
dispositions (sa11}skrta) and che naruraJ world of dependent
arising
(prafitysamutpanna), but also the ideał world , che world of
freedom. Niryana
would remain inexplicabłe in the context of a substantialisc
world-view. This is
che subject maccer of the next chapcer. Before proceeding to
explain freedom,
Nagarjuna has a quotation from the Buddha (XXIV.40).
40. Yaft prafityasamutpadarrt P<lśyatida'f!l sa paśyati,
dul?kha11} sa1n.udaya1(l caiva nirodha'f?J margam eva ca.354
THE PHJLOSOPHYOFTHE MIDDLE WAY
Whoevcr pcrceives dependent arising also pcrceives
suffering, its arising,
its ceasing and the path (łeading to its ceasing].
MKV(P) p.515; MKV(V) p.225.
The Buddha maintained chat he who pcrceives dependenc arising
pcrceivcs the
dhamma (M 1.190·191; Chung 7.2 [Tairho l.467a}. Perceiving
dependent aris·
ing is not mcrely perceiving "things as they have come
co be" (yath'iibhuta), but
also seeing how a human being placed in such a context of
dependent arising
experiences suffering (dul/kha); what causes such suffering;
what kind of
freedom can be attained and what the path is that leads to
the attainmcnt of
freedom and cmancipacion. Dependent arising and the four
noble truths arc,
therefoce, the foundations on which the whole edifice called
Buddhism is built.
Any school of Buddhism chat refuses to recognizc the
centralicy of these doc·
uines would loose its claim to be a legitimate pan of that
tradition. These con·
stitute the truths chat Nigarjuna was attemptiog to
explicatc in che pcesent
chapter.CHAPTER
TwEN1YFIVE
Examination of Freedom
(Nirvar;,a~partk!ti)
l. Yadi śunyam idarp. sarvam udayo niistina vy4Jal/,
praha„ad va nirodhad va karya nirvaf!am i!ya.te.
If all tłUs is empty, there eństs neithec arising nor ceasing.
[As such,]
through the relinquishing and ceasing of what does one
expect freedom?
MKV(P) p.'.>19; MKV(V) p.227.
Even though some·of the problems rdating to freedom
(nittlaf'!a) have al.ready
been discussed in the context ofa tathagata (Chapter XXII)
and the four noble
truths (Chapter XXIV), Naga.rjuna singles out this topie for
further analysis,
especially in view of certain grave misconceptions that
emerged as a resuJt of a
substantialist world-view. Without making any attempt to
determine what
these metaphysical views were, many a scholar has plung.ed
himselfinro assertions about Nagarjuna's coaception offreedom and produced
views that arc no
less metaphysical than those rejected by Nagaijuna.
The present verse 6cplains the di.fficulties the metaphysicians,
who acceptcd
substantial phenomena, cxpeticnced when they attempted to
elucidate
freedom. While the ptcvious chapter dealt with the problems
the substantialists faced when they accepted a notion ofself-nature and tried
to accountfor
che four noble t.ruths, especially the empirical fact of
sliffering (duf?kha). the
present context Nagarjuna is primacily concerned with the
question offreedom
from suffering. The substantialist dilemma herc would be:
How can freedom
(niniiin.a) be explained, if the conception of empciness is
ucilized not only to
explain the empiricaJ fact of~suffering but also to
elucidate ninii'!a) which,
even though described as the cessation ofsufferiog
(du~kha-nirodha), was also
the uJtimace or absoluce reality.
After deoying any substance (111aóhava) in the conventiona!
or the contextuał
(11yav11hara). if Nagarjuna had not proceeded to extend that
denial to the ideał
(p11ramiirtha), the substantialist could have remained
silen.t. Hbwever, when
Nagarjuna univetsaJ.ized "the empty" (i#njll) by
saying "aJJ this is empty" (IllT:
3)5356 THE PHJtOSOPHY OFTHE MIDDLE WAY
vam idaf(J fUnyatrJ)- and that included the substantialiscs'
conception of
"ultimate reality" (poramiirtha) understood in
various ways, either as "atomk
reality" (parama11u) or the "seed of rdease"
(rnok,a-liija) or the "originally
pure thought" (prakrt1:prabhasvarr1-citta)(see
XXIV.32)-he was rhreatening
the very foundation of substantialist metaphysics. In the
next cwenty-three
verses, Nagarjuna proceeds to demolish that foundation.
2. Yady af unyam z'da17J saroam udayo nfisti na vyayaf!,
prahar(iid va nirodhiid va kasya ntNiiit?am l!Jdle.
'
lfall this is non-empty, thete exists neithecarising nor
ceasing, [As such,]
through relinquisrung and ceasing of what does one expect
freedom?
MKV(P) p.521; MKV(V) p.227.
As in the previous chapter, it is because of his preference
for an empiricai explanation of things in terms of arising and ce~ing
(udaya.vyaya) _that Nagarjuna is not willing to accept a mctaphysical
substaQce. Hence his argument that
relinquishing (praha11a) a.nd ceasing (nirodha) are
meaningless in the contcxt
of the ''non-empty" (afiinya). Thus, for Nagarjuna, the
non-cmpiricaJ view is
the one expressed in the form , "All this is non-empty
(sarvam idam afUnyatrJ) ,
rather chan .the view presented as "AU this is
empty" (sarv(lm ida?(l fUn.:;af!l) . If,
on the i:ontrary , the substanti.µists were to accept the
empirical phenomena to
be empty, but noc.ni rvaf!a, srill Nagarjuna could ask the
question: lf nif'tl(Zf!a is
a permaoenr and eternal substance, why talk of arising and
ceasing, relin•
quishing and abandoning. for suffering (duf?kha) or
defilements (kiesa) that
need to be relinquished actually do not affect the
originally pure existence?
For Nagarjuna and the Buddha, neither the empirical events
nor the
ułtimate fruit wece substantial. Neither samsara nor nirvana
were absolute in
. . '
any sense. As such, what Nagarjuna is presenting is not
different from the cmpiricaJ view of bondage and freedom explained in the
Buddha's discourse.ro
Katyayana. ·
3. Aprahz„am asampraptam anucchinnam aś?i:fvata?(l,
aniruddham anutpannam etan nirva„am ucyate.EXAMINA.1.lON OF
FREEDOM
Uruelinquished, not reached, unannihilated, non-eternal,
noń-ceased
and non-arisen - this is called freedom.
MKV(P} p.52 l i MKV(V) p.228 .
357
Having rejected a permanent and eternal substance which, as
explained earlier
(XXIV.38), "is unboro, unceased, remaining immovable
and devoid of
variegatecl _situations," if Nagacjuna were ro explain
freedom jn almost idenrial
terms, his philosophy would not be any differen.c from those
of his substancialist opponents. Furthermore, it is the subscantialists
chemselves who considered freedom (nirvaf!a) as well as the non-defiled good
·seeds (atiiiśra11akusalt:1-btja) oc the seeds of release (mo~a-bija) to be
subde (susuk~ma) and
uncorrupted or undescroyed (nasamudghata)(see XXIV.32). This
leaves ·the interpreter of the present verse with only one escape-route,
namely, to consider
the six negations presented hece to be simple oegations of
metaphysical existence (sat) or its associate, non-existence (asat).
How relinquishing (praha11a) becomes probłematic if one
we.re to accepc a
self-nature (Jvabhava) has been explained at XiflV.27. The
substantialists, as
mentioned in the ruscussion of XXN.32, were left with two
distinct selfnatures: the good (kusa/a) and the bad (akwala). 'f.heit problem
was how any
one of them, being permanent and eternal, could be
relinquished.
If it is assumed that the "seed of release" (moh.a·biJ~)
is subtle.and incorruptible and produces freedom (niniiit?a) as the
"ultimate fruit" (parama artha or
phala), Nagarjuna's refutation óf ie is dearly stated at
XXIV.28. He explained
how the reaching (sa~priipti = sama'dhigamana) ofa fru•it
(phalr;) is made impossible by the recognitioo of a perPianent and
iocorrupcible selfcnarure. Thus,
when freedom (nirva11a) is explained as rcqlinquishing
(prahat1a) and reaching
(sa1!Jpraptz), these should not be understood in a
substantialist way. I/ they
were .ro understood, the óoly way to explain the empirical
concepcion of
freedom is by negating them. Thus, in freedom there is
"oo r.hing1' (na
kaścit)(XXV . 24) - a thing understood as being substantial
or haviog sel:fnarure-that is either relinquished (prahT11a) or reached
(Ja1!Jprapta).
The other four negations were distussed in relation to the
Dedicacory Verses
(as part of the eighr negations). There roo, it was pointed
our tłiat che eighc
negations-·were intended to elim.inace the metaphysical
nocions of existence
(astilva) and
non-existence (naJtitva). The same could be said of the two
couplets in the present verse: anucchinna?!J/afiifvatatrJ
and aniruddhaf?l/anuI ·
pannartz.
Thus. the sixfold acriviry- rclinquishing, reaching,
interruption, remaining.
constant, ceasing and arising - as explained by the
metpphysicians need to be
negated beforc an empiricist theory could cmerge. Such
mecaphysical explana-358 T HE PHlLOSOPliYOFTHE MIDDLE WAY
tions can easily be abandoned if their foundations, namely.
the metaphysical
concepts of substantial existence (sat or t:!Jtit'lla,
bha11a oc s11abha11a) and
nihilistic non-existence (a.rat or nastit11a, abh'ii11a or
parabh'iiva), wece to be
given ~p. This, indeed, is the task that Nigarjuna sers up
for himself in the
following verses.
4. Bhavas t'iivan na riinia'!af!' jara-mara„a--lak!a1Ja7?1,
praJajet?isti
bhavo hi najfl1'a-maraf!af!' virfi.
Freedom, as a matter of fact. is not cxistence, for if it
were, it would
follow that it has the characteristics ofdecay and death.
Indeed, there is
no existence without decay and death.
MKV(P) p . 524~ M.k"V(V) p.229.
Inada ~es bhava in the present contextas the nature
ofordinaty existence. Instead, the term is better explained as a reference to
metaphysical existence
(a.rlitt1a), as has been the case with Naprjuna (see
especially, XXl .15-16; also
XXV.10). The metaphysicians who admitted bliava or rvabhava
as eternal and
perrnanent entities nevcr attempted. an empirkal
justification of tbeSe eotities.
They seem to have assumed that these are known through
"ominscience" (stlf'tlt1-
J°fł4f11a) . Nigarjuna, realizing the Buddha's attitude
toward such knowledgcclaims (sec discussion of Sabba-sutta at IX.3) and,
thcrefore, making no
refcrcncc to sucb knowledge at all in the present text,
simply noted the implkations of rhls metaphysical speculation and iosisted that
such existence (bhava,
s11abhi11a) is invariably associated with charactcristics
(/a/qa„a) , Uke decay and
death (jtll''ii-maraf!a). Thus, freedom will not includc
frecdom from decay and
death and this would contradict the Buddha's claim that he
is freed from the
recurrent cyde of births and deaths. On the contrary, if the
mctaphysicians insis.ted that there is no invariable connection between
existence (bhava) and
characterisiics (la/qaf!4), then they <.:ould claim that
after p11rinirvar1a a freed
peoon can retain the eternal existence and drop the
characteristics. N:igarjuna was
qui~e certain that this is an extension of the metaphysical
position and is in conflict with the non-substantialist teachings of the Buddha
(sec X:XV.17).EixAMINATION OF fREBDOM
5. Bhii11aś ca yadi nirvaf!tlf!I ni111ii1'Jtlf!I
Jt1f!IJRrlt1f!I bht111et,
niiJaf!lskrto hi vidyate bha11al/ k11acana Raścana.
Morcovcr, iffrccdom wcre to be cxistencc, thco &cedom
would be condicioned. Yct, an existence that is unconditioncd is not evidcnt
anywbere.
MKV(P) p.526; MKV(v) p.230.
359
In rendering the terms Jaf!JSkrta and t1.It1f!llkrta as
"condirioned'' and the "uoconditioned" rcspectively, we havc, in
the present cootcxt, tried to ret.a.in the
interpretation of the metaphysicians, for it is this
panicuJar interpretation that
is being questioncd by Nagarjuna. UndoubtedJy, it is the
Sarvastivada theory
which cquatcd Jtlf!IJR[/4 and prafityt1.Iamulpanna that Nagat:juna
has in mind
(see commcnts on VTI.1). The implicacioo of this equation is
that "the uocon·
ditioncd" (asaf!1Jkr14) is also the
"independent" or "uncaused''
(aprafityasamutpanna), an implication not acccptable to both
Nagarjuna and
the Buddha.
In fact, XXV.4-6 highlight the sharp distinction the
metaphysicians assurned
between frcedom and bondagc (sec Chaptcr XVI, Examinacion
ofBoodagc and
Releasc). lt is this sharp distinction, whkh is the
foundation of the substan·
ciafuc cxplanacion of freedom and bondage, that is being
analysed by Nagarjuna. Unlcss this metaphysical cxplanation is kcpt in view.
speculatoins about
Nagarjuna's owo conception offrecdom can turo out to be as
wcird as those of
the met.aphysicians.
6. Bh'ii11aś ca yadi nirva11am anupadiiya taf kathaf!I,
nirv'ii'!tlf!l niiiulpiidiiya kaicid bhii110 hi 11idyate.
Furthctmocc, if frccdom werc to be cxisrcnce, how can tbat
freedom be
independent, for an independent cxistcncc is ccctainly not
cvidcnt?
MKV(P) p.526; MKV(V) p.230.360 THE. PHILOSOPHY OF THE M
IODl.f. WAY
Hece agaio we have a metaphysical inte(pcetation of upadiiya
(see IV.1-2)
whece existence (bhava), as the permapeot and the eternał ,
becomes not only
che "unconditioned" (XXV. 5), but also ·the
absolutely "independent"
(anupadiiya)(see also ±x!I.5). Nigarjuna is not prepared to
equate freedom
with such non-empirical existence.
7, Yadi bh?ivo na nirziiif!a1n abhavaf? ki?p. bhavijyati,
nirvfirta?p. yatra bhavo na nabhavas tatra vidyate.
If freedom is not existence, will freedom be non-existence?
Wherein
there is no existence, therein non-existence is not evident.
MKV(P) p. 527 ~ MKV(V) p.230.
The metaphysical notions of existence and noo-existence
expressed in such
terms as aststva and nastitva are hece ccferred to as bhava
and abhava. They
bcing back the pcoblems ofidentity and differences (see
1.3). Nigarjuna's argu-
,
ment, as at 1.3, is tbat these rwo are relative concepts.
8. Y(ll/y abhavaś
ca niniartam anupadiiya t4t katha?p.,
nir.va1!a?!J na
hy abhavo 'stt' yo 'nupadiiya vidyate.
Iffreedom .is non-ex.istence, how etn freedom be
independent?for there
exists no non-existence which evidently is independent.
MKV(P) p.527 ; MKV(V) p .231.
If there were to be no p ermanent existence, there could be
oo permanent nonexistence. If chere wece to be no absolute existence, there
could be no nihilistic
non-existence. Just as much as freedom is not absoluce
existen~e, it is also not
nihiłisLic noo-existence, Nigarjuna's atternpt in the
present chapcet is directly
aimed at getting rid of sucha metaphysical explanation of
freedorn . The Buddhists, throughout history, were prone to .make such
distinctions, sornetirnes
ignoring the empirical middle position advocared by the
Buddha. This is what
Nagar)una intends to explain in the next vr:rse.EXAMINA1 lON
OF FREEDOM
9. Ya ajavaf!Z·favz-bhava upadiiya prafitya va,
so 'prafity?inupadiiya nirvfirt-am upac/iryate.
Whatever is of che nacure of coming and going that ocrurs
contingently
or dependently. Freedom is, rherefote, indicated as being
noncontingentand independent.
MKV(P) p.529;
MKV(V) p.23t.
361
Eveo though the Buddha empahsized the avoidance of
metap,hysicaJ extremes,
there was indeed a tcndency to distiogulsh saf!Zs'iira and
niniii'!a. The cycle of
binhs and deaths, "comings and goings" (iijavaf!Z·fa'llif!Z),
was looked upon as
having its owo nature (bhava) which is dependeoce. This is
contrasted with the
narure (bhiiva) offreedom which is independent. The inuusion
of the substantiałist notions in the form of saT!Jvrti (convention) and paramartha
(''ultimate
reality") into the Buddhist doctrine during the
scholastic period has aheady
beeo rcfened to (see comments. on XXIV.8). Even though most
Buddhist
rhinkers were able to avoid such ontological speculacions in
explaining the
nature of the world and freedom, the Buddhist metaphysicians
had difficułty
in avoiding such a dichotomy. Therefore, in the next verse,
Nagarjuna proceeds to remind the Buddhists of the Buddha's teaching on becoming
and
other-becoming (bhava-vibhava) .
10. Parhii11af!Z cabravzc chasta bhav"!ya vibhavasya
ca,
tasmiin na bhavo nabhavo nirva11af!J iti yujyate.
The teacher has spoken of relinquishing both becom.ing and
otherbecoming. Therefore, it is proper .to assume r.hat freedom is neither
existence nor non-existence.
MKV(I() p.530; MKV(V) p.232.
In addltion to the two concepts ofSaf!Zbha11a and 11ibhava,
discussed previousły
(Chapter XXI), Nagarjuna introduces another ·pair: bhava and
vibhava. lt is
significant to note that when Nagarjuna rejected astitva and
nastitva b~ was
quoting the Buddha (XV.7). He does the same when he refers
to bhava and
vibhava (XXV. 10). Yet, when he rejects bhava and abhava,
rwo concepts that362 THE PHltOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
do not appear in the early discourses, except as suffixcs,
Nigarjuna mercly in·
dicates that lhe Buddha realized their implications
(bhav'libh'li11a-11ibhavina,
XV.7) and does not present it as a statement of the Buddha.
This supports our
previous contention tbat bh'iit!a and ilbha11a represent an
attempt to reintroduce mtitva and riiistitva into philosophkaJ discussions by
the
BrahmanicaJ and Buddhist metaphysicians.
One significant difference berweeo the concepts of bhiva and
abhiva(astitva and riiislitva), on the one hand, and bhavaand vibhava, on the
other, is that .
the former arc metaphysical ass\unptions and the latter
dcscribc cmpirical
events. As such, the reasons for their rcjection would be
different. Bhiva and
abhava arc rejected bccause they arc mctaphysicaJ and, as
such, unvcrifiabłe in
terms of the cpistemological standpoint adopted by the
Buddha. On the cootrary, bhav~ and vibhava arc experienced processcs of life,
namcly, becoming
and ocher-becorńing, and the reason for theit being rejecced
is chat they lead to
suffering (duf?kha) . B'hava is the process of becoming
conditioned by dispositions. Hence .the Buddha spoke of "craving for
becoming" (bha11a-l411h'ii), a
constant thirś'ting to btcomc this or that. Vibhava could
mean either ''becoming something different" or annihilation of tbis
process of becoming (namcly,
suicide). This was aJso referred to as a form of craving
(vibhava-tat?hi).
Howeve.r, the process of becoming and becoming ocherwise
could be explained
in terms of metaphysicaJ and, therefore, wrong beliefs
(mithyii-drrti) in absolute.existence (bhiva) and nihilistic rion-existence
(t1/?h'litit1), respeccively, in·
stead of dependent arising (prt1t1tymt1mutpida). Neither of
the metaphysicaJ
explanacioos, according to the Buddha, could serve as the
basls for frcedom.
11. Bhavedabhavo bhiivaf ca nirva11af?'J ubhayaf!l yadi,
bhavedabh'iivo bhavaf ca mo/qas tru ca na yujyate.
If freedom were to be both existcnce and non-existence, chen
rclease
would also be both existence and oon-existence. This too is
not proper.
MKV(P) p.531; MKV(V) p.232.
It is possibłe for someone to assume that
"freedom" represents a special kind of
existence which combines both exi,stence and non-existence.
Jf it is understood
.. '" .
as some myscerious existcnce beyond exi~tence and
non~existence, Nigarjuna
reminds his opponents that it is no more than simple
"release" {mo/qa),and
this latter nced not be describeq .' as both existence ' and
non-existence . . Release is·ExAMINATłON OF FlUlBDOM 363
no moce than the release from suffering and there is
rtothing transcendental
about it.
12. Bhavedabhiit10 bhiit1af ca nittlafłam ubhaya'!I yadi,
niinupiidiiya nifV!ii'!am uP"iidiiyob/jaya'!J hi tal.
Iffreedom werc to be both existence and non-existence,
freedom could
not be independent, for existencc and non-existeoce arc,
indeed, dependent upon one another.
MKV(P) p.531 ;
MKV(T1 p .232.
As pointed out eadiei:, the substantiałist definition o(
fre·edom implied independence, rather than non-grasping or non-dinging (sec
comments on XXIl.5). Thus, if the metaphysicians were to define freedoro as
both existence and
non-existence, it could not be independent as they expect it
to be. This is
because existepce and non-existence are dependent.
13. Bhat1ed ahha110 bha11af ca nirva11am ubhya~
katha?"?Z,
tZSflf!1Jkrta~ ca nirvfif!tlf'?Z bh?i11abha11au ca
sarrukttau.
How could freedom be both existence and non-existence, for
freedom is
unconditioned while existence and non-existence arc
conditioned?
MKV(P) p.531 ; MKV(V) p .233.
As in the .previous verse, here too Nagiirjuna is takiog the
definition proffered
by the opponent and cdticizing his conception of freedom.
This is similar to
the argument adduced by Nagarjuna atXXV.6, except that in
the present case
Nigarjuna is insiscing that if something is both existence
and non-existeoce, it
could not approptiately be called an
"unconditioned." 'The "unconditioned,"
by the meraphysician's definition, is the
"inde(>endent" (apratftyasamutpanna),
and an element witb rwo eotities as parts of it will always
be conditioned by
those rwo parts.364 THE PHILOSOPHY O!' 'rHE MIODLE WAY
14. Bhaved abhavo bhavaś ca nirvaflam ubhayaf!' kathaf!',
na tayor ekatrastitvam (j/oka-tamasor yathli.
How could freedom be both existeoce and ooo-ex1stence, for
theit
simultaoeious ~xistence in one place is not possible, as in
the case oflight
and datkness?
MKV(.P) p..532; MKV( V) p .233.
This brings out anothcr aspect of the mecaphysicians'
conception of frecdom,
namely , the mooistic implication. Nirvfi11a, looked upon as
the "ultimate reality" (paramartha), could not accommodate variety
and multiplicity. For them ,
ie is the ooe ultimate truth, everything else beiog
provisional. However, Nagarjuna is insisting that they could noc maintain that
nirv'iif!a is both cxistencc and
noo-ex1sten ' ce.
15. Naivabliiivo naiva bha110 nirviif!am iti fii 'njanii,
abhave caiva bhave ca s'ii siddhe sati szdhyati.
The proposition that freedom is neitber existeoce nor
noń-exiśterice could
be established if and when both existence and non-existence
arc
established.
MKV(P) p .532; MKV(V) 233.
Anjanii from (yanj, ''to annoint") can mcan a symbol.
Here Nagif.rjuna is not
speaking of logicaJ proof to decide the validity of a
symbolism, or a proposicion. Rather, he is interested in the ernpiricaJ
justification. Thus, unless both
existence and non-existence, as cxplained by the
metaphysician, can be shown
~o have empirical validity, their oegations too would ruean
nothing.
16. Naivabh'iivo .naiva bhavo ninia??af?i yadi vi'dyate,
nai11abhavo naiva bhavo iti kena tad ajyate.EXAMINATION Of
FREEDOM
Iffreedom as neithec existence noc non-existeoce is evident,
by means of
what is it made known as neither existence not
non-existence?
MKV(P) p.533; MKV(V) p.233.
Thls seems to be a rather devastating cr1ticism of the more
popular view that
freedom caooot be expressed either as existeoce or as
non-existence. That is,
it is linguistically transcendent or is ineffable. If the
statement, "Freedom is
neither existence nor non•existence," is intended to
express the ineffability
of nit;iii'!a. Nagarjuna is questioning the meaningfuloess
of that very statemenc. This means that absolute negation is as metaphysićal as
absolute assertioo , ''absołute nothingness" is as meaningless as
"absolute chingness," and
these arc che absolutes chat are expressed by terms like
bh'iiva and abhava.
17. Paraf!Z nirodhad bhagatiiin bhavafity eva nohyate,
na bhavati ubhayaf!t ceti nobhaya'l!Z ceti nohyate.
lt is not assumed that the Blessed One exists after death.
Neither is it
assumed that he does not eióst, or both, or neither.
18. T1thamano 'pi" bhagavan bhavality eva nohyate,
na bhavaty ubhayaf!l- celi nobhaya1p celi nohyate.
lt is not assumed that even a living Blessed One exisrs.
Neither is it
assumed that he does not exist, or both or neither.
MKV(P) p.534; MKV(f-9 p.234.
These, indeed, are the metaphysicał assertions made
regarding the tathagata
(XXII) which both Nagarjuna and the Buddha rejecied. The
foundations of
these metaphysical views were the theocies of identiry and
difference. This very
important problem is next taken up for examination
by.Nagarjuna.
19. Na s_a'l!Zsarasya nirv'iif'!al ki~cid asti
11iśift11Jaf!l,
na nirv1if!asya sartuarlit kif?tcid a.sti
viśe[f.l'!fl'f(t.366 'f.HE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
The iifc-pr~ has no thitig that distinguishes it from
freedom. Freedom
has no thittg that distinguishes fr from the life-process.
MKV(P) p.535; MKV(V) p.234.
This statement of Nagarjuna has contributed to a major and
wide-spread assertion regarding the uniqueness of Mahayana philosophy, namely.
the ultimate
identity of sa1{'Jilira and nirvii11a. This assertion may
appear to be correct, ifwe
arc to ignore all that has been said by Nagarjuna regardiog
the metaphysical
doctrines of. identity (ekatva) and difference (n'iinatva),
especially in the
chapters dealing with the tathagata (XXII) and the four
truths (XXIV).
Those who upheld the view that this statement is an assenion
of the identicy
of Sllf!JSfJf'fJ and nirtiii11a do not seem tó have paused
for one moment to reflect
on the question regarding the nature of the identity they were
implying; nor
have they attempted to place that conception of identity (if
there is one) in the
historical context.
The facr that chere wa's a great urge on the part of the
Buddh.ists, especially
after the Buddha's death, to taise him to the level of a
supreme being, having
no real connections with the ordinary human world, can
easily be seen from the
mote popular Mahayana texts lilce the Lalitavistara · and
the
Satldh11rmapuf!t/4.fik11 as welł as the Theravada treatises
like the}iilaka-nidiinakathii. Through thac popular perspective, substancialist
views regarding the
nature of the Buddha began to emerge among philosophers.
These
philosophical views were prominent with the early
metaphysicians like the Sar·
vastivadins and the Sauuantikas.
.Nirv'a11tJ, understood as the "ultimate reality''
(paf'l~martha) , came to be
distinguished from sa1{'JS'iira, the unreal, ćhe convention,
the impermanent.
The Buddha's owo view chat niniiif?IJ is the "ultimate
fruit'' (paramattha), a
culmination of the fruit (111th11) of everyday life, the
highest morał peńection
invoJving the eschewing of aJl immoral cooduct
(sabba-pap11ssa a.kartT!/111?") and
thepromotión ofgood (kus11/111s11 upp,;11mplll/ii), was
gradually being forgotten .
Dharma was gradually being distinguished from the dharma in
che dharmaadharma context. The inapprop,riate equation of the pu;,ya-papa
distinc:tion
with the dharma-adharma distinction (see commeots on
XVJI.24) led to the
belief in a Dharma that transcends che dhamza..adhanna
distinction.
However, this was not Nagarjuna's understanding.
Vyavah'iira, the contex·
tual or the conven,tional, 1s not provisional in a cheap
pragmacic sense and,
therefore, unreaJ. lt is the concrete wichout which the
ideal (paranzartha)
makes no sense at aU (XXJV.10). lt is the absolute
distinction between
vyavahara and pararnartha rhat is denied in che present
verse.
The fact that the Buddhist metaphysicians were involved in
Jong-drawnEXAMJNATlON OF FREEOOM 367
phiiosophical disputes with the Brahmanical schools of
thought and. therefore.,
the possibility of mutual influences should not be
discounted. For example, the
Saurranrika philosophical standpoint resernbles in many ways
the standpoint of
the Vaise~ikas . This Jatter philosophy is founded on the
basie methodology of
makiog "distinctions" (viśe1arJa). Nagarjuna's
present statement can be properly evaJuated in the background ofsuch a
methodology.
Indeed, the most sigoificant part of the statement is: na
ki1?1-cit asti
11iśefa11a'!' , i.e., "there is no thing that can be taken
as a distinctioo," or "tbere
is no distinct thing." (see XXV.20 and 24). The
reference to somc metaphysical
entity as "some thing'' (kif?l-cit) is a popular
feacure in the early discourses as
well as in the Prajflaparamita-sutras.
20. Nirvaf!asya oa ya kofi/t koti/t saf?Zsara11(1.Jya ca,
na tayor antaraf?Z kif?Zcit susuk1mam api vidyate.
Whatever is the extremicy of freedom .and the extremicy of
the lifeprocess, between them not even a subtle something is evident.
MKV(P) p. 5 3 ~ ; MKV(V) p.235.
Haviog rejected a sharp dichotomy between saf?Zsara and
niroiif!a, Nagarjuna is
not willing to let the metaphysician discover something
~xttemely subtle
(kif?Zct't suiuk/maf!J), comparaele to the extremely subtle
and incorruptible
seed of release (mokfa-blja)(see comments on XXIV.32),
between saf?Z.Jara and
nirvii11a. The identity theories of both Sarvastivada and
Sańkhya school posited
such subcle encicies to explaio cootinuity. Nagarjuna's
present stacement
should be understood in the background of the ideas expressed
by these
schcols.
Therefore, the translation of ,he first line as "The
limits of nirvatJa are the
lin1ics of ItJf?Zsard' (Ioada, p.158), is not very
appropriate. Furthermore, che
first line does noc make a complete sencence. The emphasis
in the completc;,
sentence is oo the phcase ~if?Zoit susikpmaf?Z (see XXV.
19), which is
Nagarjuna's major concern hece.
21. Para:?p nirodhad antlidya"f; faśvatlidyaś ca
dofaya/f,
m·rvlittam aparantat?'t ca purvanta'f!J ca sam'iifrita/?.368
THE Pl-OJ.OSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE WAY
Metaphysical views relating to the finite, etc„ to the
etcrnal, etc„ after
death arc associated with [the problems of] f.reedom as well
as the
posterior -and prior exttetńities.
1WKV(P) p.536; MKV(V) p.23).
Herein, reference is made to eight of the ten
"undeclared'' (avyakrta) issues.
Nagarjuna perceives them to be associated with the question
of freedom, a
freedom 1ooked at from two of the major concerns of.the
human bcings, namely, the first bcginning and the ultimate end, the flrst eause
and the final cause.
Human concerns like "Where did I come froro?" or
"Where woufd I go after
this?" (as will be exlained in the finał Chapter on
"Examination ofViews") have
influenced human thinking and often led to metaphysical
views about freedom
and bondage.
22. Silnyefu sarva-dharmeftt ki11J anantaf!Z kim antavat,
kim ananta1n antavac c.a n'iint#nta??t nfit111ntavac ca
ki'!Z.
23. Kir(I- tad eva kim anyat kir(I- śafvalaf!l kim
aś1iśvataf?1.,
aś'iiwata1!l śaśvata'f?Z ca kif?Z va nobhayam apy atai; ~
When all things are empty, why [specułate on] the finite,
the infinire,
both the finite and the infinite and neither finite nor
the·infinite? \Vhy
[speculare on] the identical, the different, the etetnal,
the non-eternal,
both or neither?
MKV(P) p.537; Ml-.'V(V) p.235 .
Empiricist Nagarjuna's fina! fina! qucstion, after
presenting such a detailed
aoaiysis of all the ,netaphysical views to which he has
devoted twenty-five
chapters, is "Why raise all these metaphysical issues,
when aJl experienced
thlogs are empcy?" (śiinyer11 sarva-dharmefu kif!l . ..
). As reiterated before in
the commentary, he is spea!dng about things that are empty
(śunya), włiich arc
the empirically given and which are seeo to be dependently
arisen
(prałityasamutpanna). H e is not emphasizing the absttact
concept,
"emptiness" (iunyata).EXAMINATION OF FR.BIDOM
24. Sarvopalambhopaśa11J11f? prapancopaśamal? śivaf?,
na kvacit ka1yacit kafcid dharmo b11ddhena deśital/.
The Buddha did not tcach the appeasement of all objccrs, the
appeasement ofobsession, and the auspicious as some thing to some one at some
pbcc.
MKV(P) p.538; MKV(V) p.236.
369
Inada has broken up the above inro two distinct statements
and thereby lost its significance. The first line contaios qualificarions of
dharma occurring in the second.
N:igarjuoa's emphasis is on the phrase: kaścil dharmafł, as
it was in the case of
the two important statementS made previously in the present
chapter
(XXV.19-20). When the Buddha spoke of freedom (nirva fla),
which he
quaJified as the appeasement of aH objects (upaklmbha =
al11mbana =
dra1ta11ya, cf. drfJ!(avyopaśama at V.8) or the appeasement
of obsessions
(prapałlcopafama) or auspicious (Jiva, sec Dedicatory
Verses). he was nor refeuing to them as "some thing,'' that is, some
cotity having a specific distinction
(viiefaf!a) or subdety (1uiulqma111a). He was oot speaking
of freedom in the
way the substantialist cooceived of it.
All these twenty-five chapters are, therefore, negative io
characrer and tone.
They were devoted to a rcfutation of the two metaphysical
but related views of
existence and noo-ex.istence (astitv'ri-ntistitva). Having
cleared up the dust that
had gachered around all the doc~rines preached by the
Buddha, Nagarjuna is
now ready to go on to the positive description of bondage
and fre·edom as
enunciated by the Buddha in the discourse to Kacyayana.
Nagarjuna's ttearment of the metaphysicaJ issues chat ernerged in relation to
all these doctrinesdoctrines pertaining to causacion, change, the human
personaJity, survival, karma, morał respo.nsibi ł ity, and freedom-is so
cxhaustive and compłe te that he
can proceed to explain the Buddha's conception. of bondage
and freedom
without any fear ofany one raising any question. Por he has
already answered
them all. Herein Lies the greatoess of Nagarjuna as a
philosopher.CHAPTER
TwEN1Y SIX
Exarnination of the Twełve Causał Factors
(Dvadasańga-paffk!ti)
l. Punarbhavaya sa??Zskiiran avidyii-nivrtas iridha,
·abhiJa1(1Jk11rute fiit?ts tair gatt~ gacchati karmabhil{.
A personeovdoped by ignorance forms such dispositions in the
threcfołd
ways łcading to re-b~oming, and through su.eh actions be
moves on to
his destiny.
MKV(P) p.542; MKV(V) p.238.
This chapter is of łitde significance to most Nagarjunian
scholars. Inada argues:
With the discussioo of Niniii'!a in the last chapter the
treatment
from the standpoinr of the Mabayana had basically come to a
dose.
ln tbis chapter and the finał one to follow, Nagarjuna goes
into the
analysis of the Hrnayanistic doctrines.... The discussion is
Hfnaya,nistic and it reveals that the source of trouble lies
in ignorance which in turn initiates all kinds of meotal confotmations
(satpskiira) (Niigiirjuna, p. l60).
While disagreeing totalły with this interpretation, I
propose to show chat thls
chapter represents the mosc positive explaaation by
Na:garjuna of the Buddha's
teachings oo boodage and freedom as enunciated in 'the vast
collection of
discourses, with the discourse to Karyayana as the pivot.al
text. lndeed, without
the positive te.i,chiogs pl'esented hece coming after the
negative analysis in the
last twenty-five chapters, it is rather difficult to see how
Nagarjuna could claim
to be restating the Buddha-word, as he openly expressed it
.in severa! places
eaclier (see XV.6; XVII.6, 8, 11; XXIV.8-9). It is indeed
surpri!ling to see how
most interpreters of Nagii;rjuna are loolcing for posidve
statemeots of the doc·
370Ev.MINATION OF THE TwELVE CAUSAL FACTORS 37 1
trine primarily through negations {XXV.3 and Dedicatory
Verses), while ignoring ałl the positive statements of Nigarjuna.
XXVI. l is a further cxplanation of the Buddh a's statement:
"Depending
upon ignorance arc dispositions" (aviJJapaccaya
sańkhafii). lts d aborarion is
also the Buddha's and is presented in the
Kukkuravatika-rutla (M 1.390).
2. Vijffiinarp 1arpni11isa1e sarpsliiirapratyayarp gatatJ,
1arrznivi!fe 'tha vi/ fiiine niimafilparp nt! icyate.
Consciousncss, with disposition as i~ conditioo, cnters [the
new] life.
Whcn coosciousnc:ss has cotercd, the psychophysical
pcrsonality is i.nfuscd.
MKV(P) p.543; MKV(V) p.238.
This represents the cxplanacion of the relationships
described in the statement,
"Depcoding upon dispositions is consciousness"
(sańkharapaccaya vińffiif!arrz)
and "Depcnding upon consciousness is the psychophysical
personality"
(vifllłaf!apaccaya namafilparp). The explication of the
first of rhese is found at
S 3.87 ( Tsa 2. 14 [Taisho 2. llc)) where it is said:
"Disposition is so called
bccause it proccsses . .. consciousness that has alteady
beeo dispositionally
conditioned, into ics present state." The dispositions
arc thus responsible for
providing an individualicy to consciousness, and it is this
individuated consciousncss chat comes to be established in a psychophysicaJ
personalicy. This łatcer event is explaincd at D 2.63 (Chang 10.2 ITairho l.6l
b]), where it is scated
that the psychophysical personalicy formed in the mother's
womb will not grow
into marurity (na vuddhi'?l viru(hirp 'iiP111/at1) if
consciousness were not to enter
it and get established therein. In fact, the Chinese
translatioo of Kuma rajl va
refers to such attainment of marurity of the psychophysical
pcrsonaJity.
Those who aJ"e unwilling to atcribure a doctrine of
survival to Nigarjuoa may
interprer the relation becween consciousoess and the
psychophysicaJ pcrsonałity
as oo more chan the explanation of the act of being
conscious during ordinary
day to day experienccs. lfso, ir would have been possibJe
for Naga rjuna to say
so at this point. Instead , he ·ptefers to sp eak of a life
(.gah) , generally
understood as a fururc life or desdny, and proceeds to
explain the process of
perception only after outlinjng the emergence of the six
sensory faculties
associatcd with the psychophysicaJ personalicy.372 THE
PHILOSOPl-IY OFTHE MIDDLE WĄY
3. Nifikte
niirnafiipe tu 1at!iiyatana-sa?!Jbha11a~.
1arfayatanam
agamya saf!JSparfal/ sar(Jpravartate.
When the psychophysical personality has bee.n infused, the
occurrence of
the six spheres (of sense) takcs place. Depencling upon the
six spheres
proceech cont.act.
MKV(P) p.552-553; MKV(V) p.242 .
The Buddha's statemenr, "Dependiog upon the
psychophysical personality are
che six spheres of sense" (niimarupapaccay'ii
sa{'iiyatanaf!'), explains an import.ant pre-requisite for the emergence of
human knowledge. If the
psychophysical personałity is not properly formed or if the
sensory faculties
were to be.defective, the sensory spheres such as materia!
form, sound , smell,
taste, touch, and concepts would not provide a foundation
for contact. Thus,
the visual organ, whicb Is part of the psychophysical
personality should be
unirnpeded (aparibhinna) and should function properly. The
external object
should come into focus (bahir'li ca Nipa ipathaf!J
agacchatt) and attention
(samannahara). which is a function of consciousness, shou.ld
be avaiJable (M
1..190; Chung 7,2[Taisho1.467a]). Theo only there will
cmerge consciousncss
which is a necessary condition for contact. This.idea is
theo elabotaced by
Nagarjuna io the next verse.
4. Cakfuh. pralitya rupa'!' ca sa1nan11aharam, eva ca,
n'iimarupt1f'?J p rafftyaivaf!J vijńiinaf!J
JIJ1(Jpravartatc.
5. Sa?!Jipatas tray'ii1{ii1(J yo
ropa-vijflanu·Ca~tt!'li'f(t,
sparśal/ sah. tas1niit sparfac ca vedanii Jat!Jpravartate.
Thus, depeoding upon the eye and mateńal form, and attention
too, and
depencling upon the psychophysical personality pcoceeds
consciousness.
'Whatever is the harmonious coocurrence of the three
factors: material
form, consciousness, and eye, is contact. .Feeling proceeds
from such
contaet.
MKV(P) p,553·554; MKV(V) p.242.Ex.AMINATION OFTHE TWELVE
WUSAL FACTORS
The i:welvefold formula presents feeling as being
conditioned by contact
(phassapaccaya vedanii). However, Nagarjuna feds the need to
explain what
contact is all about. He, therefore, inserts the cxplanation
of cootact provided
by the Buddha in the Madhupif!fika-sutta (M 1.111-112;
Chttng 28.3 [Tairho
1.604b]). Contact is che harmonious concurrence (sańgatt) of
three factors:
materiał form , (visual) consciousness, and eye. lt is tłUs
harmonious concurrencc chat provides a foundation for feeling (vedanii).
6. Vedanapratyaya trf'f!a vedanarthaf!I hi trf'yate,
trf~amlina upadiinam upad11tte catut'tlidha'(Z.
Conditioned by feeling is craving. lndeed, craving is
feeling-directed.
The one who craves, gtaSpS on to the foutfold spheres of grasplng.
MKV(P) p..554-555 ; MKV(fl?p.243.
Hece Nagarjuna has an interesting explanacion of craving
(tr1n.?i) when he says:
11edan4rtharp hi t(!yate, i. e, "it i~ for feeling that
one craves ." Ie is a reference to
the pleasant feelings (śubha1 maniipa, or sukha). The
fourfold spheres ofgrasping are: grasping for desires (kama), for views
(dil(h1). for rules and rights
(i1/abba1a), and for theories of self (attaviida)(M 1. 51).
7. Upadiine sati bhava upadii11,f; pravartqte,
JYtidd hi yady anup1idiino mucyeta na bhaved bhaval;.
When grasping exis(S, bccoming on the part of che grasper
proceeds. lfhe
were to be !l non-grasper, be would be released, and there
would be no
further becoming.
MKV(P) p . 5~6; MKV(V} p.243.
lt is inceresting ro noce that at this point i"n the
explaoarioo of the twelvefold
formula Nagarjuna speaks of freedom or release (mak.fa). It
is a point at which
,374 TuE PH!LOSOPl-IY OF THE M IDDLE WAY
the process of bondage can be interrupted. Nagarjuna is
problably emphasizing this because he witnessed how his fellow Buddhists, in
spite of their enormous intellectual capacities, constantly adhered to
metaphysicaJ views and wece
caught in "Brahma's Net" (brahma-jii/11). Some of
these intellecrual giants, who
wece able to write commentary after commentary, even though
they had abandoned househoJd lives wece cnamoced with their views and invoJved
jo ceaseJc~
diatribes. Realiziog the emphasis placed by the Buddha upon
"non-grasping"
(anupadiina), Nagarjuna interrupts his exposition of the
process of bondage co
explain freedom.
8. Panca skandh'iil/ sa ca bha11afl bhav'iijj'iitil/
pravartate,
jar'ii-maraf!a-duf?khadi sokiil/ saparidevan'iif?.
9. Daurmana.syam
upay'iis'ii1ater etat pravartate,
kevalasyaivam
eta.sya dul/kha-skandhasya sa1tJbhaval;.
The fivc aggrcgatcs constitutc this bccoming. From becoming
proceeds
birth. Suffering rclaring to decay and death, etc., grief,
Iamcntation, dejcction, and ruspair- all tbese proce~ from birth. Such is the
occurrence
of this e.nti.re mass of suffering.
MKV(P) p.556-557; MKV(V) p.243-244
The elimination of craving for becoming (bhava-Jaf!h'ii), as
mentioned
cadier (sec XXV.10), was encouragcd by the Buddha. The
rcason for this
is not merely because craving causes suffcring in this life,
but aJso because
it could lead to birth in another Jifc (jatt), whicb would
also involve the
repetition of all the unfortunate experiences of the present
life. Tht<
phrase duf?kha-skandha is used in the sense of heap or mass
of suffering
rathcr than "suffering attached to the skandhas,"
(lnada, p . 162).
10. Sa?!Jsar11rmu!an sao/skiiran avidvan sar!l.skaroty
atal/,
a·11idvan kiirakaf; tasrniin na vidva??Zs tattva-darśaniit.
Thus, che ignorant forms disposjtions that constirute the
source of thefx.AMJNt\.110 N OP THE TwELVE CAUSAL FACI'ORS
life process. Therefore, it is the ignorant who is the
agent, not the wise
one, because of his [the łatter's] perception of truth.
MKV(P) p .558; MKV(V) p.244.
375
The enlightened one who had attained che appeasement of
dispositions
(S4'f!Uk'iiropaśama) does not conttibute to the perpetuation
of the life-process
(.ratrJsara). Hence, he is not an agent (kart.1kt.1f!)
respoosible for such perpetuation. This seems to indicate Nagarjuna's awareness
of the Buddha's famous
statement chat upon attainiog enligbtenment he perccived the
builder of the
house (gaha-karaka, Dh 154). ·
Reading too much metaphysics into the phrase
tattv11-darlt.1nt.1 can destroy all
that Nagarjuna attempted to do in the preceding cwenty-five
chapters. Instead
of explaining it as "the perception of an absołute
reality," it could be more appropriate1y understood as the perception of
the empirical truth that "all this is
empty" (slZT'llam t'daf!J śUnydf!J) of a substance
(svabhavt.1tal/).
11. Avidyay1i1fl niruddhafiif!J saf!Jskiiraf!am
asa1{Jbht.1vaft,
avidjiiya nirodhas tu jniinenasyt.1t'va bhavanat.
When ignorance has ceased, there is no occurre.nce of
dispositions.
However, the cessation of that igoorance takes płace as a
result of the
practice of that [non-occurrencc of dispositions] through
widsom.
MKV(P) pp.558-559r MKV(P) p .244.
The murual relacionship betWeen cessation of ignorance and
the aon-arising of
disposicions is emphasized by Nagatjuna, keeping in mind the
distinction between the appeasement of dispositions (sa1{Jskaropaśama) in the
pcesent life
and their waning (saf!JSk1ira-k1ay11) at the time of death,
theccby not pcovidi:ng
another opportuniry for rebirth.
12. Tasya ttZSya nirodhena lal tat1 nabhipra1111rttite,
du/;Jkha-skandht.14 kevalo 'yam evaf!J samyag nirudhyate.376
T HE PHILOSOPHY Of THE M.JDDLE W AY
With the cessation of these, these othere factors [of the
twelvefold formula] would not proceed. ln this way, this entire mass
ofsuffering ceases
comt>łetely.
MKV(P) p. 559; MKV(V) p .244.
The emphasis is probably on the cessation of ignorance and
the non-arising of
dispositions. These two factors are taken to predominace the
entire łife-process.
The attainmeot of e~ghtenment and the appeasemeńt of
dispositioos through
non-graspiog (anupadiina) account for "freedom with
substrate'' (saupadiśefa·
nirv'iif!a), whi.le the elimtnation of dispositions provides
for non-re-becoming
(a-punar-bhava)(cf. XXVL l) and the waning of birth
(iiiti-kfaya), which is
freedom "without substrate"
(nirupadi1efa-11irvii11a).CHAPTER
'fwENTY SEVEN
Examination of Views
(Drffi-parz k~a)
1. Dr1fayo 'bhuvaf?Z nabhuvaf?Z ki?!/> nv alite 'dhvanlti
ca,
jiis tal? śaśvatalokady7if? puniiintat?Z samupaśritaf?.
Whatcver views asserting an eternal world, etc. based upon
[the perceptio.nJ: ''Did I exist or not exist in the past?" are associated
with the prioc
end [of existence].
MKV(P) p.571; MKV{V) p.249.
The first line of the verse has been reconstructed by
Poussin on the basis of the
Tibetan ttanslation.
In che Pari(eyyaka-sutta (S 3.94-99; Tsa 2,.,25 [Tatiho
2.13c-14a]}, the Buddha maintained chat views such as "The self and che
world are etetnal" (sassato
afta ca loko ca) are metaphysical because they are
dispositional answers
(sankharo so) to querries about the past such as: "Did
I exist in the past or
not?" As such, chey are not based entirely upon
empirical facts. lndeed, they
are attempts to go back to the prior end of existence
(pubbanta). While the
Buddha recognized them as futile attempts, mostly because of
the limitarions
of human knowledge and understanding (see Chaptet XI), he
was not uowill·
ing to accept wbatever evidence available through veridical
memories (sadi,
pubbenivasanussati). On the basis of such evidence, he
characterized the past
existences as impecmanent (anicca), clispositionalły
decermined (sankhata), and
dependently arisen (pa;iccasamuppanna), and not as permaoent
(nicca) , immutable (dhuva) , and eternal (sassata).
Nagarjuna's explanatioo of the metaphysical views of
eternalism (śaś-vata),
etc. is, therefore, a vivid representacion ofthe Buddha's
attitude regatding such
v1ews.
2. Dpfayo na bhavi!yami kim anyo 'nagate 'dhvani,
bhavzjyatniti cantadya apf.1ńintam. sa1nupt1śritaf?.
377378 THE PHlLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE wAY
Whatever views asserti.ng the finite, etc. based upon [the
perceptioo]:
"Would I not exist U1 the futu.re or would I become
sorńeQne else?" arc
associ.ated with the posterior end [of existence].
MKV(P} p.573; MKV(Vj p.249.
The assumptions that the self and the world arc finite or
iefinite ate similarly
based upon one's dispositions (sańkhara). Those who arc
enamored with life as
it is would insist upon the world being infinite. Those who
are averse to life
would advocate finiteness, insisting that there will be no
way in which life
could continue. This is tantamount to annihilation
(uccheda-ditthi, S 3.99;
Tsa 2.25 [Tairho 2.14bJ) .
3. Abhum atitam adhvanam ity api etan nopapadyate,
yo hijanmasu purve!u sa eva ,na bhavaty ayaf!Z.
The view that I existed in thepast is not appropriate, for
whosoevet was in the
prcvious birth, he, indeed, is not identicał with his
person.
MKV(P) p.573>MKV(V) p.250.
This sratemenr may appear, at first sight, to mean a denial
of rebirth or survival; that is, it would be inapproptiate to say: "1
existed in the past." Howevet:,
if one "is careful in observing the emphasis in the
second line, nan1ely, sa eva
("he himself"), it will become apparent that what
is denied is not ally relatiooship between two lives, but the identity of the
two persons in different existences. Therefore, the statement, "I existed
i11 the past," becomes
metaphysical only if an absolute identity is posited, which
indeed was the prod ivity of the metaphysician.
4. Sa evalmett' tu bhaved upadiina'f!l viśi1yate,
rtpadiina-vinirmukta atmii te katamal? puna/;.EXAM1NATIC5N
OF Vtl!WS
Ifit were to occur [tosomeone): "He, indeed, is
theself/' thcn graspingis
identified. Scparated f.rom grasping, what coostitutc your
selt?
MKV(P) pp.574-575; MKV(V) p.250.
379
The Buddha explained self-consciousness expressed in such statemenrs
as "I
am ... "(asmltt) as dependent upon (upiidiiy11) the
five aggregates. lt is like
seeing one's own reflection on a clean mirror or a pan of
elear water. In this
case, ooe cannot perceive one's refleccion unless there is a
personality that is
rcflccted, and these constitute the five aggregates (S
3.105). However, convert~
ing cllls sdf-consciousoess to a cogito, a "self' that
is permanent and eternal, is
also the work of upiidiina, meaoing "grasping or
clinging.'' lt is sometimes
described as thirsting or craving (ta„ha) and this could be
for becoming (bhav11)
or other.-becoming (vibh1111a)(S 3.26; Tsa 3.23 [Taisho
2.19a].
Tbus, neither self-consdousness nor a "self' would be
fouod independently
(upiidiina-vinirmukta). Howcver, the attaino;ient of
freedom, described as
anupadii vimukti, does not imply the ncgation of
self-consciousness, but only
of the "thirsting for becoming/' (bhava-t1J'!h7i),
which otherwise could lead to
the belief in a permaneot and eternal self that is
independent of the aggregates, and idea already rejected by Nagaijuoa .in
Chapter XXV.
5. Upadiina-vinirmukto nasty atmetikrte sati,
syad upadinam evat-rna tzasti catm.eti 11a!, puna}/.
When it is assumed that there is no selfseparated from
grasping, g~g
itself would be the self. Yet, this is tantamount to saying
that there is no
self.
MKV(P} p.575; MKV(V) p.251.
The assertion that thc:re is no .self apan from grasping
(upadiina-vinirmukta)
provides the identity tbeorists with the opportunity of
ideotifying the selfwith
grasping. Thus, when the Bllddha,.having denied a self,
maintained that consdousness (vifl;;a'!a) prov,ides a link. between two łives
(D 3.105; Chang 12.2380 TifE PHILOSOPHY .OF THE Mrooi.E WAY
[Taisho 1. 767aJ), one of his disciplies, Sari, immediately
assumed that "tbls
consciousness icself t.ransmigrates, and ńot anotber"
(zdam eva vifiiiiif!a'f(l sandhavati sa'f(lHtrati ananfla'f(l, M 1.256; Chung
54.2 [Tairho l .767a]), chereby
atrributing ao identity theory to the Buddha. The Buddha's
immediate
response was to. deny such identity by asserting that
consciousness is depeodentły arisen (paficcasdmuppanna). Theo the Buddha
proceeded ro show how
consciousness, when explained in terms of causa! dependence,
leads to a denial
of such identity. This, indeed, is what Nagarju na eodeavors
to do in the
present cootext.
6. Na copiidiinam evatmii vyeti tcrt samudeti ca,
katha'f(l hi namop'iidiinam upiidiiiii bhavi.fyati.
Grasping is not identical with the self, for that ~i.e„
grasping] ceases and
arises. Furthermore, how can grasping be the gta$per?
MKV(P) p.576; MKV(V) p.251.
As was dooe by the Buddha, (see comments above XXVlI.5),
Nagarjuna is rejecting the notion of self (iitman) on two grounds. First, it is
assumed to be
permanent and eternaJ, whereas grasping that is identified
with the self is sub-
- ject to ac:isiog ·and ceasiog. Secondly, the self is also
assumed to be the ageo t
behind all human action and, rherefore, of grasping. lfso,
how can tt be both
action and agent at the same time?
7. Anyaf? punar upadiinad atrna 11t1ivopapad'yafe,
grhyeta hy anupadiino yady anyo na ca grhyate.
Furthermore, a self thar is different from grasping is
oor~ppropriate. A
pecson who is without grasping can be observed. However, if
he were to
be differeht [from grasping], he could not be observed.
MKV(P) p.577; MKV(V) p.251.EXAMINATION OF VIEWS 381
For che Buddha as wełl as for Nagarjuna, the denial of a
substancial encity is
based upoo empirical evidem::e, namdy, the perception of an
individualiry consisting of the five aggregates. The five aggregates do not
appear individually as
insulated discrete elementS. They appear as·a lump (puflja)
wh.ich retains its individuality (based upon dispos.hions) and cootinuicy
(founded tipoo consciousness). In such a conte.xt he is caUed a person (hoti
satto ti sammuti, S
1.135; Tsa 45.5 [Taisho 2.327a]). In the context of a
society, he becomes a
social being with relarionships to others (as son, facher,
or daughter , mother.
etc.) In the context of morał behavior, he becomes good or
bad (see the explanation of empirical self by William James, The Pn·nciples of
Psychology ,
vol.1,291-293). However, if the self wete to be considered
different from che
perceivcd individuałity, it woułd turo out to be a rather
mysterious encity and
bence unknowable through the availabJe means of knowledge.
CandcakTrti, who pcefers a transcendentalist interpretation
of Nagarjuna, .
gives .a negative explanacioo of what is very clearły a
positive statement of
Nagarjuna.
8. Evarp, nanya upadiinan na cop'iidiinam eva sa~
11tma nasty anupadiinal; n'iipi' niisty e!a niścayaf?.
Thus, he is neitber clifferent from grasping nor identical
with it. A self
does not exist. Yet, it is not the case that a person who
does not grasp
does not ex;ist. This much is certain.
M.KV(P) pp.577-578; MKV(V) p.252.
CandrakTrti, who favored a uailScendentaJist interpretation
of Nagarjuna,
makes this a negative statement. The positive reading given
above is justified
on ~o grounds. First, ,iQ the previous ·instances; Nagarjuna
was clearJy asserting an empirically known ( = grhyeta) anupadiinaf? (that is,
a person f.reed from
grasping), white at the same time rejecting an atman
different from both grasp·
ing and non-graspiog. Secondly, che posicive readiog is
clearly justified by
KumarajTva's Chinese rendering of this verse. .
As such, what Nagarjuna is denying is both jdentity
(upadiinatn eva sal;)
and difference (anya upadiina'f!J). A rejection of
metaphysicał identity and difference does not necessarily tnean that Nagarjuna
was abandoning an empiricaJ
personality. For Nagarjuoa, Janguage need not be necessarily
metaphysical in
character.382 TuE PHILOSOPHY OP THE M IODlf W/\ Y
9. Nlibhum afftam adhvanam ity etan nopapadyelte,
yo hijanmaru purve1u tato 'nyo na bhavaty aya?!J.
The statement, "I did not exist in che past," is
not appropriate, for this
person is not different from whosoever existed in the
previous lives.
M.KV(P) p.578: MKV(fl?p.252 .
This. theo is a elear deoial of absolute difference. Just as
much as rhe statement, "I existed łn the past," is noc appropciate so
long as it is interpreted to
meao absolute identity, even so the statement, ''I did not
exist in the past," is
not appropriate as long as it is cakcn to mean absolute
differeoce.
10. Yadi hy ayatrJ bhfl'vedanyal? pratyakhyayapi tafl'.J
bhavel,
tathaiva Ca Ia Iaf!Zti;fhet Jatra jiiyeta 11amrtaf?.
If this person wece to be different [from that person in the
previous existence], then he wouJd come to be even forsaking tbat person. In
that
case he would remain the same and, in such a context, an
immortal
wouJd emcrge.
MKV(P) p. 579: MKV(fl? p.252.
Absolute difference impłies absolute ideocity. Nagarjuna has
alJ:eady shown
that "other-nature" (para-bhava) means the
sclf-nature (svabhiiva) of aoother
(XV.3. s11ahha11af? parabhavasya parabhavo hi kathyate).
Absolute identiry as
wel1 as absolute diffetence, trus involves complece
iodependence, and as such ie
woułd constitute immortality. Notbing is to be achieved.
Kumarajlva rende.rs
the phrase tatra /iiyeta v'iimrtaf? as "The atman will be
self-cau~ed."
11. Ucchedaf? karma„af!' naślJ! Jatha 'nyena
krta-karmatJaf!J,
anyena paribhogaf? sjiid evam adiprasajyale.
(1f that were the case,] there would be annihilation and
destruction of ac-EXAMINAT!ON OP VIEWS
tions. This implies that the fruic of action performed by
one will be experiencecl by another.
M.KV(P) p.580; M.KV(V) p.253.
383
The verse has been reconstructed by Poussin on the basis of
the Tibctan uanslauon.
How a metaphysicaJ coocepcion ofdifference would lead not
only to a denial
of survival but also a repudiation of moral cespoosibility
has bcen aJready
discussed by Nagarjuna (Chapter XII). There it was shown
that he depcnded
upon a discourse of the Budclha co explain this problem. The
presenc is simply a
rcstatement of chat argument.
12. Napy abhutva samudbhu10 rlofo hy atra prasajyate,
krtako vii bhaved atmii sa1?J-bhu~o 'Vapy ahetukaJ?,
Yet, in that context, the error of assuming an emergent
without prior existence docs not follow. Eithcr the self would be caused or,
ifit has occurred, it woułd be without a c:ause.
1HKV(P) p.580; MKV(V) p.253 .
The concept of self (atman) was posiced in order to account
for the concinuity
in the human personalicy which could also explain morał
responsibility.
However, the denial of an eternal self led to the opposite
view that there is no
continuity, but annihilation (uccheda). The denial of an
eteraal self and the
consequeot assenion of ąnnihilarion do not imply (na
prasajyate) che further
metaphysical view.;chat- stu:ticthing chat did nor exist
before comes to be
(abhutva sqmhhotz), which carne co be interpreted as the
abhutva bhava utpada in the Sautrantika school (sec Kalupahana, Causality ,
p.p. 152·254). In
other words, rhere is no implication hece chat existence is
completely independent, withouc any prior connections. As such, if there wece
to be any self
(atman), ir would be "made" (krtaka, see karaka ar
XXVT. 10). lf it is not, and
if it were assumed co arise, the·self would be causeless.
13. Evaf!J dufir a.lite y'ii nabhum aham abhu1n aha'f!J,
ubhayaf!J- nobhayaf!J ceti 11a1!a sa1nupapadyate.584 THE
PHILOSOPHY OF THE MlDOLE WAY
Thus, whatever view there is such as, "I existed in the
past; I did not exist;
both or neither," is not really appropriate.
MKV(PJ p.581 ; MJ(V(V) p.253.
The views (dr!ft) referred to here a.re the metaphysical
views relating to idencity.
difference , both or neithe.r. lt should be ooced chat the
reasons for rejecting
these views are empirical. Empiricism, in the Buddha as well
as in Nagarjuoa,
allows for the recognition of concinuity without having to
posit absplute identity or absolute difference.
14. Adh11any anagate ki~ nu bhavzłyiimzti darśana~,
na bhav#yami cety
etad afitenadhvana sa1na/?.
A view such as "Will I exist in the future?" or
"Will I not exist in the
futu1e?'1 is comparable to those associated with the past.
MKV(P) p .5.82; MKV(V) p.254.
Here again, the views that rue inappropriate are those
involving identity and
difference, not aoy explaoation of what the future could be
based upon one's
experience of the process of dependent arising.
15. Sa de11af? sa
manu1yaf ced eva??J bhavati fiifvata??J,
anutpannaś ca
devaf? syajjiiyate na hi faśvatam..
If it is tJtought truit a human is the same as a divine
being, then there
woułd be .the eternal. H the divine being were to be
non-arisen, th61l he
would not be born and that would consritute the eternal.
16. Devadanyo ma11u1yaś ced afiiśvatam .ato bha'llei,
devad anyo tn4nu1yaś ced S4??Jlatir nopapadyate.EXAMINAT!ON
OF V1ew s
lf ił is thought that a human is the same as a divine being,
then there
wouJd be the non-eternal. lfit is thought that a human is
different from
a divine being, chen continuicy is not appropriate.
MKV(P) p.583; AfKV(V,) p.254.
385
ln addjcion to the attainment of the uJtimate goaJ of life
(para1nartha) which is
freedom (nirvaf!a), the Buddha allowed for the possibiJity
of a human being
reachiog up to the status of a deicy or a divine being
(deva). assumed to be one
who is macerially as well as morally superior to ordinary
human beings, yet not
coming anywhere close to the ultimate goal (see S 1.228; Tsa
40.l [Taitho
2.290b]). H owever, the Buddha refused co recognize these
divinc beings as
eternal and permanent enticies (D I.20, sec Chang 14.l
(Taisho l.90b-c]).
The recognition of che above possibility could prompt the
subsrantialiscs co
discover ''some-thiog" (ki?(lcit) in the human being
that is identical with the
divine. Nagatjuna is herc rejecting any such idenciry, as
well as aoy alternace
theory that coułd make diviniry uncaused.
Funhermore, the emphasis on absolute difference would not
only lead to the
belief in non-eteroalicy (aśafvata), which woułd imply a
denial of continui ry in
or the process of becoming (Jtt'!11afl), the.lacter being
distinguished from the
meraphysical process referred to carlier (see XVI!. 7-10).
17. Divyo yady ekade.fa~ sjiid ekadesai ca 1nanu!a4,
aiaf!flta'!1 fa:fvata'T(I ca bhavet tac ca na yujyate.
If a part wece to be divine and the otber part to be human,
then there
wouJd be both the eternal and the non-eter.na!, and this tod
would not be
propcr.
MKV(P) p.584; MKV(V,) p.255
The combination of two metaphysical views do~s not prov1de
for a noometaphysical one. The Buddha's rejection of SJJch views is clearly
srated in the
Brah11iajala-1uJlanta (D 1.21) . Nagarjuoa is simply
reiteratiog that posiLion
herc .386 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W'AY
18. A:fii1vala1!J 1af.vata1!J ca prasiddham ubhayar(J yadi,
siddhe na fiiivala'f!l kama??J nai11afiiJ11ata11i ity api.
Supposing both the eternal and the non-eteroał arc
established, then it is
not possibłe to cithcr assert the etcrnal or the
non-etetnał.
MKV(P) p.585; MKV(V) p.255.
Nigarjuna is hece refusicg to accept a conclusioo which is
only a pan of a conjunctive proposition.
19. Kul41cid agataJ? kafcit ki'f!lcid gt1eche1puna!/ ku(Uit,
yadi ta.smad anadis tu sa'f!J.fiiral/ syan na casti sal/.
Ifanyonc has come from somewherc and apin werc to go
somewherc,
tben the lifc~process would be beginningless. Such a
situation does not
cxist.
MKV(P) p.585; MKV(V) p.255.
The m.ctaphysics rejected in Chaptcr II is refccred to in
the first line. The second line cmphasizes che ideas cxprcsscd in Chapter XI.
20. Niisti cec chaivatal/ kafcit ko bha11i/yaty ai7iśvataf?,
fiifutTIO 'fiiśvataf capi dvabhyam abhfii'f!l tiraskrtaJ?.
Ifit is thought that thcrc is oothing ctemal, what is it
that will be noncrernal, both ctecoal and non-eteroal, and also what is
separated from
tbese two?
MKV(P) p .586; MKV(V) p.256.
Hcre again, we havc Nagarjuna's analysis of
"something" (kaicit), an entityWMINATION OF VIEWS 387
that he was determioed to get dd of oo previous occasions
(XXV. 19,20,24),
The theories of identity, differeoce, both or neither, are
associated with such
metaphysical eotiti:es. Hence Nagarju.na's refusaJ to accept
such theori~ing.
21. Anlariiin yadi /ok.al; sjiit paralokarp. katht1rp.
bh1111e1,
athapy anantavarp.f lok.alf para/ok.alf ka1haf?Z bhavet.
H rhe world were to have a Jimjt, how could there be another
wo.rJd?
Furthermore, if the world were to have no limit, how cou1d
thcre be
another wodd?
MKV(P) p.587; MKV(V) p.;?56
Having discussed the rnetaphysical views relating to
dw:ation, i.e„ eternality.
etc., of the world and the self, Nagarjuna moves on to a
discussion of. the
theories.relating to the extent of the world.
The rejection of the metaphysicaJ notions of the finite and
the infinite are
bascd upon a recognicion of the possibilicy of a future
world (para-lokt/). According t0 Nagarjuna's analysis, a fioite (anta) implies
abseoce of continuity (uccherla), and as such militates against any conception
of a future world explained in terms of dependent arising (pralttyasamutpiida).
The infioite (ananta)
implies permanence or eternalicy (fiif11ata) aod, as such,
it woułd be meaningless to speak of a future world as an "other world"
(pf/f(l-/oka), for it would be
identical with the previo.us world.
22. Skandhaniim efa sartzfiino yasmad dipiitci1am iva,
pravartate tasman tiiintiinanta11att1111~ ca yujyate.
As this scries of aggregatcs proceeds along like a flame of
a Ja.mp,
[spcculation about] its finitude or its infinitude is not
proper.
MKV(P) p.587.; MKV(V) p.256.
The simile of the lamp (patlipa) was popu]ar a.moog the
Buddha and his
disciplcs, especiałly in their expłanation offreedom
(nibban11). As the flame of388 THE PHILOSOPHY OFTHE M IODLI! W AY
a lamp is extinguished, because of che absence of the
condicions necessary for
ics concinuous burning, so is a person's miod freed when the
fuel chat feeds ics
continuous burning with anxiecy is cxhausted. Explaining
this process in rerms
of dependencc, it would be most inap_propriate to speak of
ics finfrude or infinicude, independent of any condicions that arc involved in
its conrinuicy or
lack ofcontinuity. This is a elear indicacioo chat an
absolutiscicconception is iocompatible with an explanation based upon
conditionalicy.
23. PUrvc yadi ca bhajyerann utpadyeran na capy ami,
skandhaf? skandhan prafityeman atha loko 'ntaiiiin bha11e1.
Iftheprior aggregates were to pe destroyed and rhese
aggregates were also
not to arise depending upon these other [aggregates], then
the wodd
woułd be finice.
24. Purve yadi na bhajyerann utpadyeran na capy amT,
skandhaf? skandhan prafityemiin loko 'nanto bhaved atha,
Ifthe prioraggregates were not to be destroyed and these
aggregates were
ałso not to ańsc dcpcnding upon these other [aggregates],
then the world
would be infinite.
MKV(P) p.588; MKV(V) p.256.
The above is a criticism of an explanation of the conrinuity
in the aggregaces
which does not takc into consideracion thcir causa!
depeodence. l f the aggregaces were looked upon as things that appcar and
disappear with no causa!
relations, then only can one speak ofa finite world. In
other words, the cooception of a finite world involves one of the exueme views
discussed earlier, namely, aonihilation (uccherla) .
The non-arising of the aggregates dependent upon other
aggregates would
thcn imply permanencc, and this is what is involved when one
speaks ofan infinite world.EXAMJNATION OF VJE\'(/S
25. Antavan ekadeśaśced ekadeśas tv anantavan,
syadantavan anantaś ca lokas tac ca na yujyate.
lf the world we.re to be pa~dy finice and also pardy
infinite, it would be
both finite and infinite, and this too is also not proper.
' + • '
MKV(P) p .589; MKV(V) p.256.
389
The rejection of both the finite and the infinite, the
etetnal as well as the noneternal, as constitucing the reality, was prompted by
the Buddha's refusal to
recognize two djfferent levels of reality: a changing and
finite world contrasted
with an eternal and infinite ultimate reality or an Absollłte.
As such, neither it:i
the Buddha's philosophy, nor in Nagarjuna's thinking is
thete any room for an
Absolute of any sort.
26. Katha1(l tavad upadiitur ekadeśo vinank,yate,
na nańkfyate caikadefaf? eva~ caitan na yujyate.
How can it be possible that one part of a gr:asper is
dest!oyed and the
othetpart is not destroyed. This too is not proper. ·
27. Uptidiinaikadeśaś ca katha1(l n'iima vinank1yate,
na nańkfyate caikadeśo naitad apy upapadyate.
How can it be possible that one part of grasping is destroyed
and another
part js not destroyed, This too is not appropri.ate.
MKV{P) pp.589 -~90 ; MKV(V) p.257.
Nagacjuna leaves no room for the recognitioo of an ecernal
and absolute entity
either in the person grasping (up'iidiitr) or in grasping
(upadiina).390 THE PHILOSOPHY 01' TH..E MIDDLE WAY·
28. Antavac capy anantaf?'l ca prasiddham ubhayaf?'l yadi,
siddhe naivantavat kctmanJ naivanantavad ity apz:
Supposing both the finite and the infinite are e5tabiished,
then it is not
possible to assert either the finite or the infinite.
MKV(P) p.590; MKV(Ji? p.257.
This rejeccion of the finitc and the infinite is comparabJe
to the rejection ofthe
eternal and the non-cternal (XXVIl.18).
29. Athava sarva-bhavananJ śunyatvac chaśvatadayaf?,
kva kasya ~atamal? ka.rmat sambhavi,yanti t/ufayaf?.
Thus, because of the emptiness of all existenr.s, wbere, to
whom, which
and for what reason vtews sucb as the etetnal could ever
occur?
MKV(P) p. 591; MKV(V) p.258.
The recognition of depeodencly arisen phenomeoa
(prafityasamutpanna dharma) meaos the acccpdnce of the non-substantiality or
emptioess of all these
things. If things are non-substantial, how can thcrc be
views about the eternal
and the non-ete,rnal, the finite and the infinite? The
answer to this question
has been provided by the Buddh.a and clearly .rcstated by
Nigarjuna. Tt is the
resułt of an urge on the part of human beings to find
absolute answers to ques.
tioos such as "Where did 1 come from?'' or ''Wherc do I
go fcom herc?" These
qucstioos wouJd be raised and attempts to answer them be
made so Jong as
human beings arc propeUed by a "craving for
becoming" (bhava-tr1'!ti) o~
"craving for other-becoming" (vibhava-tu'!ii) .
This was the riddle of human
existence faced by the Buddha. Understanding that riddJe of
existence, the
Buddha attained freedotn (nirva11a) by spewing out craving
(tr11iii)~ and
abandooing any grasping (upadiina).
30. Sarva-drtfi-pr11ha1faya yaf? saddharmam adeśayat,
anukampa"' upadiiya ta1{'J naffl4Syami
gautama~.EXAMTNATION OF VtBWS
I revcrcntly bow to Gautama who, out ofcompassion, bas
taught the truc
doctńne in order to rclinquish all vicws.
MKV(P) p.592; MKV(V) p.258.
391
Th.is finał statemen't of Nagarjuna referring to the
Buddha's.preachiog of the
doctrine (sad-dharma) is to be contrasted with his statement
at the end of the
chaptcr on freedom (ntrviifła)(XXV.24) , whcre he says that
the Buddha did not
"preach anything as .. ." (na ... kalcid dharmo
buddhena deiital/). and
should open the cyes of those who stick to a completdy
ncgative'interprctation
of Nagatjuna. Nagarjuna's rernarks clearly show that he was
aware thar the
Buddha did not spcak "metaphysically'' but only
"empiricalJy."INDEX TO THE KARIKA
NOMlNAL FORMS
agni (firc) X. I, 6-9. 12- 1); nirogniAa X .9
ag111 (beginning) Xl.1. 2
11;1kura (sproul)
XVIL7
alłj11ni (proposi
tion) XXV. l 5
alita (pasc)
XlX.1-3; XX.12; XXVll. l, 3, 9,
13- 14
adhama (low) XDC.4
adh1ga1t1 (attaincd, realized) XXJV.28
adh1la-ya
(obscssion) XXIV. 13
11dhya1ma
(imcrnaJ) :XVlll.4
adh111111 (time, pcńod) XXVll.1-3, 9. 14
fl'!(ll!aragrtJ (without prior end) Xl. l
anagata (future) XJX. 1- 3; XXVll 2, 14
anukampa (compusion. sympathy) X:XVJl.30
anu.van.11/a (excolkd) XVll.13
anta (end, limit, finite) XXll.12; X:XV.21, 22;
imania XXJJ.12; XXV.22; X:XVJl.24
anantaval XXV.22; XXVll.21, 22, 25 .
28
amaval XXV.22; XXVIJ. 21- 23, 25, 28
11paran111XXV.21; XXVIl .2
purvanta XXV.21 : xxv11.1
antanJ (becwccn, mcdiatc) XXV.20
atJantara (immediate) 1.2, 9
1mdhakara (darknc$S) Vll.9
a,11ya (orbc1, anothc1, differcnc) 11.8. 15. 18 ,
20. 23; VII .19, 28; IX.6, 9: X. l, 5-7;
XJl.3: XIV.3. 5-8; XVLl.4, 28, 31. 32:
XVlll. l, IO: XXII.I: XXV.23:
XXVll .7-1 1, 16
QflJOfQ X. 13
a11onya (mutU:il, togctbcr) X.7: XIV. I;
•
XXl.6
a11y11111a (differtncc) XlV. 3-4. 7: X.X, t9;
XXIl.8
a11yathiit11a
(change) .XV.9
anyathiibhiiva
(change) Xlll.;}- 6; XV.5. 8
apalu1rfant;
(climinacion) XVL. 10
apara (postcrjor) XJ.2, 6
apekfii (cootingcnt, comingencc) XX. I I
nir- (non-) Vl.3;
X.3; XV.2
apekfita11ya X.1O
abhidh"iilavya (ro be de$ignated) :XVIJI. 7
abhin11J1a (mountcd) XXIV 15
abhutva (without prior exlsrencc) XXVU. t2
abhfiigama (bcing con!rontcd) :XVll.2')
abhyupapanna (cngr<>Mccł) XXl.14
amrt11 (immonal) Xl.3: xxvn_.10
11rcifilf1.1 (fl:unc) xxvn.22
artha (fruit, cffcct, purposc, mc:injng) 1.6;
IV.2; Vl.7-8;
VUl.6; X .16: Xl.7
ekarJha (one meaning, identity)
Dedi~tory Vcrscs; XVIJl.11
'1a11ar1h11 (vllicry of mc:anings,
difference) Ocdicatory Vccses;
XVJU. l t
nairarthakyfl (futility) Vlll.6
paramiirtha
(ultimnte fruit) X:XlV.8, 10
prajfJaptyartha (purposc of dcslgnatibn)
XXII. 11
11aryar1hya (meaningless) X.2-3
alarrz (adcquarc) Vll.2
a11agiihalif!1, dur- (difficulty of undcrscanding) XXIV.17.
/
a11ara (end) Xl.1. 2
a11as1ha (state) Vll.28; XXIV.38;
avaslho XVJ.6
at1ava11hi, ana11a11hiti (infinite regress)
Vll.3. 19
aJva (horse) X:XfV. 15
a.uan;gala (rc:ichcd it's end) X:X.10
as/iii ("cxists'') XV. IO
303
flOJfiti ("docs nm cKist") XV.], 10-1 l
asti ni11fili lX.
12
a11i1va
(existcnce) V.8: XV 8, 10
XXlll.3: XXV.14
11ii11i111a (non-existcntc) V.8; 10: XXll.3
nau11'ii XV.8394 TuE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
aham iii ("l am") XVlll.4
nirahaf!'Kartz (free from cgoism)
XVUl.2, 3
iiuJa (space) V.l, 7
iiRhyiila (explaincd) Vll.14
iig11111 (come) XXVll. 19
71gl1fl'J4, an-(noo-appcarancc) DcdiC3co.iy Vcrscs
aJ11t11»!1/tMbliiiva (oanuc of coming and going)
XXV.9
iltma (self, form) IX.9; X.15, 16; XVlll.l-2, 6;
XX.5; XXlll. 3. 21- 22; XXVIl.4- 8, 12
llniltma (oc>sclf) XVIll.6; XX23: XXIJ.3;
XXlll.22
111malł.r:111 (self..caused) Xll.8
i1ma-111f{Jy111'fl!lka (sclf-n:sttaint) XVll.1
ilmanly11 XXJV. I5
iilm1J11 xvm.2
p4iiil1TNI (anothcr self) vn.25. 32
svilma (iaelf) m .2; Vll.13, 25. 32; :XX.24
$V11-pri1ma VIJ.8, 12
iitli(bcginning) Xl.l. 4
tmiitli (bcginn.inglcs.s) XXVII.19
iidhip111eyy11 (dominancc) I.2
iytilli1111 (sphercs of scruc) XIV.2; XVl.2
!4ff (six) XXVl.3
ifmhdha (initilued)
1111· (non·)
XXIV.37
4111mbh4
(commencemcnt) ll.13-14: X.2-3
iilmnbtm4
(objcctivc ruppon) 1.2, 8
iiloh (light)
XXV.14
i.fr111111
(inllux)
1111· XVIl.19
14- XVll.19
mdriya (faculty)
!Ilf/ (sile) m.1
Urtifuna (fucl) X.I. 4, ~9. U-15
idhµm;ina (buming) X.4
uuheda (annihibtioo) :>W.11; XVll.20;
XXI.14-17; XXVll.11
an- (non) Dcdicatory Vcr.scs; XVlll. I I
ucchee/a.rillTfana XV.10; XXJ.14
ucchinna
(annilulatcd) XVIl.8, 10:
XVIll.10
t111- (non-)
XXV.3
1111i1ma (highest) XIX.4
11//(lm (follc>winu\ XI.3
„
.utpitla(arising) VIJ.1- 5, 8, 13, 18-19, 25. 29,
32-34; XXJV.17
t111· (non-) Ded.IC3tory Vc.iscs; XVUI.12
mulotpiitla (primary arising) VIJ.4, 5
.utpalli(arising) VD.15-16, 20-2 I
o-p11nar-11tpt111i (abscncc of rcpcatrd
arising) XXI.16
u1ptllly11mii174 (prescndy arising) VU.7, 10,
14-16, 18
11/jxmfltl (arisco) I. I; Vll.14; XX.10
tm- (non-) l.9;
Vll.IJ..: 14, 17, 22; XVU.21;
XVlll.7; XX.17- 18; XXlll.9: XXY.3
im-.uj>Qpatti(ab.sense of arising)) V.4;
XX.22
11p11J)iltli1t1 VU..20
uihy11 (uprising) XVJ.5; XVIll. l: XXL 15-16;
XXN.l, 20; XXV. l, 2
uihyo-~111f!114na XXI. 1~16
udiihrto (cxamplified) Vll.34
utibhuti(occuuencc) Vl.3
1uibht11111 (uprising) XVU. to; XXl .2
upfllllmbha (objcct) XXV.24
uplli4"111 (appeasement)
uplllllmbhopaiama (appcasemcm of
objcct) XXV.24
tl171!{1111yop11ftlma (appeasement of
objcct) V.8
pr11paflcopaJam4 (appeasement of
obse.ssions) Dedicarory Verses; XXV.24
11ptlf11111a (appcased) XXIIJ. 15
.upiidiino (grasping) 111.8; Vlll.13; X. U ;
XVl.3, 6; XVllJ.4; XXII.7-10; X.XVl.~7 ;
XXVll.4- 8, 27
""" (non) XVl.3, 6, 9; XXVI.7
nir-(witho11~) XXII.7
upadaua (sphcrc of grasping) XXVl.6
:t1'·(spherc of
non·) XXJJ.7
11pidii1r: (graspcr) XXlf.10; X:XVL7;
XXVll.6, 26
upiyt1 (mcans) XVI!. I I
upiiyisa (dispair) XXVI.9
upiiltlmbha (ccnsurc) JV.9
up4/abtiha (ccnsurcd), a1'111pilabdh11
(unccnsurcd) IV .~.
urdhva (abovc) IX. 12
r'!a (dcbt) XVCL 14
rli! (without) 11.41 20; X.1; XIV.5, 6: XV.4;
XVI!.7, 9; XIX.6; XXU.4lNDEX 395
fdrfhi·Iamp11tliJ (psycho-kioetic power)
XVll.31
r1i (3.Scciic)
parama- (supremc-) XVll.2
eka (one)
ek.al11a (idcntiry) VI.4, 5; Vll.30; X . I ;
XIX.4; X:X.20
ek"tirtha (one meaning), an·ekanha
XVlll.11
eklbh1i11P (ideociry) 11. 19, 21
aika (identical) XXI. JO
aika111f? (co-exis1) Vlll.7
aikahla (identity) XX.19
aikya (identity) XX.20
karma (action) 11.19: Vlll.l-3; 9-13; X.l ;
XVll.2-3, 5-6. 10, 14-18, 20-23, 25-27,
29-30, 32-30; XVlll.5; XXVI.1 ; XXVII.11
-ja (bom of action) XVIl.30
-patha (path of-) XVI!. I I
-11aa'ha (destruccion of-) XVll.16
a-karmaka (withouc action) Vlll.2; X .2
kamtJa (performance of action) XXN. 17
k.
arta11ya (to be donc) XXJV.33. 37
kattr (agent) II. 19; VUJ.2-4, 8, 13; X. I;
XVIl.28-30. 32-33; XXIV.17
kartrka, li· (withoUl agem) VUl.2
karaka (agent) Vlll.l, 3. 7, 9- 12;
XXIV.37; X.XVI. IO
ak11r111if!a (noo-accing) XXIV.37
kfira'!a (causc, sufficiem condicioo)
IV.1-4, 6: Xl.7: XXIV.17
ni[- (withOUI·) lV.5
karya (effecr) łV .6; Vlll.4; Xl. 7; Xll. l;
XXIV. 17
a-kiiryaka (in-effcn-ivc) IV. 3
kr1a (donc,
causcd) Xll. 1-4. 7-9:
XVll.24, 32;
XXVIl.5, Il
a- (not·) XVIJ ,22, 23
krta.k.a (made) XV 1-2; XVIL23;
XXVll.12
J.ririma, 11-
(un·made) XV,2
kriyfi (activity) 1.4; Vlll.2, 4-6;
XXIV. 17, 37
kalpa (fabricarion) XXll.9
kalpan?i (thoughr) IX,12, XVU.12, 13
11i-k.alpa (discrimination) IV.5
11U11;/pa1af? (one who disc.riminates)
XVlll.5
11lr-11ikalpa (without discrimination)
XVlll.9
11ikalpaya~ (discrimioatjng) XXII. H
!ll"J?l·kalpa {thought) xxm:1
Kiityfiyanilvavada (Admonition 10
Katyliyana) XV.7
klima (plcasuce, dcsirc)
·KUf!ll (strands of-) XVU.11
kfiyika (bodily) XVI13
ki/a(timc)XVll.6; XIX. I, 3, 5-6; XXl.21
ella- (comcmporaneous) XX.7
111/ya- (nmc·)
XXJ.3
nirv1ir/a·
(-offrccdom) XXI. t7
kfl(.:utha (remaioing immutabłe) XXJV. 38
ke11ala (cxclusivcly, cntirely. otll) VU.4; X.l.8;
Xll.10; XlV.4: XXlll.8: XXVI.9, 12
koti (cxtrcmiry, end) XI. I, 8; XXV.20
krania (mcthod, mode) fV.7; VI.2; X .n ;
XVI. I; XIX.4
puniaparasaha-krama XI.2. 6
klei (defilemcor, impurity) XVIl.26-27, 33;
XVU.5: XVlll.5; XXJll.2-6, 24-25
k/11fii1maka (defiling natwe) XVll.26, 27
-praha'!a (diminatioo, relinquishing)
XXIV.39
klifta (ddiled) XXJll.5
R,t:ya (waning) XVIU .4-), 12; XXI.7
a- (not·) XXl. 7
k[lr111 (waned) XVIJl.4
ki'ira (milk) XIIl,6
gamana (movemcm) 11.3-7, 9-11, 13-14 ,
16-20, 24-25
a- (non-) 11.3
gamyam1ina (presenr moving) 11. 1- 5,
12- 14, 17; llł.3; Vll.14; X.13: XVI.7
gala (mo~·ed) Jl. I- . 12-14, 17; lll .3:
Vll. 14: X.13; XVl.7
fi· (un·) 11.1-2,
12-14, 17; 111.3; Vll. 14:
X. 13; XVl.7
gati (morion) 11.2, 4, 17-18, 20, 22-23,
25; XXVI.J-2
gat11411Jll (space to be: movcd) li.n
gani(' (movec)
11.6-12, 15-16, 18- 20,
22- 25
a- (non-) 11.8. 15
, 20
gandha (smell) XXJJI.7-8
gandharva11agara (city of the gandha.rva)
•396 THE PHlLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
Vll.34: XVlt33: XXIU.8
gambhlra (profound) XX.IV.9
grhita (grasped) XXll tl3: XXlll.1.5
a- (non-) XIX..5
d11r- (wrongly-) XXIV+li
gocara (sphcre) IfJ, l
c1iia- (-of rhought) XVIII.7
Gautama XXVIl.30
graha (grasping, hold) XVI.9
a- (non-) XVI.9
griiha (grasping)
XXJJ. l3 ; XX.ID.13-16
ghatan (conrcnd) XXJV.32
ghana (substandał) XXII 13
ghfii11a (smdling) 111.1, 9
ca,t!u·(cye)
111.7; X..XVJ.4-3
ttJrama (łase)
XXI.18-19
ca1tirt1tdhya
(fourfold mcthod) Xll. IO
ciita (thought) IV.7: XVll.9-10: XXIV.12
-gocara {spherc of-) XVIII.7
-IDf?11'iina (-scrics) XVU.9
cettna/; (from thought) XVIJ.9
c1#ta (rhough1) XXli, 14
cet11na
(vołitioo) XVll.2,3,5
ce1fii (efforc)
li.2
chedana (cuning) Vll.31
/agat (univcrsc) XX0. 16; XXJV.38
janma (birth) XVfil.4; XXl.2-3. 5
punar· (re-) XX.9
purva- (prcvious-) XXVIL3, 9
janaka (producer) XX.7, 20
a-jamia (not produccd) Vll.5
janya (co~ produced) XX.10
janyamona, a- {not produdng) XX.22
jiit11 (bom)
Vll.13; XX .6, 12- 14
a· (un-, fururc)
VU.26; Xl.4; XX.12- 14;
X:Xlll.19;
XXJV.38
Jtili (blrch)
Xl.3-6; X.XVl.8-9
jifyamana (being boro) XI.~; XXI.19-20
Jana (peopfe) XV.5
jrmt11 (scmient being) XVJI. 28
jara (dccay. -age) Vll.24: Xl.3-6; X.XV 4;
XXVJ.8
jit1a (vocwrlous one) XIII.8
J1rf!a (aged) XIll,5
jfliina (wisdom) XVlll.12; XXVl.11
la1J1111 (icsclf.
1ruth, idemi1y) XV.6; XV!lf.9;
XXII.8; XXIY.9
ta1111ala~ ("in icself") XVI! .26; XXlll . 2
/llttva-tlariana (perccpcioo of truth)
X.XVI.IO
lathya (sucb) xvnts
a-(not-) XVl!I.8
1111hiiga1aXX.Jl.1 , 3-8, IO, 13, 15-16
lama (darkness) Vll.9-12~ XXV.14
t1roJkr1a (scparaced) VJ.1; X .7; XXVJJ.20
ti!fhrJn (enduring) XX. LO
l1[!hamona Vll.22; XXV.18
111/ya (cqual. same) XX.20; XXl.3
trfT{ii (craving) XVll.28; XXVl.6
f(!Jamana XXVI.6
darfan11 (secing. pcrccption) 111.1-6, 8-9;
l.X.1-4, 6-7, 1~12; XIV.l
11- (not-) 111.5
darśana (view, mctaphysica l view)
XXI.14; XXVH; 14
du!a, dur- (wrongly perceived) XXJV.l l
dr!!i (view) XIH.8; XXVIL l-2, 13.
29- 30; s11akaya· XXllf.5
drfyamiina, a- (nor being perccived)
11.14
dra.ff( (scer) IJf.5-6; JX.8-9; XIV. l
41-a,rtavya (objcct of seefng) 111.l, 6, 8;
XJV.l, 3-4
drał(avyopt11ama (sec upalam.a)
tlahana (burning), '1'" X .5
dipa (lamp) VJl.9; XXV!l.22
duqkha (suffedng. unsacisfacrorin~) Xll. J.
3-10; XXlll.22; XXIV.21 , 23, 25, 39-40:
XXVI.8- 9, 12
dofanta (example) 111.3
dew (divine being) XXVII.15-16
divya (clivioc) XXVIl. l7
defrma (1caching) XXIV.8
defita (caughc) XVll.20; XVJU.6;
x:xv. 24
deóa (body) XVI!. 27. H
do1a (error, faulr) VJil.8; XVU. 12. 16.
23; XXJV.1.5; XXVll.12
do!a-prasai1ga XXlV, U
daurmanasya (dejccilon) XXVI.9
dviialJ (pairs) XIV. L
d11c1a (hacred) XXOI. l, 7. 12INDEX 397
dharma (ching, nature) I.7-9; XVll.5;
XXlV.19; X.XV.24
/ariimara'!a· (nacurc of dccay and dca,th)
Vll.24
drffa- ( • druaJanman, prcscm life)
XVll.18
fłi· ( distinct chings) V,6
1arva- (all·) Vl.10: Vll.29: X:XV.22
dharma (good)
Vlll.5: XVU .l , il ; XXIV.6,
33-;5
a· (bad) Vlll.5; XXIV.6, 33-35
dharma (doctrinc) XVll.20; XXJV.5, 12
sad- (true-) XXlV.4, 30; XXVU.30
-deiana XXJV.8
dharma!?
(conccpts) XXUI.7-8
dharma/ii. (nature
of things) XVUl.7
dharmin, udaya-vyaya- (nature of arising
and ccasiog) XVI.5
dhatu (element) XVl.2
panca· (fivc-) V.7
far! XVll.17
naya (mcthod, modc), a/mam- XVlll.2
rfi1nli (differcnt) XXl. 10
-bhli11a (differcncc) li.21
nanlirtha, a· (without a varicty of
mcaoings) XVlll.9
nimariipa (psychophysicaJ pcisooaliry)
XXVl 2-4
nilia (dcstrutcion) XX.VII. I I
''Offa (dcnroycd " past) X:X.14
riii1t1ifi
(non-cicistcncc) XV.8
na1ffti
("does not exiJt'') XV.10-11 ;
X:Xll 13
flitya (pcrmancm.
etcmal) X.2-3; XVI. I;
XXl.14; XXIU.13- 14, 22
a- X:Vl .1; XXl. 14; XXlll.13- 14, 22:
XXJV.21
nityalii (pcrmancncc) XVll.6
a- (impcrmancncc) )QQ.4
nimitta, dharmiidharma· (occasiohccl by good
and bad XXJV.34-n
mroa'ha (cessation, ccasing) 1.9; Vll.27,
29-32; XXJV. 17, 23. 25. 40; XXV. 1- 2;
XXVJ.11- 12
a- (non·) Dcdicatory Vcrscs
parr11~ nirodhad (aftcr death) XXll.14;
XXV. l7, 21
nirodhana (ccssacion) XXIII .23
m·ruddha (ceascd) VlJ.26: XVll.6;
XX.5-6; 10; XXl.18; XXUl.23;
X.XV!. I I
a- (not·, oon-) Vll.26; >.'VIIJ.7;
XX.17-18; XXJ . 18; XXIV.38; XXV.3
nirudhyamiina (ccasing) Vll.21.2},26;
XXl.19-20
a- (oon-) Vll .21, 23
'!irgama, 11 (non-disappcar'lnct) Dcdic-.uory
Vcrscs
nirmila (crcared) XVI!. 31, 32
m'rmitaka XVJl.31
nirmuakakiira (crcatcd form) XVll.32
nirmimita XVU.31
nirmukta (distinct from) IV. I, 2; V.5; X.X.8
11i- IV.3
'
m"rllartaka (producing) I.7
niffla'!a (frecdom, cessation) XVl.4, 9-10;
XVlll. 7; XXl.17; XXIV. 10, XXV. l- l6;
19-21
a- (that wbich docs noi ccase) X.5
nmtrkl (cc:asc:d) XX1I. n
fli11rta (cnvclopcd) XX.VI. l
11ir1Jr1ta (rcnounccd) rx.12
11ivr11a
(cc:asc:d) XVIII.7
niJcaya (cercain)
XXVll.8
nl!panna (accomplishcd) X.8
flil/1arana (1clinquishing) Xlll.8
pa)ąa (view, position) li. 10
pa~ (cloth) X .15
patlrrl (promissory notc) xvn.14
para (ocher) 111.2; V.7; Xll.3, 7-8
pańin11grii/xJka (bcncfittiog ochcis)
XVll.l
-kara (ca.using by-) Xll.9
-krta (Cllused by-) X.Il. I , 3, 7- 8
-pudgala (-person) Xll. )-6
pamta~ (from anothcr) I.I ; XXl.1 3
paratra (dscwhcrc) X.3; XV.2
parabhava (othcr-oacurc) I.3: XV.3-4 , 6:
XXll.2- 4, 9
paraspara (mucually) Vl.3
paramartha (ultimate ftuit) XXIV.8, 10
pankTr1i1a (cxpounded) XVIl.2
parig(h'!ata4 (one who upholds) XXIV.28
parljilii (undcrst~nding) XXIV.2. 27
panjfl'iia (under$tanding) XXIV.26
11· XXJV. 26398 THE PH!WSO!'HY OF THE MIDOLB WAY
paniliptda (1lluminating) Xlll.1
paride11ana, sa· (Jamcncation) XXVl.8
pan·/iiitaytm (attributing) XX'JV.15
paribhoga (experience, enjoymcnt) XVll.5;
X.XVU.ll
padvartal:a (1clacc:d) XIX,4
pan·hilra (rcfut:u.ion) TV.8
parihrta, a- (unrefutcd) IV.8
parya11os1hina (adhering) XXIV.23
paryi1pta (adequa1c) lll.3
pa!ciiJ (posterior} XI.4
pafcima (cod) XI.l
ptiiya"1iina, 11- (noc pecceiving) 111.4
pika (m11.turing) XVIl.6
putJya (merle) XVJL5, 24
a· XVII.5
putra (son) lU.7
pudgala (pct!lon)
XII.4-6; XVl. 2
puru1a· XXTV.4, 29
purufa (man) X6
-pudgala XXJV.4. 29
purra (prior)
Jl.13; V.1; Vl. t ; l'X.6-8; X.8;
XJ.1-3, 6, 8;
XV.Il ; XVl.7; .XX.8-9;
XXVU .2)-24
PrthaJ:
(discrctc. scparacc:) Vl.8; X. l6
·lllfJ (discrcrcnC3s) Vl.4-7; XX.20
, -bhiiva (discretcness) VJ.6-7, 9
prakaia
(illuminacion) Vll.9
prakrti (pramal
narure) XV.8- 9; XVll.14
pr.1j1JajJl i
(eommunicatiofl, &on 11en1ion)
XXJ/.l/
upiidiiya
(dcpcndcn~) XXlV.18
pmtipa,, madhy@iii (mi6dłe path) XXlV.18
pra1ipanflaka (rcachcd the way) XXlV. 3, 29
pmtibiidhatal, (one who concmdicts)
XXIV.22, 37
pralibimba (mirror image) XXIU.9
prat1u1thitP (sicuatcd) Vll.9
prPtisandhi (moment of conccp1ion) XVll. 17
prati!iddhP (rcfu1ed) V.7
prafi1yosamulpiida (depcndcnt u ising)
Dedica1ory Vcrscs; X.XIV. 18, 36, 40
pmlJllJfJ (condi1ion) l.3, 5- 6. !>. 11- 14;
XV. I; XVJJ,27 . 29; XX, 1- 4. 8, 23;
X:XVl.2, 6
a- (0011-) 1.5, 12, 14; XVll.29
t1/JPrt1· (indcpendcmly reaJized) XVJJI.9
· nhZJll (made of-) 1.1 3-14
-siimagn (harmony of-) XX.24
-11.zff (constinucd of-) 1.4
&alfliiml? (four) I. 2
pratyikhyiiya (fot!lak.ing) XXVll.10
pralyulua (ccfuted) lll.3
pratyulpanna (prcscnt) XlX. 1- 3
prPtyudiivrtta (cccoilcd) XXJV.12
pradipa (lighr) Vll.8-12
pradipta (aflamc)
X.2- 3
propaflca
(obscssion) XVIU.) , 9
-alila (gone beyond-) XXIl.15
-hata (impaired by-) XXll. 15
-opaśama (appe:tScment of·) XXV .24
pmpancita, a- (unobsesscd) XV!ll.9
prt1brti (bcgins wich) XV!l . 7
prabóaVtJ (sourtc} XXI!l. I
pmyojana (purpose) xxrv.7
pravrlli
(occuucoce) V.3
pnzfalua
(implied) li. 5-6
pmsPnga (accompanying, following) XXIV.13
praiadhi1a, tiul· (wrongly cultiva1cd)
XXIV .1I
prasiddha (cstablished) XXVl!.18, 28
pra1iddhi (cscablishmcnt) IJl.3; Vl.8-9
a· (non·) VTI.33; XJl.7; XV. ~
prahli'!a (relinqu.ishiog) XVLl.15-16; XXlV.2,
21, 39; xxv.1- 2, 10; xxvu .~o
prah1'1a, P· (unrclinquishcd) XXV.3
pr/Jh11ya (10 bt
rdinquisncd) XVll.15-16
piiik (pl'ior) IX.1- 3. 12
praptP, a- (nor rc:ichcd) X.5
prip1; (ceaching) X.XIV.39
baddba (bound) XVl.8
bandhP (bondagc)_ XVl.8
bandbana XVl.6-7
bahirrihli (cxternal) XVlll .4
bahu (many) xvn.12
·lllP (pluraliry) IX.9
bahya (cxccrnal, Olhcr) XJJ .10
b/jP (sccd) XVIl.l, 7-8
b11ddh1Z XVll.I;, 20, XVlll.6, 8. 11; XXIJ.2.
L4- 15; XXlV.5, 8, 30-31 ; XXV.24
·fiisana (Buddha's mcssagc) XV.6;
XXlV,9
a- (unenllghtcncd) XXJV32
pmtyeliP· (self-enlighic.-ned) XVll. 13;
XVlll.12
sarn· (pcńoctly cnligh1enc.-d), Dc:dica1ory
Vcrscs-; XVIII. 12INDEX 399
b1uldhi, alpa- (meager imdligcncc) V.8
bodhi (cnlightenment) XXIV.31- 32
bodhilatllla, -caryo (c21ccr of a bodhisanva)
XXIV.32
broh111acarya1 a- (ignoble life) XVll .23
bruv'iiTfa (speaking} xxrv»
bhagaviin (blcsscd one) Xlll.1- 2; XV. 7;
XXV.17-18
bhanga (dcstruction) Vll.3. 33- 34
bha11a (becoming) XXI.18; XXV.10;
XXVl.7- 8
·SllfJJlllli (sueam of-) XXl.17, 21
vi- (other-, dissolution) XVl.3; XXI.1-5,
7- ll; XXV.10
punar- (re-) XXVl. l
bhava (cxistcnt, existence) l. l , 3, JO; IV.7;
V.2. S-8; VIL ,17, 21, 23-24. 27, 30-31;
Vlll. B; IX.2-3; X .10-11, 16; XJ.8;
XJl.lO; Xlll.3; XV.4-7; XJX,6: XXl.4, 8,
12- 16; XXJll.20; XXIV.16; X:XV.4-7,
10-16; XXVII.29
a· (non·,
abscncc) V. 6-7. 30; Vlil.4:
XV.3, 5-7;
XXl.12; XXIV.l-4, 20,
29-30; XXV.8.
10-16
bhavaniJ
(cultivation) XVll. l~ ; XXIV.2, 24.
27: XXVl.11
bhuta
(clc:mc:nrs) lX.10
bhuta (come to be) XXlll. 24
a- XX!ll.25
bheda (distinct v:uicties) XVIJ.2
bhoktr (cxpericnccr) XVIJ.28, 30
rnadhya (middle) XJ.2
marlhyama XJX.4; XXIV. 18
'11111111 {mind) m.1, 9
mar1ufy11 (human) XXVU. l}- 16
mil#Ufa XXVll.17
mam/a (me:igcr incc:Wgcncc) XXIV. 12
-medhasa XXJV.11
mama
mamefi ("mine") XVlll.4
nlr- (free from sdf1Shne.ss) XVUl,2-3
ma!'tlf!11 (death) Vll.24; Xl.3- 6: XVl1:19;
XXl.2- 3, 5; XXV.4; XXVl.8
maffci (miragc) XVll.33: XX!Jl.8
mahan111 (grcat) XVII.12
miiliipi1arau {mothcr and father) 111.7
miinaJll (mcnal) XVll.3
marga (path) VID.6; XXJV.24-25; 40
miiy'ii (ilłusion) Vll.34; XXlll.9
milhyl (wrong) xxrn.16
mucyamiin11 (frccing) XVl.8
muni (sagc) XXIV.12
maha- (great-) Xl.1
mu/4 (sourcc) XXVl.10
mrgyamilf!11 (sought for) XVl.2; XXU.8
mrfil (ddusion) Xlll.1-2
medha1 (inrcUigcncc) XXJV.I I
maitro (fricndly) XVll. l '
rno/qa (rtlca.$c) Vlll.6; XVlll.); XXV.11
mo1f11'!a XVl.8
mofa-dh11rma (dcccptivc nacurc) Xlll. l- 2
moha (confwfoo) XXI.Il; XXXIJl.l. 7
11111u/11 (prima.cy) VII.4-6
yukta (propcr) l.9; Vl.;; VII. I~ XV, I ; XXl.21
yugapad (sirnulcaneous) XVl.8
yu11a (young) Xlll.5
rakla (lustful) Vl .1-3. 6-7, 10; XIV.2
ra1Jj11n1ya (objcct of Lust) XIV. 2
flllna (jcw(ll) XXJV.5
rasa (tascc) XXJll.7-8
flUl11711 Ili. l
, 9
rahita (dcvoid)
XXIV.38
r.iga(lusc)
Vl.1-3, 6-7, 10; XIV.2; XXJII.l,
7. 12
riipa (m11ccria.I
fonn) !11.7; N .l- 5, 7; XXIIL7;
:XXVl.4-5
liil:sana (characccristic/ V.1- ). 7; VII. I; Xl.7;
XVlll.9; xxv.4
a· (without·) V.1-3
11Jkandha- (-of non-aggrcgatc) XVlll.2
sarpskrta· (of the conditioocd) Vll.1, 3
-karrnanl (function as-) VII.2
/11kf11'!1, tri- (having duce charactcristirs)
VII. I .
lakfya (ch:uutcriz.cd) V.5, 7; XI.7
liriga, SI/O·
(owo matk) X.5
loka (world) X:XVll.21, 23-2)
para· (other-) XXVU .21
-ni1tha (pattoo of the-) xvm .11
-sarrivrti (worldJy coovcntion) XXIV.8
/auAika (worldly) XXIV.6, 36
vak111vya (to be dcdatcd) X:Xll. 11
11a1111 (foundation) XXUI.7
viik {word, speech) XVll .4400 THE PHILOSOPHY OP nm MIDDLE
wAy
v'iicika (vetb21) XVII.3
'var/41i1(1 (spcak.cc), Dcdkatory Vcrscs.
Vtmlf!J (best), Dedicatory Vccscs
11iuk.f111!a (discerning person) XV.10
vigraha (analysis) N .8
11id1ra (vc:riegatcd) XXIV.38
11i}llllp1i, a- (n.on-mtimation) XVIJ.4
flijlliinfl (consciousncss) fil.7-8:
XXVI.2, 4-)
vitijflrni11111 (cvidcnt) XXIV.22
fi· (not·) 1.3; V.6; IX.2; XI\1.7;
XXIIL 12, 16
11itlyii (knowledgc) XXIV.11
11- (ignonncc) XVU.28; XXIII.23;
XXVI.1 , 11
J1itl11il# (wise
ooc:) XXVI.10
a· (ignorant one) XXVL.10
11inii (without) Vl.5; IX.4-5 ; Xll.5-6;
XX.24; XXI.1-2, 4, 6, 8; XXlll>-4.;
XXV.4
11initmtd111 (separatcd) ll.1; XXVIL4-5
11ip111114 (sub)ect to perversfon) XXIU.17
a- (not·) XXIIl.17
11i.łparyflya (pcrversiOJJ) XXIlI.6, 1}-14.
16-2 1, 23
a- (non-) XXIJL
16
flipary'iisa
(pc:rversion) XXIII.1- 2
11ip1Jry4Sjaf!iiina (being subject to
pervcrsion) XXII!. 18
flipiilł:a (maturiry) XVII. 25
l'iptmvfl (marurcd) XVII.18, 2~
11ijm1'!iiifl, 11- (impcrlshable) XVll.14- 15 , 20
vibha1111 (sec bh1111a)
11ibl/ilgt1
(distinction) XVIl.19; XXIV.9
prtwi· (XVll.24
·vibhaviil (adept) X,V.7
111roli
(non-dclight) X:VU.4
11- (delight) XVII.4
vbuadha, par'1Jp11r11- (sclf-conrradictory)
VIU.7
11iie!"1!" (distinguishing) XXV. 19
tiiglhatui11 (dced) XVll.4
11rl4 (separatc<l) XX.10
fi· (DOt·)XX.U
vedako (feclcr) IX.8-9; XI.7
vet/ana (feeling) JV.7; IX.I, 3, 10-11; XI.7;
XXVI.5-6 •
vdiyt1rlhya (see 11rlha)
tlyatiArat114 (incerruption) XVll. 19
11yaya (ceasing) XVI.); XVlil. l ; XXl.15-16;
XXJV. l , 20
a·(comtant)
XXII.15
vya1111Jthi'4
(dctermined) IX. 2-4; XVU.25
vyflflahiinr(convencion)
XVI1.24; XXlV.10
IO'!J XX1V.6, 36
vyasth4 (scparaced) l.11; VII.2
11jiillr1a. a· (indcccrmlnate) XVll.14'
11jiillhya111 (explained) Ill.:>, 9; X.15
11jiillhyiin11 (cxplanation) IV.9
'JUtsarga (rejeccion) Vlll. H
i11bda (sound) XXlll.7
ft1ma (appea.scmcnr) XVIlf.2
Pl'fl· XXl.17
iinltl (pcaccful) Vll.16; XVlll.9;XXII.12
1"iJiwll4 (ctcmii!, etemalism) XY.11; XVD.8, 10,
20, 23; XVlll.10; XXI.14-15; XXII.12;
XXV.21, 23; XXVIl.15, 17-18, 20, 29
fi· (not-, non-) Dedkatory Verses)
XVIIl.11; XXIL12; XXV.3, 23;
xxvu. 16-18, 20
-lou (-"Vo.rld) xxvn.1
~gr11h11 (grasping after-) XV. IO
Jiisl11'a (mcssage) X.16; XVlll.11
· b11ddh11- (Buddha's-)XV.6; XXIV.9
anu· (admonition) XVIll.8
I 'iisJr (teacher) XVll.31~ :XXV.10
Jir11Ja~ (head) Vll.31
fiw (auspicfous), Dcd.icatory Vc:rscs; V.8;
XXV.24
ftll/11 (pure) XVIJ.11
i11r;i (pleasant) XXlll.21- 22
11- (unpleasant) XXIII.22
finy11 (cmpty) XIII.7; XVU.27; XX.16, 18;
XXl.9; XXll.10, 14; XXlll. 13-14;
XXIV.l, 13-14; XXV. 11 22
il· (non·)
XIII.7; XX. 16'-17; XXl.9;
XXIV.19-20, 33.
35, 39; X:XV.1
fiiny11m iri
("empty") XXIL11
·fil (cmptincss)
IV.8-9; Xlll.2-3, 8;
XVIl.20; XVlll.5;
XXIV.6-7, u,
B-14, 18, 22, 36-37
-14rtha (mcaning of>-) XXJV,7
-wa (cmptiness) XXVU..29
i ubha(pleasant) XXIII.l- 2, 6, 9-12
a- (un·)
XXIll.l-2, 6, 9-12
iou (grld) XXVI.s
Jm111111 (hearing) lll.l, 9: IX.1. ·3. 10-11INDEX 401
iiilv11k.il (disciplc) XVD.13; XVlll.12
iro111t1111 (sound) 111.9
irotr (hcarc.r) IX.8-9
s1111,1yd (rightly, completcly) XXIJl.16;
XXVI. 12
s1111,11111'111U (rcsuainc) XVU.l
11111,1yoj11n11 (fctter) XVll.28
s1111,111rti (convemion) XXJV.8
111'!J111Jt1 (doubt, uoccru.inty)
11- (undoubtcdly, c.cnainly Vll.12; IX.4;
XVIl.22
"" (wlchout doubt} XVU.24
Sllf!Ullrlln (moviog) XVl.3
Sllf!ISllfill (a5.50Ciacioo) XIV.I, 3, 8
a· (w1iho11J.) XVlll.2
saff.11int (łifc-proccss) XI.1. 8; XVI. IO;
XVll.20; XXV.19-20; XXVl.10; XXVU.19
11111,ll.Ura (dispositioo) IV.7; X.Jl!.I; XVJ. l,
4-); XXJil.23: XXVl.1-, 10--11
Stlff.'14{111 (conditioncd) Vll.l- 3, B;
XXV.), 13
li· (un-) Vll.l .
33; X:XV.) , 13
saf!Jf/"llł{ll (agem of2SS0Ciation) XIV .8
St1ff.1Jr.iJt1m4n11 (2.SWCiatlng) XIV.8
I"f!ISr/{il (associ11tcd) XIV.8
Ja~l'Omll (wuuformacion) XVU.16
st1f(lkntmą11 XX.9
s11f?1g11ti (assemblage) XX.12- 14
s11rriJlli1 (pcrccption) IV. 7
J'"!f/llit11 (dcslgmm~d) XVIJ.4
Sllf!1141i (sucam, contlnuity) XXVll. 16
bha1111· (-of bccoming) XXJ.17, 21
I11f!Jli1111 (serics) XVU.7-10; XXVJl.22
'"/6Jl1·VJllJl1· (·ofacising and ccasing)
XXJ.15-16
•1at(cxis1cnc1)
l.6-8: Il.li; VU.20; 30: VlIJ.7,
XVll.6
11· (non·) 1.6-7,
12: Vll.20 , 31;
Vlll.7-8, Il
-111111~11'!1
(substantiality) X. 16
.Ja (existcoce)
1.10
-111'1 (scmiem
bcing) XVI. I , 4-~
-bho11a
(existcncc) XXJ.17; XXlV.6, 16
4··bliii11a
(non·existencc) XXJ.17:
XXJll.n
-bhu111 (come to be , real) Jl . 24-2~;
Vlll. 1-2, 7. 9-1 I
1P-bhu111 Il.24-2): VUJ. I, 3, 7, 9- ll
IRii (locarivc case of 11111111, pr.p. of 1111)
I.IO; IV.4: Vl.1- 2, 9: IX.9; X.2, 9;
XV.4, 9; XX . 1~ ; XXJV.16, 24;
XXV. 15; XXVl.7: XXVJI.~
fi· 11.7; 111.6: V.2; Vl.2; Vll.17;
Vtll.4-6: XV.9; XVll.30; XX.15;
XXJV. ~
Jfl/J'1, iry11- (ooblc troth) XXJV. l-2, 4.
20, 30
ti11e (rwo) XXIV.8-9
lou·sllf!l•rli· (-rclating to wocldly
convention) XXIV.8
p11ramiirthal'11j (-in terms of ultimacc
fruit) XXIV.8
s11tir!11 (idcnc.ical) JV.6
fi· (not·) JV.6
Jll"!nipii111 (occurrrcnce) XXVJ .5
Illf!tnibha (rcscmble) XXJIJ.8
Jllf!1Prakiii11Yilii (illuminatc) VIJ.8
lllf!IP'""rlli
(commeoccmcnt, occurrcncc)
u.17
• '1· (non-) V.4
.
lflf!'Priip1111
fi· (noc rcacbed) XXJV.39: XXV.3
Jt1f!Jbh111111 (birth, occurrcnce) 111.7; V.4:
XV.I; XXJ. 1-~; 7-11: XXVl.3. 9
111".'bhim (occurrcd) XV.1; XXVll.12
111bhaga (simila.r) XVJI. 17
11i· (dissimiłar) XVlI.17
s1m111 (comparablc, cqual) 11. 17; lV.8-9;
VJ.2: XVl.2; XX.4: XXIJl.9; XXVJJ.14
saman11ihiil'l1 (attcntion) XXV1.4
sam'1Jl'1 (combined) l.11 ; Vll.2
1am1111111thita (ftxcd) XXJV.26
sam4ropa (atuibutioo) XVJ.10
JRmain'lll (associaterl} XXV.21
sam1111hi111, Rpratyay11· (issuing fonh from a
OOO·COndition) XVJl.29
11Jm111p11111111 (uisen)
prafftJ1J· (depc:ndently-) XXIV.19. 21
praty11y11- (-from a condition) XVll.29.
tihllrm4tihimna· (-from good and bad)
XXIV.3 ~
samutpatia (arising)
pr11fity'1 (dcpc:ndcot-)(sec prRl1/ya)
samutiaya (arising) XXJV.22. 25, 40
samudilhrt11 (sptcificd) XVU.27
Jflm11tibh'iita (cmcrgcnt) XXVll.12
111m11pi n'111 (a530Ciatcd) XXVll.1- 2
a· (non-) VJU.5; XXVI.11402 THE PHllOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE WAY
Jlll'Pll (snalcc) XXIV.11
s-iJ (all, cvciything) IV.7-9; VTI.19, 29;
VIIl.8; IX.6-7; X.U; Xlll.l; XIV.l;
XVll.17-18, ~4; XVlll.8; XXll.15;
XXIl!.15; XXIV. l, 6, 14, 20, 36, 39;
XXVl-2, 24
·Ariji (·acrivlcy) Vlll.6
-Rufi (·view$) Xlll.8; XXVlI.30
-dh11fl'J'UI (·things) Vll.29; XXV.22
-bhi1111 (-cxisrcncc) VU. 24; Xl.8,
XXVU.29
-Iw (-in the wodds) VII'. 11
s~111hi (everyway) ll. 14
111ha (with, togcthcr, simułtancous,
coocomitant)
Vl.3, JO; XI.5; XXI.I, 3,
5-6
11· (without)
VI.10
J11habl:la1111
(co-existence) VI.4-9
iiiltrirb/t111111
(rcalizatioo) XXJV.'27
. iiill[ilt11rm11
XXIV.2
rjitlhaflll (proof, achicving) X .9; XVll.11
iiitlhyll (10 be provcd) IV.8
a- (iocorrigiblc) Xlll.8
iii11J11gfi (harmo.ny) XX.l-4, 7-8, 23-:Z4
proty11ya- (-of conditions) XX.24
·ltrttJ (made by-) XX.24
sif!tpru'°~ (slmultancous) IX. 12
iiirdhaf?J, (togct:hcr, jointly) X.lS; XIV.4;
XXl.20
1it/</h4 (cstablislied, PtOvcd) VI.6-7; X.9. 11;
XXV.U; XXVll.18, 28
11- (not·) X.11
si<ldhi
(csrablishmcm).II.21; VI.10; VIIf.12;
XlX.3; XXJ.6
a- (non-) Vll.33
pra- Vl.8
1u@T~(head)
VIJ.31
rulthll (happy) XXI11. 21-.22
111suAfm11 (subtlcst) XXV.20
slmdha (aggregaccs) Xll.2; XVI.2; XXI.20;
XXll.l-2, 5-6;
XXVU.22-24
11- (non-) XVIII.1
d11f?ltń11- (ma.u of suffccing) XXVI.9. 12
p11flca· (fivc-) XXVl.8
·viin (posses.«:d of-)"X:xU.l
slfi (woman) f'.6
slhlina
(enduraiicc) vu.2~. 34
J1hit11 (codurcd,
static) VlI.27
t1· VII.27; XIX.5
-bhiva vn.22
slhifi (duratlon,
stasis) Vll.3, 23, 2), 33
spańll (roucb,
roocact) XXIIl. 7-8; XXVl.5
Sllf!I• XXVl,3
sparś11'!a (toucb.ing) 111.1, 9
1mr1a (reminisccd) XVIl.3-5; XVUI. l l
vi- (co.ofused) XXlV.U
1v11 (own)
-/a(from irsclf) 1.1; XXl.13; xxm.20
-pudgtlla (-person) XIl.4
sv11pn11 (dream) VJI.34; XVll.33; XXIll.8
w11/:/Jii11a (sdf-nature) 1.3; XIIl.4; XV. 1- 4; 6,
11; XVll.22; XX.21; XXl.17; XXll.2 , 4,
9. 14, 16; XXlil.2, 6, 24-25; XXIV.16,
2Z-24, 26, 28, 32-33, 38
wrJbhii11111ilf? (inhctcntly) Vll.16
s11iibh'ii11ilt11 (posst'S$ing sclf-narure)
XVU.25
li· (wichout·)
Xlll.3
11il?- (devold
of•) 1.10; XVll.21; XXll.16
11if?11111bh'ii1111tva (abscasc of sclf-narurc)
Xlll.3
svay~ (self, oncself, own) X:Xlll.18
-ltiira (-causing) Xll.9
·krt11 (·Ca\ISed) Xll,1-2, 4, 7-8
-maya (made of.) I.13
11111rg11 (hcavcn) Vlll.6
hetu (cawc, ca11$al, rcason) 1.2, 7; VUl.4,
9-11; XV.1; ~1-6,
8- 16. 19-23
d· (non-) I.I ;
XX.20; XXJV.16
helultil X.2.-3;
XX.5
a· VIU.:3;
XI.4-5; XII. l, 9; XX.6, 8;
XXVII.12
11he1111t11 IV.2
·tvll(causal efficacy) XX.22
heya {to be rcliaquished) XVII.15
VERBAL FOR.MS
ajyate (mll,dc knowa) IX.5-6; XXV.16
ade1ayal (taught) XXVII.30
adhigamifjyaJi (will anaia) XXIV.32
lldhigamyale (is act:aincd) XXJV.10
anupaiy111i (perccive) XXIV.16
apekfya (bcing eontingcnt} X.8- 12; XIX.1-2
llfl· X.12; XIX.3; XXIIl.10-11
11bhiifala (has said) XID .1
abhipravarlale
(procced) 1.12; xvn,7' 9;
XXVl,12
TJbhitaf!JJkurule
(forms) XXVl.1INDEX
abhi~11m, 11hhum
(I cxisccd) XXVU. I , 3,
9. 13
1111aiJi (comprchcnd) V.6
aga&&hati (comes) x.n
ag11rnj11 (dcpcncling upon) XXVl.3
iipnuyill (shoułd reach) X.7
arabhyate, ar11bhye111 (begun, initiated)
11.12- B
lłfn'ty11, 1111· (not rcłying) XXJV . IO
afffyeta (should 1cly) XV.10
1cch.ui (inclinc,
cxpcct) Vl.8-9
idhyat'iifl,I (being burnt) X.4
lhate (Is intcndcd) Vill. 1
ucyate (is spolcc of) U.11, 22- 23: Vll.15
111p11dyatt1 (u isc) 1.5; Vłl. 14
111p11riyt1111 VII.17
111p1111ya1e XX:.17-18
111pariyer1111 XXVll.23- 24
111padayate (producc) Vll.6; XVll.17-18
u1padayati Vll.18-19
u1pada:ye1VII.7-8, 18
111padayi111m VII.7
up11g11my11111m (shouJd adm ie) 111.5
upaliisyale (shown) 1.8; XXV.9
upapaliyatt (is appropda1e) Jl.3. 6-7, 9, 16;,
IV.4-6; V.4; VII.21, 23. 27, 29-31; Vllł.6;
I.2; XIV.5: XV.8; XVI.4; XVll.12; XX.19,
22; XXl.9-IO; XXll.), 14; XXlll .10;
XXJV.2, 13, 24, XXVll.3 . 7, 9. 16, 27
upapatJyate U.3,
9, Hi
11papaliye1e
11.23
_ 111m- XXVIJ.1j
11plllabhy11te (is obtaincd) JV.1
upadadyad (should be dependent) XXIJ.5
11p11riasyate (wlll be graspcd) XXlI.6
up11day11 (dependent) XXl1.2, ); XXV.9. 12;
XXVJI.30
1111- (not grasping. indcpendcm)
XXlJ.5-6: XXV.6. 8-9. 12
uhyate (is assumcd) XXV.17- Ja
ltathy111t1 (is callcd, is cxpressed, is said)
XV.3; XXII.li; XXlll.t
karoti (performs, doc:s) Vili .I, 3, 9-11
/lurute VIII,7
ltnyale VIJ.8; XVll.22; X:XIV.33
urifyate XXIV.33
.łuryat XJI.7
ll11rute XXIV. 13
ulpay11 (woułd thiaJc) XXIJ.13
llramate (proc~ds) VJI.l}
g11&&ha1i (gOC$, movcs) 11.8-11. 22-25;
XXVl.1
pra· 11.23
g11&&he1 X:XVll.19
gamyate li.1, 4
grhyalt' (is observcd, is graspcd) XIX.5;
XXJll.15
grh~ati XXlll .15
grhyeta XlX.5; X:X.3: XXVJJ. 7
ce1ayi11111 (vołitio112ł) XVU.2-3
chadayifyali (will conttal) Vll.12
1i1r1ayate' (produccs) Vll.4, 6. 13;
XX. U- 16
ja1111ye1 VII. U ; XX.10-11, 23
janayifyati VIL5; XVU.6; XX.21
ja11yaJe XX.7
j1111iy111 (should be known) Ili.9
jay111e (be, arisc, be boro) IV.8-9:
XVll. 15;
XX.1- 2; XXlll.20; XXVU.I5
j11ye1a Xl.3; XXVl1. IO
jiry11111 (age) XJll.5
1lr111łlrtya (having separated 11.6-7; lll .6
li[{hati (stays, is statiooary) 11.15- 17;
Vll.22, 24; XVll.6, 18
riattva (having passcd on) XXV.5
11· XX.6
drsyate (is sceo) IV,I ; XXI. U
dr1ya1am XJV.2
drff11a, adrstva, XX. I I
riesyate (is taugbt, is prnched) XXJV.10
de1ay11mt1Ja,
Dcdicacory Verses
de111yi111m XXJV.
12
droA,y11ti (sec)
lll.1
dha/qyati (bums)
X .)
nan„yate (is des1roycd) XXVU .26-27
yj. XXVll.26-27
1111m111yami (I bow reverently) XXVll. 30
nllJti (docs not cxis1) 1.2; ll.22, llł . 6 , 8;
403404 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
lV. ~; Vl.4: Vll.9. 32-33; VIII.2: XID.3,
7; XlV.6-7; XVI.2, 7; XVll.29; XIX.6;
XXJ .1, 7. 21; XXIl.2, 4, 6, 8- 9;
XXlll.10-11; XXJV.1, 20, 22:
XXV.1-2, 8, 19: XXVU.8, 19
111111111/i XXIV.3
ninl.tlh,11111 (ccascs} Vff.26, 18: XVll.19;
XVll.>; X:X.)-6; XXJII.23: XXVl.12
nirudhyllllii
XVllJ.4
11iro11µ111
XX.17-18
n1r.:lir11nti
(posit) X .16
11itW1r111111 (produces) 1. 7
nirvll!Jllli (cease) X.5
ni,-,#{y11111i (J will be free) XVI.9
"i!i&yote (is infuscd) XXVl.2
lllhof'!i!Joti (will destroy) vn. 11
pori.łlllp11y11Se
(umcclvc) Vl .8
PlllJl11i
(perccives) 111.2, 4--5 ; V.8; XVIll.3;
XXIV. 16, 40
posyimti XV.6;
XXII. U
. ptt.syomllh
VUI.12
Prdip11J11ti
(illuminaccs) VIl.9
Pńl&M,mllhe
(souc) XXlV:tB
Pfllfa11pyau
(makcs known) IX.3; XIX. 5;
XXll.5. 10
prt1fa11P11Jemahi XXlll.10-ll
pra}noydle (is known) Xl. l
pra1i/J11dh11re (conmdicc) XXJV. 5- 6, 17, 23,
36
Pf1111°tyll (depending, dcpendcm, dcpendcocly)
1.5; UJ.7; Vl. l ; Yll.15- 16; Vlll.12; XII.2;
XIV.5; XVIII. IO; XJX.6; XXll.J;
XXlll.l-2, 6, 10--11: x:xv.9: XXVJ.4;
XXVll,2.3--24
11· XXIV. 19. 21, 31: X:XV.9
prlllliy11te (givcs over co) Xll.5
pr11p11„c11Janti (obscss) XJ.6; XXIl.15
pfllbh11V1111ti (arisc) XI.6
pro11~omi {I will expound) XVU. 13
Pfl1Vllrl41e (proceeds} 1.12; V.J; Vlll.12;
XV!ll.12; XXVI.7-9; .JO..'Vll.22
pr.u11jyo1e (wiJI, follow, fimply) Il.4, 10; IV.2;
Vlll.6, 8; X. 3; XV.1j; XVll.23; XX.9. 18;
XXl.14, 16; XXN.f. 20, 31: XXV.4;
XXVll.11-12 I
ptrJ.J11jye1e ll.61 11, 19; V. I; XX.7
prasojyeran XVII.16
pr.rhif'!Oli (bcstows) XIJ.6
pf'flh11.1y111i ( rdlnąuish) XXJll.24- 2)
prahiyer11n XXllI.24-2S
pradurbho11e1 (would appcar) XX. 7- 8
pmp11yqya1i (will lead to) XX.IV. 25
propf!ule (rcach) Yll. 10
prapf!uy11dX.6-7
Pf"llPJll, O· Vll. IJ
prop!J11le X.5
prety11 (having gooc bcyond, in the nat life)
XVll.1. n
badhniyod(sbould be bound) XVl.7
ŃbÓll/lre (ha.s said) IU.8
blldhyale (is bound) XVI.5-ó
badhyonle XVl,5
bn1v111e (ca.Il, say) V.5
brumah XXJV.7
b/:Jajyerrm (wece to be dcstroyed)
XXVll.23-24
bha11111i (comcsr to be, eKists, i.i) l.10; lll.4ć
Vll. 16; IX.I, 10; X.4; X:Xll.14:
X.XV.1 7- 18; XXVll.3. 9. 15
bh11~11nti XXlll.4
Bho11i!Jati U-7: UJ.8; Vl.2, 4; IX.2. 4;
X.9; XllI.6; XV.2-3. !>: XVl.9;
XVtl.30: XVUI.2: XJX.t, 6; XX,17;
XXI.2-4; XXIl.3; XXlll.9. 12;
XXIV.5. 30, 38; X:XV.7: XXVJl.6
bh11vifyami xxvn.i' J4
óhl1llel l.11 : 11.1!>: VI. I; Vlll.3; JX.8-9;
X .1; Xl . 2~ ; Xll.3; Xlf!.6-7; XIV.6;
XV. I, 8; XVl.3. 7; XVJl.22: XVIII.I ;
xx.~6. B-9: XXI.u. 14, 19;
XX.ll.4-5, 11; XXlll.16; XXJV.37;
XXV.5. 11-14; XXVl.7; XXVU.4, IO,
12. 16, 23- 24
bhave1a1n Vl.3
bh11vy111e XXlV.24
m1111111 (having rcfl~ctcd) XXIV.12
manye (1considcr) X.16
1'11J&ya1e (is releascd) XVI.' , 8
m1"yan111xvr.5
m1Jcye111XXVl. 7
mn'yale (dies) XXl.20
mriy4l11 Xl.5
ytitiJ111e (proper. pcuincnt) J.6-7; ll.18; Ul.4:
Vll.20, 25; IX.8; X.li ; Xl.5; XID.5:XlV.8; XVII.24:
XXlV.14: XXV.10-ll;
xxvn.22. 25-26
y11fj11nte XXXIV.27
:10Jy11te x.vn.13
"1k,11yet (should be indicatcd) XVIJ.19:
XJX.4
11°"'11'li (dcdaic) IX.1
1111ek1 IV.B-9
ł'111'tle (l salutc) Dedicatory Vcrscs
111u/p11ye1 (should think) IV. 5
v1blpy111e 11.14, 20; XVl. lO; XXII!.7
11ikil1'~11Ji (faocy) Vl.8
11ij'1111tl1'li (uodcm.and) XXIV.9
11ijaniy111 VIII. 11
INDEX
11rr1j11nli (function) XIV.1, 3
sakyam (possiblc;, :1blc) XXIV.28
.std1111y11d VII.7
saf!lfi/fhtt (would remain) XXVll.10
Jllf!Jnilli1a1e (cntcrs) XXV1.2
saf!11tilli!!e XXVI.2
santi (arc, ClCist) 1.4; Xl.7
It1f!1PraR11Jt1JaU (illuminatcs) Yll.12
Jt1f1JPN1111rtate (procttds) XXVl.~5
Sllf!1Pr11pf!oli (rcach) X.6
405
saff!bhilllanli (occur) Xll.2; XXIll, 1-2, 17-18
Jll'f?1b"411i!Jllli XXVll.29
s1111UU1hig11nl11f!J (to rcalizc) XXIV.28
J11m11<kti (uiscs) XXVU.6
11itly111t(iscvidcm)l.l, IO; 11.21, 25; V.1, 5:
s11m11tle!Jllle XXlV.22
111m11p111rity11 (bascd upon) XXJV.8
I11f!111irlyate (is cvidcot) 1.14; VIl.17
1ao/-111r111i (t1'11nsmigratc.s) XVI.2
VU.31: Vlll.4-5: IX.6-7, 10-13: Xl.8;
Xll.10; Xlll.4: XlV.~4 . 7-8: XVlll.3;
XIX.3, 5: XX.12- 14; XXl.3-6, 8;
XXUl.11, 13. 15, 21-22; )Q(IV.4, 19, 21,
23- 25, 30, .34-35. 39; xxv.~-8. t G, 20
111rn- V.2
llirlyPntll lX.ll
11itly11nte XXlll.2, 6: XXJV.3
11itlya1 Vlll.13
vinasay1m1i (ruin) )Q{IV,11
11ip11~y11ti (matures) XVU.25
111pr11f!ll!Jl1ti (pcrishes) XVll.21
vióhavayet (should be critically cxamincd)
VJil. 13
11~/PSlltl (rdlcct) XXlU.18
virutihyante (arc c.ontradictcd) XVU.24
11iJ011te (is idcntified) XXVIl.4
vihanyase (arc tormcntcd) XXJV.7
11et1i (comprchend) XX.IV.7
vy11t1' (ccases) XXVll.6
St1f!Ullrt1trli XVI.l
JITf?11t1rify111i XVI.2
saf?Uuroti (forms) XXVl. 10
sitlhy111i (is csrablishcd) Vl.B-9; XV.4-~ ;
XXJll.4; XXV.15
stilhyate X. l 0--11
sitlhy111ah XXIJl.3
1itftihyaum X .lO
Jel!)ati (could be) VII.33
1lh11SJ11le (rcmaias) X.~
sy111 (would be, wece ro be) U.20; JV.3: V.l ;
Vl. 5: VJH.2: lX.9; X.l : XJ.4- 5; Xll.7-9~
XIU.4, 7; XV.8; XVII.16. 23, 26, 30;
XX.20; XXl.19; XXIV.1&: XXVI.7:
XXVU.11, 15 , 19, 21, 25
Jy11111m X.7; XVl.8; XlX.2
sy11r Vll.2; XIl.3; XVJl.12: XX.4406 TuE PHILOSOPHY OF THE
Mroou; wAy
GENERAL INDEX
Abhidharrna, srarus of 3, 6, 174; period of
20; ca.dy Buddhisrn and canonical 22- 26,
29, 3H; theory of conditions 28, 38, 106,
107. U0-114: catcgories of the 37, 132,
147 , 193. 244 , 245 , 275; interprctation of
the 6, 125, 140, 141 , 160, 171-173. 178.
179, 252, 278, 280, 284, 323. 331.
Abhidharma litcrature a.nd ccxts, 6, 20, 25 ,
26. 38, 181. 323.
Abhidharrnika 32, 107.
Absolucc 2), 47. 116 , 272. 389, For adjectival
usc, sec undcr cxisccnce. diffcrcnce,
ldcntity, truth, reality. etc.
absolut.ism 86, 128, 340.
absoludstic (vicws, sy5tems, traditions, etc.)
1, 16. 20. n. 69. 85, 90, 148. 2s5 , 326,
328, 336, 337. 342, 3H . 388.
Acela-lcou11pa-s11111J 45
urion (.łorma. ltn]"ii, etc.) 29, 30, 33, 42-44,
46, 51, 53, 54. 55, 56, 59. 61, 64, ~8. 69,
74. 90. 91. 128, 133. 162, 180-187' 195.
197, 205, 218, 219, 236. 243-2)1 ,
253-258, 260, 261, 263, 266, 261, 2n,
276, 332. 3}9. 3H- 353. 380, 383;
impcrisbability of 30, 55, 251 , 254, 255.
agem (ulf, karaka, etc.) 29, 42-44, 46, 55,
69. 83,.90. 105. 128. 180-187. 195- 197.
205, 214, 221, 259-261. 302, 339, n2,
37), 380. 195.
aggrcgatcs (1.ł11„Jh11) 18, 21, 29, 36-40, 46,
)2, 56. 64, 132, 140, 144. 147, 148,
179-181, 193. 196. 211, 212, 222, 236,
237. 263, 264, 301-307. 315. 374, 379.
381, 387. 388.
altrui.~m (absolutc) 4, 91: altruistic 91.
analysis 21 . 22, 40, 49-50, 61, 125 , l28m
129. 143-147, 1')3- 156. 159. 167, 174,
224-226, 228. 277. 285. 293. 297. 30.8',
322, 349, 368, 386.
anoihilacion (ucr:heda, etc.) 9. 13. 14, 19, 29,
33. 4), 46. 51. 54. 55. 59, 67. 75. 79, 81 .
88, 101 , 21 9, 220, 234. 238. 254, 264,
267. 269. 273, 274, 287, 292. 298-300,
362. 378, 382, 383. 357
aonihilationism (iaclJet/41iiid11, etc.) 16, 92.
131. 184. 212. 218, 232. 236, 246. 259.
267. 292 . 298. 299.
annihil:uionist (uccheri11vitli. etc.) 184. 185.
219. 247, 56.
ar/Mnl 24 , 25, 72.
1triyap11nyuona-111J1a 17 , 240, 336, 240, 332.
Aryadcva 102.
Asoka 2, 2).
asscrtion, Abhidbarrna 193; absolute 365,
Buddha's 159. 379; Nigicjuna's 42, 43, 55 .
56. 92. 114, 122, 123. 136. 142, 205, 210.
2}6. 265. 291. 340, 341, 347; racion:i.list
81 ; Sarvisrivida 109; subscantialist 71, 120,
123. 182, 383; Vicslpurriya 197, 230.
attainment, nou-amunrncnt (pr#pli/
11priipl1) 127 . 241. 242. 251 , 318. 349.
amibutc 17. 43, 47, B. 62, 122. 124, 127-
129. 150, 155, 190, 222, 2H, 239, 258,
371.
bc:coming (bh111111) 10, ll. 15, 26, 32. H,
62-64. 72. 74, 78. 88, 218, 237. 241, 294.
298-301, 337, 361, 362. 370, 373. 374.
H6. 379. 385. 390: sucwn of 62, 218,
241 . 299. 301.
bcginning (absolutc) 44, 61, 79. 2o6. 207.
259. 271, 292, 293. 368.
Berkeley, George 112, 142.
Bhogavadglfii \9, 20, .238.
Bh:lvavivckll 26, 101, 105. ·
borihua111111 24, 25, 53. 91. 348.
bondage (b1mdhana. etc.) 9, n, 18, 20.
2.9-H. 40, 51-53. 56, 57 , 72, 76, 77, 80.
85, 88, 92. 133. 235. 238-243, 304-307,
3412, 356. 359. 368-370, 374.
Brahmajii/11-111/trmf.t li , 79. 80. 188. 385.
Candrakrrci 17, 26, 28. 29. 40, 86. 96. 101.
102, 105-107, 112, 114. 134, 138, 153.
154. 189. 199. 201, 203, 207, 234. 350,
251, 255. 381.
causallty 31 . 34-36, 68. 73. 77, 94, 95, 97.
137. 143. 169. 174, 182 , 191 , 244, 347.
356; mctaphysical thco.cies 36. 77.
causation 22, 34, )0, 61, 78, 94, 97, 108,
114. 116, 134. 143. 144. 162, 163, 165,
166. 170, 171, 2ll. 215. 216, 273, 276,
282, 283, 286. 327, 369; ~ternal causation
14, 27. 28. 32. 46, 1o6. 107, 115. 174.
176. 204. 259. 260. 298; sclf-causatlon 14,
27. 28, 32', 39. 46, 106. 107. 115, 168,
169. 174, 176, 204. 212. 214, 258-260.
280, 281 , 298.INDEX 407
cercaincy (absolute, etc.) n. 79, 84, 188,
256.
change 8, 27, 28; 31, 34-36, 41, 32, 54,
102, 125 , 131, 134, 159, 160, 163-165,
173-175, 178, 179. 182, 192. 204, 220-
222, 23()-233. 263, 273. 274, 286, 295,
346', 369.
clairaudience 8}.
dalrvoyance 83.
cogito, sec under Dcsca([Cs.
co-existeli.ce 155-H8.
commitmeot (pralijn'ii) 92, 93.
conccptuafuatoo 49, 56, 57, 66, 129, 143,
209, 249, 263.
conditionalicy 18, 30, 271, 388.
Confucianisrn 8.
confusion (tnrfii, 11UJha, etc.) 46-48, 59, 66,
67, 72. 82, 90, 217, 219. 297, 312. 313,
323, 332; big bloomiog buzzfog 92, 159;
cognitive 316, 318.
consciousness (11ijffiin11, viftifii1!11) 10, 11, 18,
38, 49. 72, 81, 84, 111, 1H. 136-138,
140, 147, !)I, 225, 261 , 264, 280, 386,
371-373, 381; self· 379; self·pt"tcc:iving 37;
tiansmigr.uing 235, 236, 252, 380.
contiogcnce (apek.fii) 198-204, 276,
convcntion (satr111rtil sammuti1 ryavahiiral
11oh'iiN, prajiiapti/paflfłatti, nif'gtti, etc.)
14, 55, 69, 241, 256; absolute reality 17;
dependent 86; idea! 330-~32, 334. 340;
linguistic 18, 19, 35; morał 88, 89; woildly
68, 330-332, 334. 340, 352. 355. 366.
dcath(matll'fll) 9-ll, 16. 45. 47, 51,
57-59. 63, 64, 66, 73, 76, 78, 159, 173.
174, 178, 197. 207-209. 218, 219. 238,
253, 254, 270, 292-295, 301, 303, 309,
358, 365, 366, 368, 374, 374.
dcfilcmem (Ń./efa) 55, 56, 112, 224, 225, 256,
258, 259. 262, 266. 278. 313-315, 324,
325, 335, 353. 356.
depeodence. principle of 12, 13. 15, 22, :B.
37, 38, 43, 45, 46, 51, 33, 61, 64, 65, 68,
69. 77. 82, 88, 93. 108, 109, 124, 126,
137, 145. 146, 154, 158, 162, 163: 165,
168, 190, 191. 200, 212, 213, 227, 231.
236. 252, 254, 273. 279. 306. 316, 342,
361, 380. 388.
dependent uising (pr(l/fty11111mNJpiJfŃI,
pa(iccasarnuppida) 1, 2, 15, 16, 21, 22,
27, 31, 32. 34. 42 , 49-51, 66, 68-70, 72,
78, 80, 82, 85- 87, 93, 101-103, 114, 131 ,
139, 142. 146. 155, 167-169, 187' 188,
216, 221, 226, 228-231, 255. 267, 269,
272-274, 290. 295. 320, 331-333. 336,
339-341. 343, 352-354, 362, 384, 357.
dependendy arisen (prali1ya1amu1panna,
p11ficc4s11mupp11nnd) 15, 21, 34, 42, 48-SO,
55, 59, 69, 70, 82, 84, 85, 93. 114, 212,
220, 235, 236, 267. 273, 274. 313, 331,
332. 340, 341, 343. 368, 377, 380, 390.
Ocscancs, Renc (Cartesian) 37. 43. 119;
cogito ergo sum or Ćogiio 37, 43, 81-84,
92, ll:l. l33, 134, )37, 164, 188, 189,
191. 264, 266, 379.
dcterminism 16, 30; detcuninistic 235, 347,
}48,
Dhammac11kkappa11alta1111-1111111 l-2.
Dham11iap4d.rJ 20, 54, 91.
dharma (dham._1714), Abh[dhanna concepcioo
of. 20-21, dharnt4.(ihatu 8; docuioe,
discourse 25, 329. 331. 392; foUI different
uscs 15-16; ethical 43 , 68, 88, U3, 1°83,
243. 257. 330, 335, 336, 340, 349, 366;
metaphysical 18, 19, 22-24, 32, 39. 77.
84. 141. 172, 176. 177, 369; life
( ~janman) 2)3, 275 ; nacurc ( = dh11rrnali)
55, 58, 268, 269; ontological 4', 8, 12, 19.
21, 22, 24, ~4. '!>7. 40, 51. 55, 56, 67, 70,
71, 83-85, 90·~ llO, 11, 132, 140-142. Ul,
153. 181, 217-220, 224, 234, 235. 273,
286, 288, .Hl, 336, 354, 390, (See also
unde( demcnrs.)
diffcrence (absolute, real, etc.) 12, 16, 23,
33, 40, 50, H. 29, 64, 76, 81, 92, 101 ,
106, 108, 111 , 116, 128, 129. 136. 137.
149. 160, 168, 182, 191, 192, 197. 199.
202, 211, 221. 225-228, 230, 231, 23~ ,
244. 2ts . _259. 262, 261, 273. 274, 276,
281, 284. 288, 289, 296, 304, 306-308,
310, 312, 360, 362. 365, 366, 381-385 ,
387.
disdples (Śrii11aka, ecc.) 2-4, 17, 19, n , 26,
31, 32. 79, 80, 90, 133. 23~. 236, 240,
243. 249. 250, 274, 292, 380, 387.
discrimination H, 56, 59, 88, 92, 126, U9,
143. 193. 266.
dispositions (sarrz.skiira, sllńkhar11) io-12, 14,
18, 40, 46, 49. 65. 66, 72, 73, 82, 84, 1·38 ,408 THE
PHILOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE WAY
144, 159, 181, 217-220, 224, 225, 324,
352, 353, ~70, 371, 374-376, 378, 381 ;
appeasement of (-fllffUlth(J, ·t1Pfli11ma) 4,
47, 48, 92, 152, 335-238, .264, 308, 320,
336, ;15, 376; ccssation or waning of
(-k,rdyd) 218, 219, 238, 375; lump of
(-p11 łlj4) 180; uansmigrątc 52, 235, 236;
unconditioncd by 6,, 73.
discinccion (11i1e!llf!ll, etc.) 7~76, 114, 121,
127, 129, 130, 14(), 141, 149, 151, 158,
172, 173, 199. 233, 239.. 258, 280, 281,
283, 285 , 349, 359, 366, 367, 369;
Humcan cxplllnacion 72.
Dogcn 257.
dogmatism 18, 80, 86, 92, 219, 223.
dream (svapna) 179. 182, 316.
clcmcots, adveoticious 241; discrctc 22, 381;
of Cllpcdcncc 15, 21, 29, 37:-40, 52, 83,
132, 140, 142, 147-l H, 153, 154, 235-
237, 261; non-subscanciality of(-nt1iriitmy11)
24, 29, 37. 40, 5l. 84, 181, 235, 235;
subjcctivc 313; subsrantiałist thcory of 4,
7, 24, 84, 140-142, 147-151. 192, 193.
197, 198, 216, 332. (See ~lso dharma.)
cmpiricist 8, 33, 39. 81, 83-85, 113, 115,
ll9, 132, 188. 258. 271, 278, 282, 285,
286, 293. 341, 342, 357, 368.
cmptiness (h1.0yat1.) 5, 6, 29, ,48, 49, 53. 55,
56, 67-7 1, 77, 80, 82, 85, 86, 89, 90, 93.
144- 132, 182, 22(}-223, 231•. 254, 266,
268, 288, 319. 320, 326-328, 330, 331,
335. 337-341, 343, 347, 350, 352, 355,
368, 390.
empty (sun~) 14, 49, 64, 67, 70, 71, 85, 86,
89, 93. 103, 145 , 220, 222, 223. 258, 259.
261, 262, 267, 287, 288, 296, 307-309.
318, 319. 326-328, 330, 331, H5.
337-342, 350, 3H, 3B, 355, 356, 368,
375.
cnłightened one 12, 47 , 58, 63, 65, n. 87,
30.2, 321, 330, 347' 348, 356. 249. 274,
313.
cnłightnmcnt 1, 9, Il, 14, 17, 18, 63, 92,
138, 240, 327, 335, 336, 323, 375, 376.
cternal, life 63, 74; sdf 12, 20, 30, 37. 43,
H, 56, 57, 64, 67, 78, 79, 106, 191, 219,
222, 236, 238, 262, 263, 269, 298. 379.
383.
ctc:rnalism 16, 92. 109, 131. 184, 212, 218,
228, 234. 236, 246, 259, 267, 292, 298,
299. 353. 377.
cternalist 247, 79.
exiSrencc (absolutc, etc. bh'ii11111 11JfŹti111, etc.)
1, 3, 7-11, 13. 14, 17 , 21, 24, 27, 29, 30.
'2- 34, 36, 39, 40, 42-46, 50, 51, 54, 56,
57' 61-65, 67-69. 71-76. 78. 79. 82, 85 ,
88, 103, 108, 113-115, 125, 131, 132,
1)(}-152. l.5~158 , 163, 164, 176, 177,
181, 184, 185, 188, 193, 194, 201, 202,
205. 220. 221 . 228, 231-234, 235, 236,
241. 246, 261, 264, 269, 272. 272. 276,
239.. 294, 296, 298, 299, 301, 303, 309,
310, 314, 322-324, 326, 329, 330, 332,
339. 342, 344, 347, 350. 356-365, 369,
377, .378, 382, 383, 390~ non-existcnce
(artrl, 11bha1111, etc,) l, 7, 9- 11, 14', 29, 32,
39. 40, 42, 44, 50, 62, 67- 69, 73, 74, 78,
82, 88, 103, 108, 131, 15(}-152 , 154, 163,
177, 181, 184, 185, l93, 194. 220, 221,
228, 231-234. 269. 272, 298, 299, 303,
309, 314, 324, 326, 329, 342, 347, 357,
358, 360-365, 355.
cxpericocc: l, 12-15, 19, 21, 37, 47~9. 51,
56. 60, 69, 78, 82- 85, 89. 92, 93, 108,
ll l. 130, 139, 145-147. 153, 156, 159.
189. 192-194. 216, 219, 220, 234, 261 ,
262, 264, 271. 278, 282, 308, 313, 316,
319, 320, 323, 331, 335. 337, 34'<>-342,
350, 384, suc:un of 192, 349.
finite (11n111) 292, 368, 378, 387-390.
fue (11gnt) 39, 140, 151, and fueld (i11dh11t111)
44, 134, 135 , 29$-205, 222, 227, 230.
freedom (11irvii~11, nibb'iin11) l, 4, 15. 16, 18,
21, 29-31, 40, 41, 43, 47, 49. 52, 53, 56.
n. 59. 63. 6~77. 80; 85 . 88, 89. 90, 92,
97. 102, 103, 138, 153, 160, 169. 184,
187, 218, 23S, 238, 24<>-243, 251, 266,
268, 269, 299. 300; 307, 321, 328, 329.
332-336, 346-349. 353, 354, 355-370,
373. 374. 376, 379, 385, 387, 390, 391.
Fruit (cffc"Ct, consequence, etc. 11r1h11/ 11tth11„
pńa/11, vipak11) 14, 15, 16, 19. 29, 33. 43 ,
5:3. 55 , 61. 68. 69. 73. 77. 80, 85 , 88,
89, 108-110, 183, ł84, 187, 189. 243, 288,
290, 291, 35<>-335. 339, 347, 348, 3H,
352, 356, 357, 366, 383: ultimatc orINDEX 409
highcst (p11rrzmiirtha, p11rrzm1111ha) 16, 19.
68, 69, 73, 77, 80, 88, 89, 184, 187, 331-
33), 352, 356, 3.57. 366.
grasping (upiidii1111) 10-13, 38, 40, 42. 48,
56, 63, 79. 80, 92, 102, 138. 187 ' 204.
205, 218. 219, 234, 236. 237, 239, 240.
263. 266, 304-309, HB-321, 329. 363.
373, 374, 376, 379-381, 389. 390,
Gudmunsen, Chris 98.
harmony (silmll~n. _ctc.) 30. 59. 61 , 226, no.
280-283 . 286, 290, 29 1.
human personaliry 68, 70.ja2. 85. 369;
Abhldharnu analysis 21 , 181; analyscd into
aggrcpccs 38. 39, 263, 264: annihilatlon of
9; bondagc and &ccdom 29. 30, H-59.
dispositions and 47; mctaphysiw view 19;
non-subscanóaliry 51, 52, 61, 62, 67 .
292; Sarvistivada and Sauuincika vicws 25,
84; sclf-consciousocss and 1.H; six clcmcms
147; survival of 62, 77. 78. 90, 92, 236,
in, 369, 3n, 378. 383; cwclvc faccors 1.
7, IO, 11 . 13. Z5, 77;
Hume, David 81, lH. 156, 224 , 338.
ideał 3. 4. 15, 24, 25 , 63, 88, 89, 91, 332,
334, 335. 341 , 353, 355, 36~
idcncity 16, 22, 33, 34. 36. 50, 51 , 56. 59.
64, 75-77, 81 , 101, 105. LOB, 111. 116.
128. 129, 136, 143. 144. 149, 1S5, 156,
))8, 166, 169. 171 . 177. 178, 191. 192,
195-197. 202, 204, 213, 221 , 226-228,
230, 23'1, 239. 245 . 254. 259, 262, 273,
274, 276, 277, 281. 284, 288-290, 296.
298, 306, 307, 310, 312, 3)1, 360, 365-
367, 378--382, 348, 384. 387.
igno~ncc (a11iriya) 10, 11 . 14, 82, 163, 259 .
324, 370, 371, Jn. 376.
illwion (nriyii) 179, 182, 316, H 7.
illusory 42, 179.
immortality (amr14) 45, 63. 208. 218, 382.
!nada 3. 20, 38, 53, 55, 64, 70, 94~97 . 120,
144, 160, 216, 217' 230. 232, 191 , 237'
243, 248. 250. 268, 270, 271, 294, 296.
310, 323, 327. 329. 330. 337, 340, 344.
345. no. 358, 367, 369. 370, 374.
infinitc 161, 162, 170, 308, 368, 378, 387-
390; rcgrcss 161 , 162. 170.
inhcrcnce 33, 109, 276.
lti11utlllkll 313.
Jaina 14, 244.
Jaini, P. S. 350.
James, William 35, 47, 60, 88, 97. 192. 219,
308. 334, 337' 381.
jayawidacma, N. A. 94. 95.
Kaa:iyana (Kiryayana) 7. 8, 10, li, 50, 78,
82, 103, 108, 184, 212, 220, 221, 228,
232. 271, 272, 294, 314, 320, 342, 356,
569. 370.
K4cliiya11agollil-1uffa (.Kiityiyanivavida) 1, 5,
1. 1~14 , 25 , 26, 29, :n. 63. 1s. 79, 81.
232.
Kant, Immanuel 33, 322.
karma (sec undcr action).
Karmmiridhiprwral!a 29, 55, 250.
Kii1yap11-p11n1'11rta 4, 6, 7, 24, 25.
K11(h11 Up1111i{llri 189.
K111h'iJ111111h11 2, 21. 23, 24.
Kityiyan (sec undcc Kaccayana),
Kil'jiiy11nii111111iria (sec undcr Kacc#y1111agotlll·
SU/Ili).
lmowlcdgc, of the beginning 61; of
dependent arisiog 21, H 11 339; iodc·
pendent or nor ocher depcndcoc (11p11r11-
pra1yay11) 10-11 , 59, 271, 272; empicical
knowlcdgc 381 ; going beyond expcricncc
320; foundation of 82, 264. 372: Jcading to
frccdom 92; of the future 159; of the past
206; hlghcr (abhińflii) 261 , 262; Jamcsean.
cxplanacioo 47; limications of 377; mctaphysical 285, 332;
of objcct, etc. 133. 148;
not omniscicncc 159. 358: pragmatic
dcfinition 219: as prajflil or y11thiibhu111°
jflina 2, 11 , 12, 67, 80, 274. 285, 294,
331. 342; sourcc of84; transccnding che
&cnscs 269; of ulcimatc fruit 335:
Upani.~11dic view 63; ViiuTpuuiya dcfini.t.ioo
196.
KumirajTva 3, 8, 39. 50, 120. 18)„243, 322,
371. 38 l , 382,
1."11i11111ir1111r1 366.
lifc-proccss (1111JJiira) 44, 45, 52, B , 55, 61,
74-76, 9 1. 206-208, 210, 211, 241 , 243.
246, 252, 254, 256, 263. 292. 293. 366,410 THE PHlLOSOPHY OF
THE MIDDLE V/!AV
367 . 37). 376, 386.
M.1ulh11pi'! r!'4-f11/t11 3 7 3.
Mah'i111tJSt11 24.
Mahiylina 1-8, 20, 24. 25. 59, 69- 71. 75,
77. 82 , 90, 9l, 94. 174, 257. 329. 348,
350. 366, 370; Mahaylinist 7. 53.
Matc:riaJisu l, 9. l4, 19, 39. 40.
maucr, Abhid\larma concepcion 193; early
Buddhist view 39, 40, 14()-145; meta·
pbysical view 9, t9, 39. 40; primordial 44;
Sarvlistiviid:l view 49, 111- 1}2, 140-145.
meraphysician(s), Buddhist 5. l5, 28, 41,
43- 46, 49. 51, H. 55. 60-62, 68, 74. 76, 88,
114. 127. 128, 133, 137. 146. 147. 149,
151 , 159. 160, 174, 175. 178. 189. 193.
194, 202, 207, 208, 213, 224-227 , 231 .
232, 236, 241, 260, 265. 267. 269, 273,
216. 218, 292, 313, 321, 328, 330, :n2,
H5, 337-339. 341, 343. 345, .349, 355,
357-359. 361-363, 366; r.caditional Ind.iw
62, 68, 189, 22~227 .
middle pach l , 2, 4, 7, 16. 18, 25 , 69, 78,
86, 9()-92, 183. 267 , 320, 339·323.
Mitchell, Dorutld 97.
Mogga!Tpurca-tissa 2, 5.
momc:nrs (theory of) 22, 23, 28, 35. 49, 54.
6()-62, 82, 112. 113. 125, 127 , 128, 131 ,
134, n6. 161-164, i66, t6s, 110. 112-
116. 191 , 192, 206, 213 , 222 . 236, 246,
2)2, 253. 278, 279. 282, 284. 288, 298.
300, 301, 319. 349.
monl, pc:rfcction U , 59, 90, 366; puri~ry 256,
257: rcsponsibility 9. 14, 27, 30. 46, 62,
64, 70, 85, 90. 180, 181. 184, 187, 235,
243, 352, 369, 383; truth 13, 59. 334.
motion 36, 38, 68, 82, 119, 121, 126-Bl,
167, 203, 204; movcmc:ot 3. 19, 24,
34-36. 118-131
multiplicicy 181, 182. 364.
Mu„tjlu UpflJ'lf!ad 189.
Muni, T. R. V. 4, 7, 28, 33, 86. 94. 183.
Nabmura, Hajime 95, 340.
ncgatioo 45, 102, 143, 169. l!H. 197, 252,
269, 295. 345. 365, 379; fourfold 58, 270.
OOO·COOtCptuaJ 32, 66, 87, 88, 203, 268,
269.
objcct (cin!(1111y11, 11Ź!f1J4. c:tc.) 50, 59, 76. 84,
88, 112, 131, 133. 136-138. 140, 148. 154,
192. 224. 266, 271, 320, ;B2, 372;
appeasement of 40, 87, 264, 308.
obscssioo (prt1jJ11iica). 18, 48, 56, .59, 86. 153.
266, 267, 270, 272, 308, .BG. 337:
appeasement of 40. 84, 101- 103. 152, 264,
369; illoof from 310; c:Jimination of 18,
freedom from 31: root of 43.
omnisciencc: 47, 63. 92, 1.59. 219, 227, 358.
ontology 81 , 83. 323.
ot.hc:c-narure (p:ln-bhiva) 23, 28, 33, 37, .50,
H , .57, 64, 67, 74. 76, 77, 81, 83, 88, 107.
114, 212, 21.5, 229-232, 272, 302-304,
3o6. 307. 382.
Pirileyyau·n#lll 377.
pc:rtn:lOCOCe 19, 29, 45, 51, }4, 5), 59, 81,
88, 101. 160, 236, 237, 24), 253, 256,
267 . 272- 274, 287, 292. 294. 295. 319,
320. 387. 388.
pecson (pudgala) 23. 24, 26, 29, 36, 44 , 4.5,
51 , 52„ 62, 83-85, 105, 126, 130, 180,
181, 189. 195-197. 200, 202, 21}-215.
221, 222 , 235-239. 299. 311. 312, c~cc
also under humllfl personalicy).
personilliru 23, 36. 37.
pc:rvcrsion (11ip11ry'ii.J11) 312- 31.5, 318-32 1,
322, 543, 312, 313. 3 15, 316, 319,
321, 322- 324, 326, 327.
po1eotialj1y 108, 161, 170, 246, 349.
Powsin, L de: la Vałlc:e 97, 101, 127, 213,
377. 356.
power (ś11h1) 81. 108, 133. 261 , 262.
pngmatic conccption, of conditions (pratya)'11)
109, 110; of emptincss 330; of language
308; of moraliry 89. 2n, 334. 366; of
philosopby 8; of truth 16. 19, 67, 80,
85, 159. 219. 224, 225. 227„. 229. 272,
332.
Pmj11'i1pirami'J7i-1iilr11J 3. 7. 367.
prii1angika 26. 101, 102.
Rath1111inlla-1111111 240.
reality 9. U. 27, 44 , 49. 57- 59, 76. 82, 84,
85. 144, 152. 156. 163. 180, 181, 196.
213. 218, 220, 23()-232. 249, 2.59, 271,
n9. 310, 319, 330-334, 340, 352,
355. 37.5, 389; ultimatc: or absolutc
rcaJicy (p11TrJmii.r1ha) 16, 17. 19, 20, 66.
87. 189. 203, 268, 331. 3.H . 356. 361 ,
364. 366.realization 59, 63. 267, 286. 328, 346.
rebirth 56, 206, 235. 237, 252, 255, ;266,
284, 294, 299, 375. :n8, cigl'n view 10-12,
31, 78, 80, 87. 103. 249. 271 , 272.
Robinson, Richard 8.
RusseU, Bertrand 225.
S11hb4-Iflll4 189, 231' 270, 358.
Sarlrlht1rmt1fł1'f!tjliilla·sufrtl 3, 4, 6, 24 , 25 ,
174, 366.
Sarvasrivada i . 6, :H-25, 32, 36, 39, 41. 50.
52, 58, 62, 64. 67, 76, 77, 84, 85,
107. 109. 119, 127, 135. 141, 143. 156.
159-162, 169, 170, 173, 182, 189. 196.
206, 225. 236, 256. 280, 288, 290, 296,
299. H 3, 349, 359. 367; Sarvinivadins
22, 25-28, 32, 34, 35, 38-40,
44, 50, H, 60, 62, 69, 77, 81, 84, 105,
106, n;, 119, 125, 120, 129. 134. 137.
U6, 160, 1n-116. 181, 196, 201. 213,
270, 276, 288, 298. 327, 338, 349. 366.
Sauuaocika 6, 22-28, 34-36, 41 , 44, 52, 54,
57. ·Go, 62, 67, 16, n. 81. 84, 05 , 106,
IB, 119, 125, 128, 129, 134, 141, 143.
U6, 159. 161, 163-166, 168-170. 172-
176, 189, 194-196, 206, 207, 213, 236,
246-248 , 255, 256. 286, 286, 288, 290,
293 , 296. 299. 300. 301 , 332, 333. 338.
349, 355, 367, 383.
'self (almafł) 9. 14, 19. 20, 27, JO, 32, 39.
40. 44. 48, 51, 55, 56, 63-65. 67, 68, 74.
78, 105, 180, 181, 191, 218, 262-264,
269, 303. 318, 380, 383 .
sclf-indulgencc l, 4, 90, 184.
sclf-mortification i, 18, 90. 91.
self-l)atOIC (J1JiJbliiifJa) 1, n ,23, 28, 32- 36,
38-40, 48-52, 55-57, 64, 67, 69. 71, 74,
76.• 77, 80, 81-83, 88, 102, 107-110,
113, 114, 140,, 141 , 154, 160, 169. 212,
215, 220, 221, 225, 228-282. 191, 240,
255 . i57. 258, 272. 280, 288, 298. 299.
302~304, 306-311, 313, Jl), 322, 324.
325, 339, 343- 351, 355. 357. 382.
sclf-tcsuainc 53, 90, 91 , 243.
sense expcricncc 12. 82, 83. 159, 219, 264,
316, (sec also undcr expcricnce)
space (ii.łiiia) 36, 39. 68, 89, 131, 147-149,
Ul, 161.
Spnmg, Maivin 96, 154.
Stchcrcabsky, T.l. 23. 70,' ?5, 154. 183. 19~.
INDEX. 411
Strawson, P. F. 98, 131.
substancc (s11abha1111, etc.) l, 7, 12, 13, 15;
21. 28, 29, 32 , 35, 40, 41, 50, 54. 55, 58.
64., 65 , 67. 68, 76. 77, 81, 82 . 84, 85, 88,
93. 103, 105- 108, 111, 112, 122, 127-102,
133. 137, 141, 142, 145, 146, 148, 1.50.
155: Vi6. 161. 164, 169. 171, 172, 175,
181. 1S2, 189-191, 193. 195. 196, 206,
212. 213, 219-222, 225, 226, 228, 229,
233. 235, 236. 239. 241, 255. 262, 267,
269, 270, 288, 298, 308, 318, 320, 327 ,
332. 338, 339. 341-34„, 345, 346, 351,
3.53. 355-347, 375; non-subscantial 49, 65,
84, 85, 103. 131 , 181 , 218, 220, 255. 258,
312, 314. 317, 325, 341 , 390; AOO·
subsuwtialiry 25. 35, 43, 49. 65, 67, 80, ·
178, 217. 220-223. 231, 320. 350, 390; of
agent/action 184; of rhc :&ggrcg:ucs 179;
human petsonality (purlga/a- „11ir'ii1my11) 24,
26, 29, 51, 62, 63, 84-87. 181, 292, 3ll;
of phcnomcna (rlharma·nairiitmya) 24, 26.
29, 40, H, 84-87, 181, 234, 264, .311; of
vicws 103.
sµffcring (rl11~.łh11) 10-12, 14, 30, 31, 40,
42, 43, 45. 46, 48, 51, 63, 65, 70, 74, 78,
80. 91, 184, 211-218, 237. 241, 259. 304,
319, 323, 32~328 , 343- 346, 3B, 354,
355 . 356, 362, 363, 374, 376.
S111ta-11tpila 17, 43, 331.
tabula r11111149, 153, 154.
T11.thigiita 10, 13, 16, 30, 47, 58, 65-65, 72,
197. 218, 238. 269. 270. 302-312, 319,
324-326, 355, 365. 366.
Thef'llgithi 2.
Thcravada l-3, 5, 6, 20, 21, 25, 62, 69. 70,
91. 141, 333, 366.
Theifgat/111 2, 335.
time (ka/a)·30, 35. 36, 59-61, 68, 82, 125,
161, 172. 197. 275-279, 286, 301.
transcendence 24, 25 , 90, 102, 149, 332, 334;
transcc:odeot 16, 24, 25, 152, 249. 303,
365; transcendeoral 363.
ttansmigntionists 23, 35 .
truih(s), absolute or ulcimate 47, 49, 82, 86,
103, 159. 218, 219, 270, 271, 272, 288,
342 , 364; a priori 12; and cóofus1on 46;
Buddha's conccption of l7, 231. 232;
cha.tactecistks of 271; 2 dependent :uising
230, 273; dispositions and 218; cmpirical412 THE PHILOSOPHY
OF TiiE MrDOLE WAY
375; four noble 67, 326, 352; linguistically
transcendent i49; meaningful language 19;
metaphysic:al 88, motał 334; percepcion of
92; Platonie n9; pragmatic: dcfinicion 16,
85, 219, 225, 229, 272, 308. 334;
provisional 220; self-conuadictory 272:
statemcnt 3l9; two 68, 69, 330, 331, 333:
unspcalcable :HO; Upan~.rdic 11ohow1 J3.
Ueda, Y 230.
ullimtlte retJllty (see umler re4'/1y).
undet/11reti questtons (1111yiilr1a-1111Jlu) 31.
2.51, 309, 368.
uniformiry U, 1)9.
unity 2ÓO, 230.
univcrse 13. 16, 65, 80, 89, 125, 166, 188,
310, 311, 353.
Up1mi.f11dr l , 37. 43, 63, 105. 18l , 237 . 199.
200.
Valbh~1:ł111JJ ,
Vajr111;chetJi,ł;i.pr11jfliipir11milii 24, 240.
VitsTpuuiya 197, 195-197, 200, 202, 222,
230. 299.
Vigr11/J111ifiiw1r111irl 92.
Vinaya-pi/f1Ńll 4. .
volition 53. 244, 245, 248: volitional 53, 244,
·252.
Warder, A. K. 7, 95.
Wittgenstein, Lud'l(ig 93, 217.
wrong view 12, 13, 78.
Yogacira 7, 9, 37.Exr.erptsfrom reviews:
"The book represents a bold, new and independent
approach to the problem of Nagarjuna's philosophical
stance and provides a readable and stimulating addition
to the already existent literature on the subject.
The index to the Karika and the generał index
appended to the work increase its research value for the
serious investigators and students ofBuddhist thought."
Journal ofthe Oriental Institute, Vadodara,
"In this book, which is a new translation ofNagarjuna's
work Mulamadhyamakakarika. Prof. Kalupahana has
given a new interpretation of Sunyavada of Nagarjuna
who is the reputed scholar of Buddhism... Sanskrit text
and its translation have precision in presenting the exact
nature of Nagarjuna as a truest interpreter of Buddha's
teachings. The author begins with a brilliant exposition
of middle path Madhyama Marga, for about hundred
pages, and then presents the Sanskrit text of
Madhyamakakarika, translating all the 448 verses of the
text, covering 200 pages; and the last 20 pages are devoted
to index. The introduction is a discussion of all
metaphysical problems raised in 27 chapters ofthe
text."
Pathway to God, Vol. xxvi, No. 4, 1992
"łOTILAL BANARSIDASS
PUBLISHERS PVT. LTD.
---Dellu
(INDIA)---
E-mail:
mlbdCvml.com
Wcbsite:
www.mlbd.com
Rs.425 Code:0774x
I SBN 81 -20 1 -07 74 -X
Comments
Post a Comment
7000