Trung Luan(3)
dhariyamiina.sabhav'ii ańfio dham1no n'iima atthi, DhsTp.21;
see aJso my aniele, "Schools of Buddhism in Eatly Ceyłon," in The
Ceylon journ11/ of the142 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
Humanities, Peradeniya 1 (i970):78], a view that resembles
the one presented
by George Berkeley during modern times.
Nagarjuna seems to be unwilling to accept such a solution.
Considering the
philosophical issues a phiłosopher like Berkeley had to
face, one can understand Nagarjuna's unwillingoess to subscribe to such a view.
Without ałłowing
the experienced elements (dharma) to hang loose, Nagarjuna
was interested in
providing a causa! exp łanation. Therefore, following the
Buddha's explanation
of "dependent arising", Niigarjuna boldly asserts:
"Nowhere is.there any effect
without a cause," (see also XXIV.19,
aprafityasamutpanno dhaN!Ull/ kaŚcin na
vid!Jate).
3. RuPe11a tu
vininnuktaf(l yadi sjiid rupa-kiirat/a?(i,
akiiryaka'l(i
k'iiraf!41(l sy4t nasti ak-Pryaf(l ca kara11a'f!1.
H there were to be a cause of materiał form distinct from
materiał form,
there would then bC a cause without an effect. There
certainly is no ineffect-ive cause.
MKV(P) p. 124; MKV(V) p.48.
The staternent in the previous verse: "Nowhere is thete
an effect without a
cause," (na c'iisti arthaf? kaicidahetukal/ kvacil)
could lead ro the belief in an
invisible ultimate cause (like ~ubstance , or even God) that
is ecernal. White th~
characteristics, perceived quałities , etc. could be looked
upon as the experienced, yet variabłc, effects, their ultimate grouod would be
the substance, eternalły existing even when it is not producing the effects.
Rcałizing that such a
view could emerge frorn his previous assertion. Niigarjuna
immediately pto·
ceeds to nip·it in the bud when he insists: "There is
no in-effect-ive cause."
Thus, IV.2 and 3, in combinacion should provide the
interpreters of Nagarjuna wich the cłearest evidence that he was upholding the
theory of"dependent
atising" (prafityasamutpada) in the form in whjch it
was fotmulated by the
Buddha in the early discourses.
4. Rupe Jaty eva iiipasya kiiraf!af(l nopapadyate,
riipe 'saty eva ropasya kiirat}at?Z nopapadyate.EXAMINATJON
Of ACGREGATES
When a materiał form exists, a cause of rnaterial form is
not appropriare.
When a materiał form docs not exist, a cause of materia!
form is also not
appropnate.
MKV(P) p. 124; M.KV(V) p.AS
143
Herc Nigirjuna is reverting back to che criticisms he made
of the Sarvastivada
and Sautrantika views in Chapter I. The first is the
ideotity theory ofcausation
and the second, che non-ideocity theory, and these
criricisms are here appłied
to the causality of materiał form (ropa).
5. Nifkaraf!af?J- puna rupa1p. naiva naivopapadyale,
lasmiit ropa-gatan klhrilcin na vikalpan vikalpayet.
Furthermore, a materia ł form without a cause is absolutely
inappropriate.
Therefore, one should n_ot cliscriminarively think
ofanything confined to
materia! form.
MKV(P) p. 125: JlfKV(V) p.29.
A theory of an uncaused event, as reiterated, was cleady
unacceptable co
Nagarjuna. Indeed, it is emphasized by the repctition of the
oegarion, naiva.
Not accepcing the epistemology chat is gencrally and
indiscriminarely at·
tributed to Nagarjuna, we have avoided transła ting the term
vika/pa either as
"conceptualization" or "conceptual
construction" or ·even "discriminacion," (see
Introduction). The importance of the term rupagafiin cannot
ge overemphasizcd. The comments on the previous verses show to what extent
speculacion "confined" suictly to marerial form
(ropa) led to all lcinds of weird
philosophical theories. The analysis of materiał form should
be undercaken in
relacion to various other issues, especially language and
epistemology. [n the
lasc few verses, Nagarjuna was engaged precisely in such an
enterprise. Hcnce
his advice in the present verse. The suffix -gala is better
understood in the
meaning in which ie occurs in phrases like kaya-gata
("confined to the body''),
ha11a-gata ("confined to che hand"), etc.144 Trm
PHILOSOPHY OFTHE MIODU! \V/AY
6. Na k1iraf!•uya sad(ia??J karyanJ ity upapadyate,
na kara„asyasadrśam kiityam ity upapadyate.
The view that the effect is identical with the -cause is not
appropriate. The
view that the effect is not identical with the cause is aJso
not appropriate.
MKV(P) p. 125; MKV(V) p.49.
Unlike I\T.4 wruch sc.ates the lnappropriateness of identity
and non-jdendty
theories of causation applicd specific;aUy co the subjecc
matter under discussion,
narody, materiał form (ropa), the present verse emphasizes t
he inappropriatencss of identity and noo-idencity theories in generaJ.
7. Vedan'?i-ciJta-Ja??J;mhiiim.- sarrutiiirar/ii'!t ca
sarvaśaf?,
sarvefiim evtT bhtivtinlif?J riipef!at'va s11maf? kramaf;:
The method of creatrnent of all existents such as feeling,
thought, perception and dispositioru is in every way similar to that of materiał
form.
MKV(P) p . 126; MKV(V) p.49.
The previous comments on the contents of this chapcer would
indicace that
Nagarjuna dld not dcny the reality ofroaterią.l form but
only the method ofe:xplaining it. A similar treatment is requested of the othcr
a~gregates tao, Note
the·use of the term bhava in the present context, which
prompts lnada to
fender it a5 "existential actiOflSH (compared wirh its
usage at 1.3 wruch !nada
translared as "entities").
8. Vigrahe ya4 pan'harartt krte Junyataya vadet,
sa1'1!1J.f?J ltnjtipanlJrta?p. samaf!1 sadhyana /iiyate.
When an analysis is made in terms ofempti.ness, whosoever
wece co ad-EX.AMINATlON OF AGGREGATES
dress a refutation, all that is left unrefuted by him will
beequal to what is
yet to be proved.
9. Vjiikhy'iine ya up'iilambhatp krte śunyatafii vadet,
sarvarri tasyan1tpalabdha1?1 sama11J stidhyena jliyate.
When an explanacion in terms of emptiness is given,
whosoever were to
address a censure, all chat is left uncensured by him will
be equal to what
is yet to be proved.
MKV(P) p.127; ti!KV(V) pp.49-50.
14 ~
These two rubtle and crypcic verses tan best be understood
in the context jo
which chey appear. They are placed at the end of an extremdy
important
anałysis of die metaphysics relacing co materiał form
(ropa). As.such they
should be consjdered the conclusion of that analysis.
The basie theme of the chapter has becn the rejection of any
metaphysical
substance (svabhava) as the cause of materia! fo®
(rtipa-k'1ira,,.a). lndeed, there
was no rejection of the cause of materiał form, only the
criticism of the view
that this cause is an invisible permanent enticy distinct
from the perceived
materia! form. This criticism if referred to ac IV.8 as
"an ana.lysis in te~ms' of
empciness" (Siinyataya vigrahe krte). lnteresti.ogly,
the term "empti1:_1ess"
(funyata) never occurred in char ana.lysis. The ana.lysis
was made on the basis of
mutual "dependeiice" of lnaterial form (rupa) and
the cause of material form
(rupa-karaf!a). Thus, materia! form and the cause are empty
of substance
because they arc mutually dependent. At this scage,
ifsomeone wece to present
a refutation of Nigarjuna's view, chat refutatioo wou1d be.
iotended as a
refucation of the "mutual depeodence" of the
materia! form and its cause.
However, such a refurarion ·does not aucomatically p.rove
the valiclity of the
metaphysical idea, namely, svabhava chat is being rejecced
by Nagarjuna on
che basis of"dependence." The argume~t in favor of
dependeoce is experlence,
Hence, che person presenting .a refucation of this idea
should be in a position
not only to negace "mutual dcpendence" bur also
provide evidence for the
establishment of a metaphysical substance (svabhava). This
has oot yet been
achieved: Thus, according to Nigarjuna, what stili remains
ro be proved
(iiidhya) is the chesis regarding "substance"
rather than "mutual dependence."146 THE PHll.OSOPHY OFTHE MI ODU! WAY
These two verses are very significant in that they seem to
admit that the
Madhyamikas have a positive thesis, namely, "dependent
arising" which is accepced on the basis of cxperience. The
"emptiness" (fiinyalii) they advocate is
simply a challenge for the mctaphysician ro prove his own
mctaphysics.
The tWo verses are idenricaJ except for the use of the rwo
pairs of terms,
vigraha andpan"haru in the former, and vyakhyana and
upala1nbha in the latter. As is welł known, Nagarjuna is also the author of a
creatise called Vigrahavyavartańi. The term 11igraha means
"analysis." On the basis of this work,
modern interpreters of Nagarjuna have assumed that he was
merely an
an:ilytical philosopher whose enterprise was confined solely
to "analysis"
(vigraha) of opposing views utiłiziog the conception of
"emptiness" (f'iinyata).
However, IV.9, cast in the same mould as IV.8, raises doubts
about the validity
of sucb an interpretation of rhe cbaracter of Nagarjuna's
philosophical method.
The use of the term vyakhyana meaning
"explanatioo" seems to indicate that,
in addition co "analysis io terms of emptiness,"
Nagarjuna was aJso providing
an "expłanatioo ." That expłanacion is once again
said to be based upon emptincss (funyatay'ii vyiikhy'ii?Je krte). But as
mentioned above, the term "emptiness" did not occur at all in the
chapter. lnstead the explanation was provided
on the basis of "dependent arising" (pralityasamutpada).
"Emptiness" being
che counterpart of "dependent arising,"
"explanation in terms of dependent
arising'' would, therefote, be the same as "explanation
in terms of emptiness."
Thus, Nagarjuna, even when presenting his posirive theory of
"dependent
arising," need not worry about someone censuring bim,
for the theoi:y of
"dependence", likc "emptiness," was
intended to reject the mecaphysicr of
subsrance, and the responsibilicy once again falls on his
opponcnt co prove his
own substance-mecaphysics.CHAPTER
FIVE
The Examination of Elements
(Dhatu-parz ksd)
l . Niikafar?Z vidyate ki'f!Zcit purvam 'iikaśa-
lak!a'f!'iil,
alak!a'f!a'f!J prasajyeta syat purva?!l yadi lak1a11at.
No space is evident prior to the spaml cbatacteristics. lf
it eicists prior to the
cbaracteristics, then it would follow that it is without
characterisrics.
MKV(P) p. 129; MKV(V) p.~l.
As pointed out earlier, the caregories of aggregates,
spheres, and elements constituted an important pace of the Buddha's ceachings
as well as of the
Abhidharma analysis (UL l ). This early classification was
incended to accounc
for che human personality (skandha), its experience (12
ayatanas = 6 indn'yas
and 6 111/ayas.) and finally the dements to which this whole
experience can be
analysed (18 elemcnts = 6 ayatanas, 6 v1jayas and 6 forms of
consciousness).
Howevcr, Nagarjuna does nor cake them in that particular
order. This is
because of the problems creaced by the ioterprcters of the
Abhidharma. They
were more concerned with defining each one of che elements
in eacb of the
catcgories without considcring them in the light of other
elements within the
category to which ie belongs or in terms of ocher cacegories
oucside of
themselves. This led to a wide range of mctaphysical
speculations. For example,
one of the elemeots (dh'iit11) chat caused much
misunderscanding and led to
many metaphysicaJ ideas is the conception of
"space" (iik'iifa). Although
"space" is not an item included among either che
aggregatcs, spheres or
elements (in rhe earlier classificacion), ii indeed was pan
of an analysis of che
human personality comparable co the analysis into five
aggregates (skandha).
The counrerpart of the skandha-classificarion is the
explanation of the human
personality io terms of six elcments (cha-dhatu or !afidhii,tu),
one of which was
"space" (akafa) (M 3. 239). At S 2.150, the Buddha
specifically recognized che
inrerdependence of material form and "the sphere of
space"
(Yaya'f!Z .. . akaJaiJcayatanadhatu ayar!l dhatu
rupa"!J pa{icca pailwyat1).
However, the Buddhist metaphysicians, creating cach one of
the carcgońes and
147148 lHE PHLLOSOl'HY Ol! THE MLODLE WAY
items independendy. assumed that "space" is
"uncond.icioned" (asa1pskrta1?J,
Akb p.3). the Jactet being unde1stood as
"independence" (see Sakv p.174;
DhsA p .193). Thus, space came to possess the unique narute
of "nonobstruction,,- (aniivarana-svabhavam akiiśa'f!J) where mate~ial
form finds its
locale (yatra
ropasya gati/?, Akb p. 3).
This, indeed, was a very absolucistic conception of space ,
a conception chat
muddled up the entire Buddhisc epistemology. Ie posed the
most significant
challenge for Nagarjuna. In order to eliminate such
metaphysics, Nagarjuna
adopted the ingenious mechod of analysing the source of
knowledge (i,e., seeing, darśana, Chapter lll), t he object of knowledge (i.e„
materia) form, rupa,
Chaprer IV) and its locale (i.e, space, ?ikafa, Chapter V)
aod this he did on the
pretext of examining the Buddha's own categories of
aggregaces, spheres and
elements (skandha-ayatana-dhatu). Thus, the presenr chapter
on the examina·
tion of ele·ments comes to be devoted not to the traditional
category of
elements, but rather to the conceprion of space,
higbJ~ghting its relativity,
especially co material form, discussed in the previous chap
rer. With these three
chapters. Nagarjuna was thus able to give a rather com
prehensive account of
the problem of knowledge.
Here there is no denial of space, but only the rejection ofa
particular way of
u nders tan~iing or conceiving it. If space were tó be
undersrood as the ult.imately
real pure enrity, a substance to which various
characteristlcs ate attributed, in
wbich case space precedes tbe c:haracceristics, then
Nagarjuna finds no
epistemologicaJ justificatioh for it. This is a c:riticism
of the first aspect of the
metap hysical explanation of sp ace referred to above,
namely, thac space has the
cbaracter of non-obstructon (anavaraf!a-svabhiiva) . The
obsrruccion, in this
case, tefers to mare.rial form (i.e., pratigha).
2. A/akf<1f!O na ka:icic ca bhavalJ Ja1rividyate kvacit,
asaty alak.rflf!e bha11e kramafiif!I kuha lak.raf!a'/'!J.
An existent tbat is without cbaracteristics is nowhere
evident. When an
existent without characteristics does not exist, where can
cbaracteristic:s
appear?
MKV(P) pp.129-130; MKV(V) p.51.
The denial of pure "space" at V. I is here
extended to all ttlemeots or entities
(bh'iiva). The question chat follows next is: lf there wece
to be no pure entity orTHE EXAMINATION OF El.EMl!NTS 149
a tabula rasa, then one also cannot account for adventitious
elemeots through
which something comes to be koown. ihis tćpresents the
second aspect of the
metaphysical definition mentioned earlier-, namely, the
"unobstructed space"
serving as the locale for the appearance of materiaJ form
(yq.tm iiiptJJya gatif? =
iiipasya kramata7(J).
3. Niifak!af!e fak!af!tJJYa pravrtttr ha Jalak.faT!e,
sa/aktaniilak.fanabhyif!l niipy anyatr(I pnwartate.
The occurrence of a chacacteristic does not take place
either in something
without chacactedstic or in something with charactecistic.
Nor does itproceed from something other than those1 with or without
characteristic.
trlKV(P) p.130; MKV(V) p .5 L
Here again, it seems inappropriate ro assume thac Nagarjuna
was denying
either space or materiał form, but only the mannet in which
they were explained by the metaphysicians. It is the sharp dichotomy berween a
thing and its
properties chat cannot account for either of them. The
subscantiaJist mode of
speakir.g about entities (bhava) leads tó two extremist
views. oameły , identity
or difference. The second scatemeot rejects the view that
the ptobłem ofidentity and di.ffereoce can be solved by transcending both. The
reasoning seems to
be that, rather than attempting co salve the problem of
identity and dilfereoce
by follow-iag the method of traosceodence, it is mare
appropriatge not to create
such a sharp distinction in the first place.
4. lak}"a1'faJa?!Jpravrttau ca na lakfyam upapadyate,
la~ya.syanupapattau ca lak!af!asyapy asa?!Jbhavai{,
When the characreristic does not occur, the characterized is
not appropciate. In the absence of the characcerized, there is. no occurrence
of
the characteristic.
1\ifKV(P) p.U I : MKV(V) p.52.L50 TuE PHILOSOPHY OFTllE
MIDDLE WAY
The relativiry of concepts, or more spedfically the contextual
meaning of concepts, is herc underscored. Definitions may be useful in
clarifying the meaning
of terms. Yet these meani ngs are not derived independencly;
they occur in conrexts and, as such, any reference to subsrance and attribute
shouJd not be taken
co imply distinct or pure referents. What are denied here
are not the concepts
of the characterized or of the characteristics, but merely
their independent ex-
1stence.
5. Tasman na 11idyate lak.fyaf!l lak1at/af!l nai11a
11idyate,
lak,ya-la/qana-nim1ukto 11aiva bhavo'pi 11idyate.
Therefore, the characterized is not evidenct. Neither is the
characteriscic
evident. Distinct from the characterized and the
characteristic, an existent is certainly not evident.
A!KV(P) pp.131-132; MKV(V) p ..52
This is not a blanket denial of the cha.racterized and the
characteristic. Rather it
is a denial of these two clements as expłajned at V.4,
namely, as substance and
attribure conscirucing independent entitics. Therefore, one
cannot find any
event, any encity, any existence tbac is separated from the
characterized and the
characteristic. An existent separated from the characterized
as wełl as the
charactcristic could turo out to be a "pure
entity," an idea clearly unacceptable
to Nigarjuna.
6. A11tdya1niine bhave ca ka.syabhavo bhavqya11:
bhihiiibliiiva-vidharmii ca bhiivabh"iivam avaiti kaf?.
When an existent is not evident, whose non-existence can
thcre be? Who
could comprehend the cli~tincr things: ex.istent and
non-ex:iste.11t as well as
existence and non-existence?
MKV(P) p.132; MKV(V) pp.52- 53.TH!! EXAM1NATION OF ELBMENTS
15 1
Herc again, ifwe arc to understand "cxistent"
(bh7i11fl) wichout takjng inco consideracion the son of "existent"
referred to at V. 5, we would be left wich a
universal statement regarcling all "existeots"
(bh7i11a). Yet, it is not meant to
be taken that way. The "existent'' referced to herc is
alreadydefined at V.5. It is
an "existent" chat is separated from either the
characterised or the characteristic
or both. lt is a "pure existent." Such a pure
existent could then be contrasted
with a pure non-existent, and i~ is this sharp distinction
or dichotomy chat is
being questioned by Nagarjuna. Indeed, it is significant to
note the use of the
term 11i-dharma (whose occurrence in any other text is not
knowa to the present
author) in the sense of ''distinct things."
7. Tasmiin na bh7ivo nabh7i110 na lak,ya?'!J -niipi
lakfa!Ja'f?Z,
aliiiśaf!t ak.aśa-samli dhatavalf pańca ye pare.
Therefore; there is neither an existent nor a non-existent,
neither the
characterized nor the characteristic, neither space nor the
other five
elements similar to space.
MKV(P) p.1 34; MKV(V) p.53.
Thus, neither eXJStence nor non-existence, the characcerized
nor the
characcerjstic as envisaged by the metaphysicians exisc. The
five
elernents= earth, water, fire, air and consciousness, which
together with space
constitute .the personality (cha-dhaturoya?'!J punso)-do not
exist if these
elements are conceived ofin the same way as space. This does
oot mean that the
way in which the metaphysicians conceive of the six elements
is the only way in
wbich tbey can be understood and explained.
8. Astiva'fP ye
tu ptlŚyanti nastif1Jt1f!J calpabuddhayal;,
bh7ivanii?'!J te
na pa.fyanti drfJ/{avyopa.fama?'!J fiva?'!J.
lhose who arc of little intelligence, who percdve the
existence as weU as152 THE PHilOSOPHY Of THE MIODLE W AY
che non-existence of existents, do not perceivc the
appeasement of the
object, the auspicious.
MKV(P) p. 135; MKV(V) p. 54.
The "appeasement of the object"
(dra1fa11yopaśa1na) is, no doubt, a synonym
for the ''appeasement of dispositions"
(1a1!JSkaropaJama) or the "appeasement
of obsessions" (prapancopaśama) . lt is indeed not the
elimination of the object
(drfl!{avya-k1aya), implying the abandoning of both subject
and objecc. lt is
mcrcly che appeasement of the object. What is implied by the
appeasement of
the object is its non-reification. The concepdon of the
non-existence of the object will emecge only if its existencc is understood in
a substantial way. Existcncc (a1titva) and non-existence (ni1Jitva) arc
correlaóve. Asscrtion or denial
of one involves the assercion or clenia! of the ocher
respectivcly. Asseróng cxistcnce in a mctaphysical way one is !cd to the denial
of existencc. Denying cxistence in the same wa.y one is led to the assertion of
non-existence. Instead of
eliminating both existence and non-existcncc and looking for
a transcendent
reality, a reality that is beyond both exiscence and
non-existence, it is possible
co appease. calm, or pacify one's cłispositions
(1af!1.Jkara) or obsessions
(prapaflca). Dispositions or obsessions, when foilowed to
their positive extreme, lead to che belief in a permaneot exiscence (aititva);
when completel)'
negated they rontribute toward the belief in non-existencc
(na1tit11a). Hence
the emphasis on rhcir appeasement rather chan cheir
promotion ot elimioation.CHAPTER
SIX
The Examination of Lust and the Lustful
(Raga-rakta-pari
k.ra)
1. Ragadyadi bhavet purva?(l rakto raga-tira1krtaf?,
fa?IJ pratiya bhaved rago rakte riige rago bhavet sati.
lf a lustful one, separated ftom lust, were to exist prior
to Just, then
depending upon bim there will be Just. Lust exists when
thete is a Justful
one.
MKV(P) p.138; MKV(V) p.55.
. .
So far Nagarjuna was considecing the basie elemencs (dharma)
lnvolved in an
explanation of the problem of perception, nąmely . the
"faculties" (indriya),
rhe ''aggregates" (sk1t11dha), and "elemeots"
(dhatu). However, the analysis of
perceptuał experience, and rherefore of the elements
(dharma) invołved in such
experience, is not confined to these. ln the Buddhist view,
lusc (raga) is an im.
pottant constituent of perception, primarily because in
Buddhism the analysis
of perception was not undertaken for its own sake, but for
the sake of discovering the cause of bondage and freedom.
We have already referred to the confusioos created by
Candraklrti, especially
in i:egard to the interptetation of the most crucial Chaptec
I where he fails to
recognłze the significaoce even of the ordec in-which
Nagarjuna takes up the
variety of ideas for examinacioo, let alone the ideas
themselves.
Another unfQrtunate misinterpretacioo emerges when
Candrakrrti' assumes
that every ioicial verse in every chapter represc.nts a
sratement of the opponcnt's
view which is to be repudiated. While this may be true in
some chapters, thete
is no necd to universalize it. There is oo reason why
Nagarjuna could not cake
up his or the Buddha's views first and then go on to
repudiate what are considered co be inappropriate ideas.
In the Buddha's owo analysis of perception, opsessions
(prapańca) appears in
a personality th~c isalready smeared with !ust. The Buddha
consistendy avoided any speculatioo tegarding absołute origins. As such, he was
not willing to
assurne either a pure personality, a tabula rasa which comes
to be defiled by
1531~4 TuE PHILOSOPHY OF THE M IODLE WAY
adventitious elemenrs (see A 1.254) or the existence of an
element całłed Just
(raga) in the external world independent of a conscious
person who generates
lust on the basis of external objects (see S 1.22). For him.
objects can be
classified as pleasurabJe (śubha) , loathsomc (aJubha). or
neuuał only in rełation to a perceiving iodividual who isprone to make such
distinctions. A person
who is prone to make such distinctions is one who is either
dominated by Just
(raga) or aversion (dósa) or indifference.
Thus, Nagarjuna is able to assert tbat if any object were to
cause any lusc
(raga). chen there must be a lustful one (rakla), noc simp
ly a "pure person" who
is uotained by lust. For him, tbere is no difficulty in
speaking of !ust, so long as
that lust is not distioguished as an entity which is then
supposcd co infect a person who is pure and undefiled by !ust. lt is the same
sort of relation that is exeropłified by a compassionate one (maitra) and the
recipient of comp assion
(upagr'iihaka), a very apt example given by Candrakfrci ro
illusuace the conception of "otheroess' • (parat11a). but whicb has been
misunderstood by many a
translator [MKV(P)p.78; Sprung , Lucid &position, p.66,
who was probably
following Stcherbacsky's earlier translation]. There is oo
sense in speaking of a
compassionate one or even compassion in a vacuum. A
compassiooate one or
compassion bccomes meaningfuł only in the concext of people
who are recipiencs of such compassion. The same sort of celarionship exists
among the
łustful (rakta), !ust (raga). and the objeccs chat generate
!ust in the individuals.
The present verse, cherefore, is a elear scacement of
Nagarjuna's own position, noc the statemeot of an opponent that is to be
rejected.
2. Rakte 'sati puna r'iigaf? kuta eva bhavifyati,
sati vasati v'ii
r'iige rakte 'py e!a sama/; kramal/.
When a lustful one does not cxist, whence can tbere be lust?
Wbether
lust exists or not, the method (of analysis) even of the
lustful one would
be comparable.
MKV(P) pp.138-1:39; MKV(V} p. 5~
Thus. Nagarjuna raises the question as to how there could be
!ust in che
absence of a luscful one . This avoids the theoty of a
tabula rasa and the adventitious impressions. Lec alooe the exisrence or the
non-exiscence of lusc. even
the lustfuJ one has to be analysed in terms of dcpendeoce ,
not in terms of pure
entities having tbeir own sdf-narure (svabha11a) .THE
BxAMINATION OF LUST AND THE LUST~Ut
3. Sahawa puna udbhutir na yuklii r'iiga-raktayo/?,
bhavet'iir(l iiiga-raktau hi .nirapc/qau parmpara?('.
Again, the simultaneous occurrences of lust and the lustful
one is not
proper. Lust and the lustful one would thcn bemutually
non-contingent.
MKV(P) p.139; MKV(V} p.56.
155
To conceive of lust ot the lustful one in vacuity and then
proceeding to explain
their simultaoeous arising (sahaiva udbhUtir) is not the
purpose of "dependent
arising." In such a case, what is found is independent
existence of lusc as well as
the lustful one, each having itS own nature. This, once
agaio , represents Nagarjuna's rejeccion of the substance/attribute
relationship. "Cow-ness" implies the
fact of having "four legs;'' the latter is not an
independent attribute of the
former. The dangers inherent in catrying out the analytical
process initiared by
the Buddha to its extre.me iś here indicated . Analysis is
usefuJ in eliminating
metaphysiES, but useless when its leads to further
metaphysics.
4. Naikatve sahabhavo 'sti na lenaiva hi lat saha,
Prthaktve sahabhavo 'tha kuta cva bhavifyati.
In identity, tbere is no co-existence. That which is
associated does not
arise together. In discreteness, ·how can ther:e be
co-existence?
MKV(PJ pp.139-140: MKV(V) p.56.
The philosophicalprobleros created by an over-extended
analycicaJ process cannot be resolved by either a cooception of ideotity or of
discreteness, The rela-
• I
tionship of co-existeoce (1ahabha11a) cannot be established
·once the analysis
leads to a sharp <;łichotomy becwee~ substance and arujbute.
5. Ekatve sahabhii11a1 cet sy'iil sahayatr1 11inapi sah.,
Prthaktvc sahabhavaJ cet syat .rahayar?f. viniipi salt.156
THE PH!LOSOPHY 01' 'THE MIDDLE WA Y.
lf, in identity, there were to be co-existence, it coułd
oc.cur even without
association. If, in discreteness, there were to be
co-existence, it could occur even without association.
MKV(P) p.140; MJ(V(V) p.55
The Sarvastivada conception of identity in terms of
substantial existence
(s11abha11a), each substance being a part of a larger and
mote pervading
substance (like Plato's "forms") did not need a
concepcion of association. Coexistence comes to be overshadowed by idencity
(just as much as the threc
Platonie forms ~ truth, beauty, and goodness-eould be found
in amore eomprehensive form, i.e„ Good). The Sautrandka anaJysis of reality
into diserete
momentary entiries (compaiable to the Humean impressions)
led to an explanation of co-existence in terms of "associaiton." Io
faet, such c;o-existence
cl.id not need any "association." Things could co-exist
even wichouc association.
Thus, association i.s not a via.ble solution to problems
either of ideotity or of
discrereness.
6. Prthaktve sahabhavaf ca yadi ki'f{Z f1iga-raktąyoł/,
st'ddhaf? Prthak-prth<Jg-bhaval/ sahabhavo yatas tayo/J.
If there were to be co-existence indiscreteness, is it the
case that lust and
the lustful one arc completely separaced, as a result of
which their coex:istence is also established.
M.KV(P) p.140; MKV(V) p.56.
The problem of"associacion" arises more with the
eoneeption of"discreteness,"
than with the nocion of identity. "Association"
was not much of a concern for
the Sarvastivadins. However, it was indeed a r:najo.r
problem fot the
Sautraoti.kas. Hence their emphasis on the coneeption
of"immediate contiguity" (1amananlara). Por Hume, with a similar
atomie analysis of experience,
"association" was the- glue that bound togethet
the discrete impressions. The
present question of Nagarjuna was a challenge co that
Sautrantika (/Humean)
cheory of the ''ideas of association. ''THE EXAMINATION OF
LUST ANO THE LUSTFUL
7. Siddhaf? Prthak-prthag-bhavo yadi va raga-raktayof?,
sahabhavaf?Z kirn
arthaf!J tu pari/uz/payase tayof?.
Ifcomplete separation between łust and the lustful one is
escablishcd, for
what pucpose do you conceive of their co-cxistence?
MKV(P) p.141 ; MKV(V) p.56.
157
The uscfulness of appeałing to co-existence after analysing
evenrs inco discrete
entitics is here questioned. Nagarjuna's approach here is to
resołve the very
idea that gave rise to the problem racher chan solving ir,
namely, co avoid
creating sharp distinctions instead of trying to find
solutions to problems
generatcd by such distinctions.
8. Pr1hag na siddhyaffty eva'f!l sahabhatlat!J vikank,asi,
sahabhava--prasiddhy artha??i Prthaktva'f!J bhuya icchasi.
You fancy co-existence assuming that the cliscrete is not
establishcd. You ,
again, look for cliscreteness for the purpose of
establishing co-existence.
MKV(P) p. 141; MKV(V) p.57.
No better explanation of the dilemma of an analytical
philosopher who
recognizes discreteness can be found than in the present
scaceroent of Nagarjuna. The vicious ciecie in which one gees invołved when,
after anałysing things
into discrete entiries, one tries to put things together is
dearly explained here.
9. Prthag-bhiivaprasiddhef ca sahabhavo na siddhyali,
katarnas1nin Prthag·bh'iive sahabhava'?"J salicchasi.
When discreteness is not cstablishcd, co-existence is not
establishcd. In158 T HE PHlLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
the presence of what kind of discteteness would you expect
co-existeilce.
MKV(P}l p .142 Mk'V(VJ p.57.
Nagarjuna's question herc is specifically oo the nature of
discreteness. If
discreteness is absolucc, then association of co-existent
entities is not acceptable. If there is no such discreceuess, then there is oo
need for co-existence, for
the lack of complete discreteness implies
"dependence" (prafityasa111utpada).
Hence, the quescion pertains tq the kina of discreteness
envisaged.
10. Evaf!Z raktena raga.rya siddhtr na saha niisaha,
1liga11at saf'tlatlhamUif'!af!Z siddhir na saha nasaba.
Thus, with or without the; lustful one, there is no
establishment of !ust.
Lilce lust, there is no establishment of anything with or
without [accompaniments].
MKV{P) p. 142; MKV(V) p .57.
On the basis of the kind of discreteness referred to above,
one caonot explain
either the association or the non-association of lust and
che lustful one. Avoid
the sha.cp distinccioo, the problems are not there to solve.
The same can be said
in regard to all phenomena (d}Jarma). Fot this teason,
neither absolute identity
nor absolute di.screceness can establish the nature of
phenomena.CHAPTER
SEVEN
The Examination of the Conditioned
(Sa'f!lskrta-parz kfa)
I . Ylll"ii JtZf!Zskrta utpidas tatra yukta
tri-lakfaf!t,
ath1is1Z1?1.skr:ta utpada~ katharp.
sarp..slą·ta-lalt;a11arp..
lfarising is co.oditioned, therein three chatacteristicsare
proper. lfarising
is unconditioned, how can there be charactcristics of the
conditioned?
MKV(P) pp.145-146; MKV(V) p.59
The examinaiton of·the "conditioned" (1arp..skrta)
coming immediateły after
the analysis oflust (raga) and the luStful one (rmeta}
brings out another important aspect of the B~ddha's conception of the pragmatic
meaning of truth, a
conception that Nagarjuoa seems to be de:u:ly aware of.
Lust, as pointed out earlier, is one of the most important
ełements in the
Buddha's analysis of experience. Lust is operative in the
perceprual process
espedalły in the formation of idcas derived from experience.
Having rejected
"omniscience" (sarvajnat11a) as a source of.
knowledge, the Buddha depcndcd
primarily on sense expcrience. However, fot him, sense
experience was a "big,
bloomiog. buzzing confusion." One way ofdealing with
this confusing mass of
sense data is by concenuating upon nems that arc of interest
to the indiv.idual
and then forming ideas. Such ·sełection is generally based
upon one's interest.
This is the signific.ance of"dispositions"
(I(Z'tJSkira "'° compounding of ideas).
For the Buddha, one's conception of truth is
invariably·bound up with such
dispositions: Therefore, all ideas are "dispositionally
condicioned" (1af!Zskrl4).
The Buddha's finał statemcnt:before his death:
"Dispośitions are subjcct to
change" (11ayadhamma sańkhara, D 2.156), thetcfore, is
an assection that,
since ideas are impermanent, there can be no absolutc truth.
However, the above conccption of the "dispositiooally
cond.icioocd''
(Jaf?Ukrta) was to undergo a cadical change at the hands of
the Buddhist
metaphysicians: Na°garjuna's examination of saf!JSkrta
becomes meanirigful onJy in the background of chat change ofperspeccive. His
was. indeed, an auempt
to reject the Sarvastivada and Sautrantika intcrpretations
ofsarp..skria (and this160 THE PH!LOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
would apply ro the ideas that carne co be acceprcd by che later
Theravadins)
and to reven back to the original teachings of the Buddha.
Once again, the Sarvastivada school was responsiblc for
initiating this change
of perspeccive. In the eady discourses, the term Ja'T!Jskrta
is used along with the
term pralilyasamutpanna, bur oot as synonyros (S 3.96, 103).
While the
former implied "the disposicionally conditioned,"
the latter was used in the
moce comprehensive meaning of "the dependent."
Thus, all dispositionalły
conditioned pheoomena are dependent, but not all dependent
phenomena are
dispositionally conditioned. The equatioo ofsa'f'(Mkrta and
pralitya1am111panna
occurs for the first time in the interpretation of the
Abhidharma. 1t was this latter traditioo that Vasubandhu was recording when he
said: "Those chat arc made
by the conditions having come cogethcr arc caJled the
samsk[tas" (sametya sambhuya pratyayail? krtii iti sa11J1krliill, Akb p.4;
see also AA 2.252, paccayehi
samiigantva kataua). The Sarvastivadins secm to have
understood the concept
of sa'T!1Skr1a as a mere refutation of the bdief in the
production ofan event by a
single cause (eka-pratyaya-janilaf!#, ibid.). Yaśomitra,
commenting upon this
statement, goes on to say that Ja'f'(Mk('ta and
pralityasamutpanna are, therefore,
synonyms (Sakv pp.171-172), thereby Óbliterating the
semantie difference between "made" (krta) and "arisen"
(utpanna).
This erroncous simplc equation was to lead to further
complicatioos,
espccially in uoderstandiog the Buddha's characterizatioo of
niniiit!a as
tl1t1"!1Jkrta. Eveo though the early discourscs
prcsenred ni1'71af!a as an aJaT!JSkrta,
ir was nevcr coosidercd to be an apralityasamutpanna
("independent"). For
early Buddhism. borh sa'T!IJkrta and asaf!'skrta are
pralityaJamutpanna.
· However. the Sarvastivada equatioo led to the equation of
their oegations as
wełl . Asa'T!IJkrta secms ro have becn understood i.n the
sense of t1prafitya1amutpt1nna, To what extent their perspcctive was dominated
by an adherence to the
notion of self-nature (wabha11a), for which they gave no
causal explanation at
all ocher thao merely maintaining chat it is permaneot,
remains a surmise,
Ie is this Sarvastivada conception of sa'T!1Jkr1t1 as beiog
identical wich
pralityaJamutpanna thac is beiog criticized at Vll.1.
Nagarjuoa, as indicated in
the first line of this verse, had oo difficułty in assunilog
that che Jflf!'Jkrta is
cbaracterized by arising, change, and cwing. This iodeed was
a statemeot atttibuted to the Buddha in the early discowses, where it is said:
"Monks, there
are these three characteristics of the disposiciooally
conditioned. The arising of
that which is dispositionaJly conditioned is evident. l ts
cessation is also evideoc.
Change of what has come to eodure is also evident," (A
1.152). Yct if, as explaioed by the Sarvastivadins. sarpskrta is ideotical with
pralityaJamutpanna
(the latter also accouoting for arisiog, change and
ceasing), then one cannot
Śpeak of thcse tłltee characteristics in the contcxt of the
asa'T!IJkrta.
It may be of interest co noce that it is not only nirv'ii'!a
that came to be included in the cacegony of asa11J1krta by these
mecaphysiciaos. Thcy also admit-THE EXAMINATION OF THE CONDITIONED 161
red "space" (akaśa) as an asaf!Jskrta. The
implications of that view was examined by Nagarj1,1oa in Chapte( V.
2 . Utpadiidyas trayo vyasfa nala1!1 lak1a?Ja-kamzaf!i,
saf!lJkrtasya samastaf? syur 'ekatra ka1ham ekadii.
When the triad consisting of arising, etc. are.discrete,
they are not adequate to function as chara~ecistics of the conditioned. lf they
were to be
combined, how can they be in the"same place at the same
time?
MKV(P) p.146; MKV(V) p.59.
Further objections co the Saivastivada and Saurra ntika
rheories relaring to the
characteriscics ofthe conditioned are raised here. The
d(screteness of the thtee
characteristics, as envisaged by these two schools, would
not allow them to
function as che characteristics of the conditioned. The
Sarvastivida theory ofan
unqedying substance, which comes to be superficially
characterized by rhe
three (or four) moments, as well as the Sautrantika theory
that each moment is
inherent in the previous one in the form of pocentiality or
seed (śakti, bija),
were the direct rcsults of such a pcrspectivc. Furthermore,
if rhcse
characcerisrics were disrinct in ćelation ro both time and
space, thcy could not
occur in any one saf!Jskrta at che same time.
3. Utpada-sthtti-bhańganam anya1 saf!Jskrta-lakfarJfl'f!J,
asti ced
(lnavasthaivaf!J nasti cet te na Ja'l'(lskrtalr
If there wece to.be a characteristic of the conditioned other
than arising,
duration., and destruction 1 tbere would be infinite
regress. lf there were
to be no such [charact~ristics], t~ese would not be
conditioned.
MKV(P) p. t47;
MKV(V) p .60.
lf arising, stasis, and ceasing are three distinc;t evcnts,
chen each one of thcse
wiU require further characterisrics of arjsing, stasis, and
ceasing to a.ccou~t for162 THE PHllOSOPHY OF THE MIODLE WAY
themselves. Thus, the moment of arising will need three
f\uther characteristics
of arising, stasis, and ceasing bcfore it could give rise to
the next moment,
narncly, stasis. The same applics to stasis and ceasing.
This wiJI lead to infinite
regress (ana11asJhi). On the contrary, if cach of these
moments do not possess
further characteristics, then they cannot be defined as the
conditioned.
4. Utpadotpada utpado mulotpadasya ke11ala'f(J,
utpadotpadam utpado maula janayate panaf?.
The ańsing of arising is exdusively the arising of pńmary
ańsing. Again,
the primary arising produccs the arising of arising.
MKV(P) p.149; MKV(V) p.60.
In order to avoid infinite regress, one may assume that the
arising of arising is
che primary arisiog (mula-utpada) , and that this latter
again causcs the arisiog
ofarising. Such mutuaJ action on the part ofprimary atising
and arising of arisiog coul~ climinate infinite regress.
5. Utpadotp'iida utpado mulotpad~ya te yad1;
maulenajanit~ la'f!l te sa katha'f!l janayifyati.
lf ańsing of arising is the prim2ry arising, not being
produced by the
pei.mary, how can it [the.former) produce that [the laner)?
MKV(P) p. l)O; MKV(V) p.61.
The questioo raised herc by Nigarjuna pena.ins to active
causation . The
substantialist (Sarvastivada) view of causacion, which
assumes the essence of
the effect to be already lateot in the cause,.does not
permit mutual dependence
ofcause and effect. In sucha case, the cause-effect
relatiooship would be a oneway relatiooship. Nigarjuna perceives that the
ioterdependence utilized in
VU.4 in order to avoid infinite regress would not be
appropriate in the context
of a substantiaJist theory of causation. ·THE EXAWNATION OF
THl! CONDl'IJO~ED
6. Sa te maulena
janito 1111JUla'f!J janayate yadi,
·maulr!I? sa tenajanitas lam utjiiidtJyate katha'f!J.
lf, produced by the primary, it produces the primary, how
can thar
primary, ·not produccd by it, produce h?
MJ..."V(P) p. 150; MKV(V? p.61.
163
Here again, Nagarjuna rcfuses to rccognize the mutuaJ
dependence of causc
and effect in the contoct of an active or substantialist
theory of causarion.
7. Ayam utpadyamanas te kamam utpiidayeń tfna'f!J,
yadimam uipadayitum aj'iital? śaknuyiidayt1'1!J.
This, while arising, ifit may so dcsire, producc tbat, so
that it, bcing not
yet bom, will be able to ptoducc tbat.
MKV(P) p.150; MKV(VJ p.61.
At this point Nagarjuna proceeds to state the Sautrantika
theocy ofcausation,
whkh is described vcry succinctly by Vasubandhu (Akb
pp.76-77). The
Sautrantikas believed that the Buddha's discourse on the
three characte.riscics of
existence-arising (utpiit:fr!), change of what has endured
(sthitasyanyathiitva),
and ceasing (11yayt1)-was intended for the foólish people
who arc blinded by
ignorance (avidyandhabaliif?). According to them, the
rccognition of ~uch
charactcrisdcs iovolves the belief in the subs~ntial
e.xistence (a1JittJa) of the
"conditioned'' (Jaf!lskrta) (sec ibid., p. 77).
Howcvcr, thesc three charactcristics
arc not part of reality which consists of momentary
(kfaf!ika) cvents. Such
momentacy events or imprcssions coming one after another in
rapid succcssion
(PUrvasya purvasyottarakfa?Jasyiinubandhaf?) produce~ the
appearancc of
"change of what has endu.red" (Jthityanyathatva),
-vvbereas it is merely a serics
of cveots (pra11aha) resembling one anothcr (a11isadrśa). In
sucha contcxt, arising is merely the immedidatc arising from ·a state of
non-existence
(pratt'k!4'!am abhii.tva hhiiva utparlal(). A moment thus
comes to be from
oowhere and ceases immediately. (Here one is naturally
remindcd of the Humcan version of causal rdacioos.)164 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE
MIDDLE WAY
In the presenc verse, Nagarjuna is providing his own
description of the
Sauttanrika theory of change. As chis cheory is based upon
the recognition of
momentarioess (k!aT!ikatva), Nagarjuoa insiscs that the
preceding event has to
produce the succeeding event (in the series of similar
events) even before the
former is born, for the former does not endure in order co
produce the laner. In
other words, if there were to beany causal connection
between two momencary
eventS, the moment chat serves as che cause should be·ready
to generare the cffect before it passes away, that is, eveo beforc it is boro.
8. Pradipal/ sva-par'iitmanau Ja??Jprakafayita yatha,
utpiidaf? svapaiiitmiinav r·bh'iiv u1padayet tathii.
As a light illuminates itself as well as others, so does
arising produce both
itself and others.
M.KV(P) p. 15 1; MKV(V} p.62.
Here, a meraphor is utili:zed to exp\a.\n che Sautrancika
version of the causal
theory. The·thrust of the argument i~ ~hac ie is noc
necessary for an event to en-
.duce before it can produce some other cffect. A lamp or
light does not have to
remaio for a while beforc it could illuminate itself as welł
as others. This is che
same argument ~cd by the Sautrantikas and óther idealistic
schools to ju'stify
the existence ofa c'tigito discussed above (see also Masaaki
Hatrori, Dignaga On
Perception , Cambridge: Harvard Uoiversity Press, 1968, p.
101). The
Sautrancikas feared chat any conception ofduration or scatis
(sthitt) will lead co
the unacceptable view of subscance (111abhiiva).
9. Pardipe niindhakaro 'sti yatra ciisau prafi!fhitaf?,
kif!1 prakiiśayati dipaf? prak'iiśo hi tamo- vadhaf?.
There ex.ists no ~rkness ei.ther in the light or in whatever
place it is
siruatcd. What does light illuminate? For, illumination is
indeed the
dcstruction of darkness.
MKV(P) p.151 ; .MKV(v,J ·p.62.lHE EXAMINATION OPTHE
CONDITIONED 165
Nagarjuna's criticism of the Sautrantika theory begins here.
In order to get rid
of the metaphysics associaced with the Saucriinika cheory of
change and
causation, Nligarjuoa begios by quescioning the meaning of
the term "illumination" (prakiifa). For bim, light (a/oka) and
darkoess (andhaliiira) are
relative ideas. This same idea is expressed by the Buddha at
S 2. lSO, wherc it i.s
said: ''This so-called element of light is known through its
dependence upon
darkness'' (yayaf(J . , , abhadhiitu ayaf(J dhatu
andhakiiraf(J paficcapaflfiiiyati;
see also Nagarjuna's discussion in his R.atniiva/i
[Ratnava/i ofNiigarjuna, ed.
G , Tucci,joumal ofthe Royal Asiatic Society, London, 1934,
1936, l.48]). The
relatonship herc is by way ofconrrast; the absence ofone
means che presence of
che othcr. Thus, "i łłumination" is synonymous
with the "destruction of
darkness" (lamo-vadhaf?). one is nor produced by the
ocher in any substantiaJ
way.
10. Katham utpadyamanena pradipena tamo hataf(l-,
notpadyamiino hi·tama!? pradipaą piiipn11te yadii..
How can darkness be desrroyed by the emergent light, when
the emerging Light, indeed , does not teach darkness?
MKV(P} p. 152: AfA.'V(V) p.62,
The example of light and darkness used to i lłus trate che
causal relationship berween two momenrary evencs is here showo to be
inappropriatc, as
ie cvenrually leads to a rarher substancialist nocion of
light reaching up to
d:ukness in order to destroy ie.
11. Aprapyaiva
pradipena yadi va nihatarrt tama!?,
iha-Slahal,
sarva-loka-sthaf(J sa tamo nihani!yati.
On the contrary, if darkńess is destroyed by light witbout
reaching ic.
then chat [light) rcmaining here will destroy the darkness
present in all
the woclds.
MKV(P) p . 15 :\ ~ MKV(J.? p.62166 TuĘ PHlLOSOPHY oF THE
Mmoµ WAy ·
The cootrary of the substantialist view referred to at
VII.10 is here shown to
lead to furthcr confusion. Iflight can destroy darkness
without reaching it, the
implication would be that any spack oflight anywhere can
destroy the darkness
present in the entire universe.
12. Pradipal/ sva-paratmiin11u Saf!Zprllkaśayate yal/1;
tamo 'pi svap11ratmii1111u cliiidayi/yaty a.raf!JŚayaf'!'.
If light were to illminate both itselfand otherS, then
certain.ly darkness
too will .conceal itself and ot~ers.
MKV(P) p.154; MKV(V) p.63.
Taking the acgument ofthe subsrantialist at VII.8 that light
illurninates itselfas
well as others, Nagarjuna is herc showing that the same
could be said of
darkness too, which would invalidate the meaningfułness of
the very example
ilsed by the substantialist.
13. Anutpanno 'yam utpadaf? svatm'iinaf!Z janayet kathaf!Z,
athotpanno janayate jiite kif!Z jany4te p11naf?.
How can this non-arisen arising ptoduce itself? Hitis the
ariseo that pr<>-
duces, theo being boro, what is it that is produced again?
MKV(P) p.157; MKV(V) p.64.
·The principle adopted at I.6 in criticizing the identity
and non-identity
theorics of causation is herc applied to reject the notion
of a self-creating arisIng. The metapliysical assumptions associated with the
Sautrantika theory of
momentary arising is laid bare by an cxamination of the
so-called "deep struc·
tures.''THE EXAMINATION OF THE CONDITIONED 167
s
Arising produces itself.
NP VP
i. (non-arisen) arising
ii. (arisen) arising
produces itself
produces ltself
The first alternative is impossible. The second is
meaningless.
14. N olp11dyaman11f?Z notpannaf?Z nanutpanna'f?Z
kath(N!1cana,
utpadjate tathakhyata'f?Z gamyamiina-galiigataif?.
Neither the present arising, nor the arisen. nor the
non-arisen, is being
arisen in any way. This has alteady been explained by mea!15
of [the concepts of] present moving, the moved and the not yet moved.
MKV(Pj p. 157~ MKV(V) p.64.
The anałysis of present arising (utpadyamana), ·the atiscn
(utpanna), and the
noo-arisen (111'1Utpanna) conceived ofin metaphysical terms
compares wełl with
the analysis.of motion in Chaptcr Il.
15. Utp11dyamanam utpattav idaf?Z na kramate yadii,
katham utpizdyamanaf!' tu parlf.tyotpatti1!J ucyate.
When this present arising does not proceed from wichin
arising, indeed,
how can the present arising be spoken of as dependent
arising?
MKV(P) p.158; Mk'V(V) p.6j.168 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIODLE
WAY
The first line utllizes the concepcual apparacus of rhe
subscantiałists in speaking
of the effect (i.e.. che present arising. utpadya1nana) as
issuing out of the c:ause
(i.e., the arising, utpattt). This is a theory of
self-production. As indicated in
1.7, Nagarjuna rejecrs this causa! explaoacion as
meaningless, for there is acrually no production of anything new in such a
cootext. lt is mere self-re·
production.
If the substancialist were to adopt the cerminology ofthe
Buddha(utilized so
oftcn by Nagarjuna), theo he could say that the
"presenc arising is dependent
(prafitya) upon arising. '' Even though this souods like the
Buddha's (and,
therefore, Nagarjuna's) formulation of the causa! principle,
yet Nigarjuna is
not willing to recognize it. This is because dependent
arising does oot simply
mean the·reproduction of the same thing. In che present case,
it is an explanation of the present arising (utpadya1niina) on the basis of
arising (utpallt),
which is simply tautological with no new informatioo
provided. "Dependent
arising" accounts for the arising of something new or
differenr, even though
such newness or difference is not emphasized to the complcte
neglect of the
cela cionship of dependence.
The present verse is indicacive of che manner in which the
Saurrancikas,
while trying to explain causation in terms of
"associacioo" of discrere momeotary cntities, wece evencually led co
a substantialist concepcion causacioo. Eirher
they had co accept self-causation or remain satisfled with
rnere self-re·
production, the latter providing no explanation of
creacivicy at all. "Dependent
arising,„ on che conrcary. accounts for creacivity without
falling into the
substancialist trap.
16. Parfitya yadyad bha11ati tat tac chiinla'f!l
svabhiivataf?,
tasmad uJpadyamiinaf!l ca fiinJam utpattir eva ca.
Whatever that comes to be dependently, thac is inherently
peaceful.
Therefore, that which is presenrly arisiog as well as
arising icself are
peaceful.
!lf.KV(P) p. l ~9- 1 60 : ,W.Kll(V) p. 6~ .
This singularly imporcanc statemcnt in the prcsent chaptet
comes after Vll.-15
where Nagarjuna refused co recognize a form of „dependent
arising" chat alsoTHE EX11MINA110 N Ot THE CONDIT10NBD 169
carries the implication of self-tausation (svata-utpattt).
The nocion of depen·
dent arising (prafitya bhavati = prafityasamutpada) is
simply free from any
idea of sdf-causation involving substance or self nature
(s11abliii11ata4 ś'iita'?!-)
and. in tbat sense, is "inhereotly peaceful." 1t
does not contribute to the notion
of "self1 (atman, svabhava) or "other" (para)
and , as a result, does not generate
lusc (riiga) or hacred (dvefa), anachment or aversion. It is
the more appropriate
view regarding the present arising (utpadya1nana) as well as
arising (utpatt1)
and constitutes an understanding (jnana) or wisdom
(prajifii) thac brings abouc
freedom (vimuk11: nirvaf!a). It is indeed not a negation of
arising (utpada, utpattt), but simply a non-substantialist way of percciving
such phenomena.
17. Yadi kaścid anutpanno bhava!J sa'f!J.vidyate kvacit,
utpadyeta sa
kirtt ta1mirJ bhava utpadyate 'sati.
If a cectain non-arisen existent js evidcnt somewhere, theo
that would
arise. When sucb a thing does not exist, how can.an
exist.ent anse?
M.KV(P) p.160; M.KV(V) p.66.
Here Naga(juna, seems to be sctting up the Sarvascivada
theory ef identity
against the Sautrintika view of non-idencicy. The identity
theory of causation
recognizes an ~nticy (bhava), permaoent and cternal, lying
concealed
somewhere (kvacit), and therefore not yet arisen
(anutpanna). If sucha thing
wece to exist, theo it could be said to arise. However,
ifsucha thing were to be
non-existent (lasmin asat1). how can one say chat a ching or
eotity arises? This
is, once again, a criticism of the Sauttantika tbeory of the
arising of a nonexisting enrity (abhutv?i bh?i11a utp?ida, Akb p. 77; sec also
Kalupahana ,
Causa/ity , p. 151). Hete, Nigarjuna is maintaining that the
Sarvastivada
cheory of causacion, though excessively metaphysical, may be
intelłigiblc in
some w.ą.. but that the Sautrancika theory of the arisiog of
a non-existent entity
makes no sense ac all. ·
18. Utpadyam4nam utpiido yadi cotpadayaty ayaf?l,
utpadayet tam u.tpadam utp'iida/f katamal; puna~.170 J).rn
PHILOSOPHY OF Tf!E MIDDLE W /\Y
lfarising we(C to produce this prcsent arising, which
arising would again
produce tbat arising of that arising?
MKV(P) p.161; MKV(P) p.66.
lnfinite Iegress becomes a n~essary corollary of the
Saumntika theory of
momentary events. As mencioned eaclier, the Sauttantikas
were compelJed. to
assume the notion of potentiality (fa/dz; hi/a) in order to
avoid such infinite
regrcss. Nagarjuna was not ready to accept tbat solution.
19. Anya utpadayaty enaf!t yady utpido 'navasthitif?,
athanutpacla utpannaf? sarvam uJpadyate tr;th'ii,
If this arising were to produce another, arising would turn
out to be in- ·
finite regression. H the non-airising IS arisen, then i.t
will produce
everything in tbis manner.
MKV(P) p.162; MKv(fl? p.67.
Not only does the Sautrantika theocy lead to infinite
regress (anavastha), it also
contributes to the chaotic view that anything can come ~ut
of anything, whicb
is the opposite of the Sa..cvastivada v.iew that notłUng
comes out of nothing._
Causa! unifocmity bas no place whacsoever in che
Saucta.ntika scheme of
things. This is another point of comparisoa between the
.Sauttaatika and Humean views of causatioa. ·
20. Sataś ca tavad utpattir asataf ca nri yujyate,
na sataś c'iisataś cetipurvam evopapadita?JJ.
As such, neither the arisi.ng ofan existcnt noc the arising
ofa non-existent
is pcopec. .Even se is the arising of that whlch is both
existent and nonexistcnt, and this has been pteviously explained.
MKV(P) p .162; MKV(V) p.67.THE EXAMlNATION OF TI-IE
CONDITIONED 171
Neither the identity thcocy of causation nor the
oon-identity theocy nor cven a
cornbinacioo of these two will appropriatcly account for all
the issucs rclating to
causation. This idea continucs to be emphasizcd by
Nagarjuna.
21. Nirudhyamiinasyo1p111Jir na bhavasyopapadyate,
yaś c'iinir11dhyamiinas tu sa bh'ii110 nopopadyate.
The ańsing ofan existent tbat is ceasing is not appropriate.
Whatever cxistcnt that is non-arising, that cxistent too is not appropriate.
MKV(P) p.163; MKV('1 p.67.
The theory discussed at VU.20 was the arising of a
non-existent entity. The
discussion oow moves oo to the question rcgarding the
arisiog ofan event that
is ccasing. The Abhidharma interpreters recognized two typcs
of causes (helu)
that provide a foundation for the causal efficacy of an
cvent that is ceasing
(nirudhyamane k'iirilraf!!- dvau hefii kuruta4, AK ii.63;
AKB p.100; also see
definition of k'iiritra at AD 321; Adv p.281). Nagarjuna is
reluctant to acccpt
even the fact that an existebt that is on ics way to ceasing
can arise. In other
words, cessation and arising cannot be describcd as evcnts
taking place in relacion to the same entity. Or moce specifically, a changing
substance is unacceptablc to Nagarjuna. Similarly, one cannot speak ofan cntity
that is not ceasing
(11nirudhy11miina).
22. Na sthita-bh1i11a.J li/thaty as1hi1a.bha110 na tifthatz~
na tifthati tirthamiina4 ko 'nutpannaś ca f#thati.
An existent that has endured is not stationary, nor is an
existent t.hat has
not endurcd. The presently cnduring is not stationary. What
non-arisen
can stay?
A1KV(P) p.164; MKV(V) p.68.172 THE PHILOSOPHY OP THE MIDDLE
WAY
Tbc Sarvasdivadins (especiaJJy the Vaibha~ikas) argued thac
u nless "stasis"
(sthit1) of an encity (dharma) is not recognized , ie causał
efficacy also cannot be
admirred (Adv p.109). This is conrrary co the view (referred
co in VTI.21) expressed by the Sautrantikas, namely, chat an entity, wheo it is
ceasiog, can
generace causaJ efficiency. Thus, while the Sautraocikas
rcfused to recognize a
moment of scasis fearing chat ie would lead co a belief in
substance, the Sarvastivadiris insisted upon admittiog such a static momenc.
As such, the Sarvastivadins can maintain that a static
moment cndures
(11hita-bhavaf? tiffhatt) , primariły because they assumed
that scasis has its own
oacure (111abha11a). lf there was no such narure, chen
phenomena could not eodure. Herc again, we have the discinccion between a
phenomenon and its static
narure. Whac Nagarjuna is denying hece is not chat a
phenomenon can endure,
but chat a static nature can endure (asthita-bhavaf?
tiffhatt)? This woułd appear
to be seł f-concradictory to Nagarjuna. To say chat
"presently enduring is enduring" {tt/(hamanaf? tt/ fhall) woułd be
taucologicaJ.
All the above mencioned views would pertain to something
chat has ąlieady
arisen. Finally, Nagarjuna insists chat we cannot speak of a
non-arisen entity as
having scasis.
23. Sthitir nirudhyamiinasya na bhavaJyopapadyate,
yaf
canirudhyamiinas tu sa bhavo nopapadyate.
Duration of an ~tent that is ceasing is noc appropriate.
Whatever existenc chat is non-ceasing is also not.appropriate.
MKV(P) p.164; MKV(V} p.68.
While the Sautrancikas (a.S mentioned earlier) recogoized
causaJ efficiency in a
phcnomcnon at the moment of its arising (utpada). and as
such they did not
have co accept a static moment, che Sarvascivadins argued
chat without a static
moment a phenomenon caaaot generate any causal efficiency
(yadi hi dharmasya sthitir na sya11 tasyatmanya11a1thria1ya hetvakhjiif?
faktiprabha11a11iśefO
na.Jyat, Ad11 p.105). A moment of stasis is ro be foJlowed
by decay (jara) and
destruction (11yaya). If the Sarvascivadins were noc happy
abour cecognizing
causa! efficieocy of a pheaomeaon at che moment of its
ar-ising, che moment
being such a minute instant of time. they will be compelled
to admic such
causaJ efficiency in a scacie moment as ie begins to
disappear (ntrudhyamana).
Nagarjuna's argument, here is, thereforc, direcced agains
che SarvascjvadinsT HE EXAMfNAilON OF THE ( ONDITIONED 173
wheo he says: "The duration of an existent that is
presently ceasing is not ap·
propriate." However, someone may assume that Na~rjuna's
C(idcism of the
Sarvaśtivada theory of scasis would mean that he is
compelled co accept che contrary view, oamely, that therc is a phcnomenon chat
is not ceasmg
(anirudhyamana). This lattet view he rejects in che second
lioe.
24.
jarii-mara11a-dharrrtef,u rarva-bha11e1u sarvadii,
t;,,thanti katame bhava ye jafii-1nara1Jan,z vina.
When all existents are always of the nature ofdecay and
death, which existents that are without decay and death can stay?
MKV(P) p"l65; MKV(V) p.68.
This is a simple Iejection of any metaphysical idea
pettain.ing to the real stasis
(sthitt) of phenomena. This rejection is based upon the
empirical notions of
decay and death (jara-maraf!4) emphasized by the Buddha
himself.
The interpretets of the Abhidharma seem to have experienced
difficulty in
reconciling the Buddha's description of the
"dispositionally cooditioned"
(san,iskrta) as having three characceristics (tn11i
lak1a11am) (A 1.152; TsenB
12. 5 [Taisho 2.607c)) with chei.r owo theories
ofmomeotarioess. While the Sarvastivadins recognized a fourth moment (caturtham
atra vaktavya'f(l syat, Akb
p .75), splitting up "change of what has Iemained''
(thitassa aflfJathatta) into
ewo moments as sc.asis (sthiti) and decay (anyathiitva,
jara), the Saucriinrikas admitced ooly two moments rejectiog both stasis and
decay. The Theraviidins accepted a thcocy of three moments , once again
omitting decay.
The need for recóg.nizing stasis o.n the part of the
Sarvastivadins and its
denial by the Sautrantikas is discussed at length by
Vasubandhu (Akb
pp.75·76). Both schooJs assumed (and this is the case wich
the later
Theravadins coo) chat the Buddha's definition of the
"dispositiooally conditioned'' in tenns of three Gharacceristics (as
arising, decay or change of what has
remained, and ~easing) is for the sake'of the unenlightened
(11ineyajan'iirthaf?').
They argued chat it is for this reasoo chat the Buddba
utilized the rerm ''appeats" (pannayati, prajnayate) when speaking of
these three charą.cceristics.
However, chis is not the case with the Abhidharma theory of
moments (na tu
kfa1'!1JJya).
The incerpreters of the Abhidha.rrna (hardly realizing chat
the Abhidharma
did not have a theory of momencs) wece making a distinccioo
between the174 D-ffi Pl-ifLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
"discourses" (1utra) and Abhidharma, comparabłe to
the distinction made in
the Saddharmapu11 f1Jnka between the Agama and Mahayana
discourses. They
assumed that the Abhidharma aoałysis (i.e. , in terms of
moments) is for those
who reałly understand the "meaning" (arthajiia),
not for those who merely go
after the "texts" (granthajfla). Thus carne to be
established the definition of
Abhidharma as concaining "taintless wisdom"
(prafl'ii 'ma/ii J'iinucara 'bhidharmaf?, AK i.21).
Nigarjuoa soems to have remained undaunted by such claims on
the part of
the Buddłiist metaphysicians. He was probably aware that all
three
metaphysical views presented by the Sarvasrivadans, the
Sautrantikas and the
!acer Theravadins (the last was pcobably not knowa to bim)
were incompatible
with the Buddba's own conception of change explaioed in
terms'of decay and
death (jafii-maraf!a). Thcrefore, he perceives no existents
(bh1iva) that arc free
from decay and death.
25. Sthityanyay1i Jthitef? sthanaf?l tayaiva ca na yujyate,
utpadasya yathotpado natmanii na paratmana.
The endurance ofan cnduring tbing bascd. on the eodurance of
jrself or
ofanother is not pcopet. lt is likc the absencc ofarising
ofarising, cither
from itself or from anothe.r.
MKV(P) p. 165; MKV(V? p.68.
lfstasis (sthit1) we.re to be a distinct event, theo the
metaphysicians who needed
to explaio such an eveot in terms ofcausality will have to
maintain that it could
occur either depending upon itself( =self-causation,
svatotpatti) or based upon
another (externaJ causation, para/a JJtpattt). Both are not
appropriate. This is
simiłar to the criricism made of arising ac VII .18- 19.
26. Nirudhyate naniruddhaf?l na niruddhaf?l nirudhyate,
lathapi nirudhyamana11J kim aj1ita1J'} nirudhyate.
T~t which has not ccased does not cease. That which has
ceased also doesTHE ExAMINATION OF THE CONDITIONED 175
not cease. Even so is that which is ceasing. Is it the
urtborn that ceases?
MKV(P} p.i67; M.KV(V) p.69.
After analysing the metaphysical concepts ofarising
(utp'iida) and stasis (1thitt),
Nagarjuna settles down to an examination of the problem of
cessacion or
destruction (nirodha, vyaya). 1his criticism follows the
method adopted at II. l, ex·
cepting the finał question: "Is it the unborn.that
ceases?" lfcessation were to be
understood in the sense of momentary cessation, it cannot be
explained.
However, if one wece to accept a permanent and eternal
substance (111tJbha11a)
which would, at the same time, be unborn (a1izta), as the
Sarvastivadins did ,
then that cenainly cancot cease to exist.
27, Sthita.rya tavad bha11asya nirodho nopapadyate,
nasthita.ryapi bhava.rya nirodha upapadyate.
The cessation of an existent that has endured is not
appropciate. The
cessation of an existent that has not endured is also not
appropriate.
MKV(P) p. 168; MKV(V) p.70.
As mentioned earlier, the Buddha's discourse pertains to
"change of what has
remaioed'' (!hitassa afJńathatta), where ''what has
remained" (!hita) would not
imply something that has remained static without any change,
but rather "what
has become" (bhUta, bhutva). What has become can then
cease to exist. Tuus,
"change of what has remained'' (namely. something that
has undergone a process ofchange or uansfocmation-vzParif!ama) can come.to an
end. Hence, itis
meaningful to speak of cessation (vaya) after "change
of what has remained"
(fhilassa afJfJathatta),
However, this is not the case with stasis (sthitt) as
explained by the
metaphysicians, primae.iły because. such stasis was
disringuished from change
(anyathatva). As such, stasis implied that sornething
remains static, without
change, for a while and then without any cause or reason it
would suddeoly
start changing or would cease to exist. This is the
implicatłon of the rheory
refe.rred to in the first line which is not acceptabłe co
Nagarjuna. ,
The second line implics the equally metaphysical and
unacceptable view of
the Sautrantikas who argued that an eveot ceases immediately
upon arising176 Tur! PHILOSOPHY OF THBMIDDLE WAY
without remaining cven for one moment (k/a11ikasya hi
dharmasya 11ina sthitya
11yayo bhavet, Akb p.77).
28. Tayai11a11aslhayii11aJtha na hi sai11a nirudhyate,
anyajii11aJ/haya11aJtha na canyai11a nirudhyate.
lndecd, a certain state [of cxistence] does not cease Crom a
state identical
with its owo. Nor docs a state [ofexistence] cease from
another state dif.
ferent &om its own.
MKV(P) p.169; MKV(V) p.70.
The principles of self-causation (siJata-uljJatli) and
external causation (paratautpattt), rejected in Chapter I, may have to be
adopted in order co explain cessacion itself (nirodha), if the latter were to
be uoderstood in the way the Sar·
vascivadins and the Saucrancikas conceived of it. Eithcr
ccssacion will havc to
occur on its owo, or on .the basis ·ofanother. Such
discussions were rampant
ducing the scholastic period in~n philosophy (especially
with the domination of the doctrine of mome,N;_armess) whcn it was argued as to
whether
dcstruction is inherent in birth or whether,~ is brought
about by extcrnal causcs
or conditions (sec Ad11 pp.106-108). Nigarjuna's rejection
applies to both
VICWS.
29. Yadaiva sarva-dharniii111im utpado nopapadyate,
tadai11a rarva-dharm7h!i'f' nirodho nopapadyate..
Indccd, when the arising ofall things is not appropriatc,
then the ccssation of all things is also not appropriate.
MKV(P) p.169; MKV(V) p.70.
Note chat the term sart1a (all) is uscd as an adjective
ofdharma, but not utpida
(arising). This means thac Nagarjuna is not rejecting all
forms of arising (sariiautpada) as being unsatisfactory. Ratber, he·is critical
of utilizing the concepcionTHE EXhMINhTION OF IBE CONDITIONED 177
ofacising-(111pada), discussed previously, to any or all
pbenomena (dharma). If
arising in a metaphysical se:ise cannot be applied to all
phenome~a , then
cessaton (nt'rodha) too, similarly conceived, is
inapplicablc. ·
30. Sataf ca tavad bha11asya nirodho nopapadyate,
ekatve na hi bliiivaf ca nabhavaf copapadyafe.
Furthermoret the ccssation ofa real existent is not
appropriate. lndecd, in
the context of identity, neither existence nor non-existence
is appropriate.
31. Asato 'pi na bhavasya nirodha upapadyate,
na d11iliyasya firasaf? chedanaf?' vidyaJe yatha.
The cessation of an unreal existent is also not appropriate,
just as a second
beheading [of a person] is not evident.
MKV(P) pp.169-170; MKV(V) pp.70- 71.
Nagarjuoa's criticism so far has been confined to arising,
stasis and ceasing
metaphysically conceived as events in themselvcs. In the
present contexts, he
retums to the criticism ofthe ccssacion of real existcnts
(satal; bha11asya), similar
to the criticism of the real cxistents in Chaptcr I. Neither
existence or noncxistence,- nor a combination of both. arc acceptablc to him.
32. Na svatmana nirodho 'sli nirodho na pariitmana,
utpadasya yathotpado na~mana na para1mani.
There is no cessarion by i_tself or by anothcr entity, just
as the arising of
arising is neither by itsclf nor by another.
MKV(P) p.lvl ; MKV(V) p.71.178 THE PH TLOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE
\Y/AY
This is the fioaJ criticism of che identity and non-idencity
cheories as applied to
the idea of cessation (nirodha). lt is comparable to the
criticism of arising (utp'iida) presenced at vn.l 2.
33. U1p'iida-1thiti-bhańganiim asUlher n'iisti
Jaf!llkrtaf!J,
Sa'f!Jskrtasyaprasiddhau ca kathaf!J setsyaty
asa1'(lskrtaf!J.
With the non-establishment of arising, duration and
destruction, the
conditioncd docs not ex.ist. With the non-establishmentof
the conditioncd, how could thece be the uoconditioned?
MKV(P) p.1 76; MKV(V) p.73.
Arising (utpiida), stasis (s1hiti), and destrucdoo (bhanga),
as explained by the
metaphysicians, would not establish their conception of che
"conditioned"
(Jaf!llkrta). If the "conditioned", so conceived,
is not cstablished, indeed chere
caooot be a similarly formulated conception of the
"unconditioned"
(asaf!llkrta).
One very significant fact chat caonot escape a careful
scrutiny of the contents
of this entire chapter is that, while Nagarjuna has
spccifically criticizcd che
tłuee kinds of even ts (arising, stasis, and ceasing), he
has made oo criticism
whatsoever of decay (jara). In fact, at VII.24 , decay and
death (jari-mararta)
were used as arguments for the rejection of stasis (1thit1).
In short, the Buddha's
owo conceptions of arising (uppada), ceasiog (vaya,
nirodha), change of what
has remained ([hita11a afifialhatta), decay (jar'ii),
impermanence (anicattii) have
been Jeft intact. These have no room for a substantial
entity (an atman, a
svabh'liva) and arc indeed compatible with the Buddha's
famous doctrine of
noo-substantiaJity (anatta). There could be no reason why a
philosopher of
Nagarjuna's caJibre could not distinguish the empiricaJ
nature of the Buddha's
anaJysis of the "characteristics of the disposicionaUy
conditioned" (sal!khatassa
sankhata-lakkha1{iint) from the metaphysical character of
the ideas expressed
by the intcrpreters of the Abhidharma.
34. Yatha mayii yatha 111apno gandharva-nagaraf!J yatha,
tathotp'iidas tath'ii 11hanaf(J tathi bhańga udiihrtaf(J.T
HE EXAMINAT!ON OF THE COND!'rIONED
As an illusion, a dream, a city of the gandharvas, so have
arising, endurance and destruction l:>een exemplified.
M.KV(P) p.1'77; M.KV(V) p.73.
179
If the analys.is of the conteots of the present chapter is
correct, then there
could be no question that the ilłusory character as
exemplified by "dream" and
"the city of the gandharoas'' is appplicabJe only to
the metaphysical ideas of
arising, stasis and ceasing as presented by the interpreters
of the Abhidharma,
and nÓt to any one of the conceprs of arising, ceasing,
decay. change, and impetmanence formulated by the Buddha and accepted by
Nagarjuna hirnself.
The Buddha utilized the similies of foam (phef!a), bubble
(bubbula) ,
mirage (manc1), trunk of a plantain tree (kadalt), and
illusion (maya) in order
w illustrate the non-substaotiality of the five aggregates
(S 3.142). Nagarjuna
is here using comparable simi!ies for the same purpose. A
careless applicatoo of
these similies to explain all forms of ideas, whether
substantialist or nonsubstantialist, has given rise to enormous
misunderstanclings relating to the
Buddhist doctrine.CHAPTER
EIGHT
Examination of Action and the Agent
(Karma-karaka--partk.[a)
1. Sadbhuta4 kiirakal? karma sadbhutarp na karoty ayaf!J,
k'iirtfko napy a.radbhutaJ? karmasadbhutam thate.
'
This really existent agent does not perform a reałly
existent action.
Neither is it intended that a really non-existent agent performs
a really
' ,
non-existent
action.
MKV(PJ p.180;
·MKV(V) p.75.
The examination of the "dispositiona)Jy
conditioned" (sa'f!Mktta) naturally led
Nigarjuna to another major philosophical problem that has
been the subject of
much misunderstanding among the Buddhisrs as well as the
non-Buddhists,
namcly, the _doctrine of karma.
ln the early discourses, karma and saf!Jskara (and,
therefore, sa?!Jskrta) are
mutually related. Wbile karmas arc said to form
saf!Jsk'iiras (see M 2.'121),
saf!Js/iara.r themselves ·arc decerminants of karma. The
Buddha who denied an
eteroal soul or self (atman) was often confrooted by
skeptics who raised the
qucstion as to how karrńas performed by a
"no-self" can affect a person (anafla-
·katiini kammani ka'!' (Aatarp) atfina?!J phusirsanti, M
3.119;·S 3.103). This is
not, howcver, the problem of morał responsibiłity
(karma--phala), which
Nigarjuoa takes up later in Chapcer XVII. The present
problem relates mostly
to the oature ofan action and an agent (karma-karaka). When
this lattec question was raised in the discourses, very often it is said that
there is no substantial
agent who is the author of actions. What is generally
understood as a substantial being (satta) or person (puggala) is nothi.og moce
than a "lump of disposicions" (sańkhiira-pułija, S 1.134), which is
another name for the five aggregates
(khandha), cach recciving irs form conditioned by the
sańkhiita.r (S 3.87; Tsa
2 .14 (Tairho 2.llc]). Neither the "lump of
dispositions" nor the aggregates
were considered to be substantial, that is, having a reality
of their own. The
"clispositions" (sańkhara) , which arc acquired by
the person and, therefore, im·
perinanent, are also responsible for condiciooing that
personality. Thus,
1ROTHE Ex.AMINATION Of AcnoN AND TiiE AGENT 181
according to early Buddhism, neither the person nor die
aggregate~ (one of
whicb is disposition, sankh'iira) have any substaotial
reality. Io the fitst place,
the dispositions chemselves arc impermancnt (11ayadhamm4
sank~iira, D
2.156) and, secondly, all phenomena, includińg all persons
or aggregates, arc
non-substantial (sabbe dhammii anrJttii, M 2.228; S 3.133;
4.401; A 1.286;
Tsa 10.7 [Tairho 2.668)).
Yet, when the canonical Abhidharma tex:ts rejected a real
self or soul (atta)
and listed the various physical and psychological factors
that go to constitute
the human personality, the intcrpreters of these physical
and psychological factors ttansgressed the limits of speculatioo and admitted
the real existcnce of
these various factors. Thus carne to be the theory of the
substantialiiy of
elemenrs propounded by the Sarvastivadins.
Thcreforc, in his attempt to establish the
non-substantiałity of all elements
(dharma-nairatmya) , Nagarjuna was compelled to examine the
concepts of action (karma) as well as the agent of such action (karaka) in the
prescnt section
of his treatise (leaving the question regarding morał
responsiblity for a. detailed
discussion at a later and more appropriate time). As
·explained previously,
Nagarjuna tealized chat the concepts of substantial
existence (sat, astitva) as
well as a.bsolute noo-existcnce (asat, na1tit11a) werc two
cxuemcs to be avoided
in any discussioo of action and agent.
2. Sadbhutasya kn'yii nasli karma ca syad akartrkam,
sadbhula.rya krijii nasti karta ca syiid akarmakaf?.
A rcally existent cntity bas no' activity. Therefore, acton
would be without
an agent. A really existent entity has no acriviry.
Thcreforc, cvcn an agent
would be without action.
MKV(P) p.181 ; MKV(V) p. 75.
This is an cxtremely interesring analysis of the
implicatioru as welJ as the conscqueoces ofadmfrring a rcally existing entity
(sadbhuJa). a soul or a self(atman,
pudgala) or evcn a substance (!vabha11a). The concept of a
self (atman) as envisaged in the substantialist traditions, like the Upanifads,
is one of pure cnti·
ty, permancot and eternal, unaffcctcd by the changes taking
place in the
phenomenal world. lt is beyond all forms of duality and
multiplicity. The con·
cept ofsubstance, even though rarely dcfined as a "pure
encity," yet pactakes of
all othcr characteristics, namely , permanence, eternalicy,
noo-duility, and182 THE PHJLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
non-multiplicity. This means tha.t any activity, any change
in quality, in quancity, in character, or in fórm would bćmerely supe.rficial.
The real or the essential is eternal. Such implications of the Sarvastivada
theory of substance
(svabhliva) wece noted ear1ier (sec Chapter I). If the cause
and effect were to be
idc:ncical in essence, then their diffe.reoce becomes
superficial. A cause becomes
un-productive and wouJd be like a tree stump that .temains
moti'onless (vanjha
ku{a!fha, D 1.14, 56; S 3.211 ; M 1.517;
11vicalit11-nity11tv11, sec Ka1upahana,
Causality , p. 28).
Hence Nagarjuna's statement: "A really existing encity
is without·activity."
This assercion leads to two rather disastrous
conseql.lences, especially for the
doctrine of karma; either an action (lu;muz) will be
rendered agent-less
(a-kartru) or an agent (kartr) would be action-less
(t1-karmakiz).
'3. K11roti yady asadbhuto 'sadbhuta'f!J karma karakal/,
t1hetuka'f!J bhavet karota karfii ciihetuko bhavet.
lfą non-existent age.nt w~e to perfor.m a non•existent
action, the action
would be without a cause, and the agent too would be without
a cause.
. '
MKV(P) p. 182; MKV(V) pp.75-76.
.
Ifone wece to accept the view which is contrary to the one
mentioned at VIU. 2,
that is, a non-existeot entity performing a non-existent
action, then both agent
(kartr) and action (ka"na) would be rendered cause-less
(a-hetuka).
VIII.2-3 thus turo out to be a elear warning against the
universal and indiscriminate application of the examples of "illusion''
(maya) , "dream'' (sv(Zpna) and the "city of the gandbarvas"
(gąndharva-nagara) , espedally in the mattet of explaining
"emptiness" (funyatli) at VIi.34 and elsewhere.
4. Hetiiv asati liiirya'f!J. ca kliraf1af!l ca na vidyale,
tad abhlitie knyli karta karaf!a'f!J ca na vidyate.
' . .
When a cause does not ćxis(, both the effect and the
sufficient conditionT HE EXAMlNATION OF ACTION AND THE AGBNT
arc not evident. When thcse are ooo-existent, activity,
agent and
performance of accion are also not cvideot.
MKV(P) p.182; MKV(V) p. 76.
18}
Furtbcr impłications of the deniał ofa cause at Vlll.3 are
highlighted herc. Not
only would it negate an effecr (karya) or a sufficient
condition (k7ira1Ja), it
wouJd also lead to the abandoning of activity, agent as well
as action, nooe of
which is accepcable to Nagarjuna.
5. Dhamiiidharmau na vidyele knyadiniim aJaf(lbhave,
dharme ciisaty adharme ca phalf(l tajjam na vidyale.
With the non-occurrence of activity, etc., good and bad arc
also not evident. Wben both good and bad do not exist, a fruit arising from
these
would also not be evidcnt.
MKV(P) p .183; MKV(V) pp.76-77 .
Inada's rendering of this verse clcarly indicates his
faitbful adhereoce to the
transcendentalist interpretation of Nagarjuna offered by
previous interpreters
like Stcherbatsky, Murti, Conze, and most of theJapancse
scholars. In spite of
KumarajTva's very elear rendering into Chinese, lnada ttanslates
dharma and
adharma as factors and non-facrors respecrively (p.73).
While ie is crue that the
term dharma is used in the Buddhist texts, both in an
ontołogicał sense (referring to "pheoomcna") and in amore ethical
sense (meaning "good"), cbere is no
evideoce at aU that the negacive term ,a.dharma was ever
used in the former
sense. A careful examinatioo of the contexts in which it
occurs provides sufficient evidence that the term meant "bad" and,
hence synonymous wich
akusala. Furthermore, ofall che terms used co refer to an
effecc, the term phala
occurring in this verse is invariably used in the sense of
"fruit," baviog a morał
connotatton.
The preseot verse. therefore, provides unmiscakable evidcnce
that Nagarjuna was upholding che morał philosophy advocated by the Buddha in
his first
discourse-the Dhammacappa111111an1rs11tla-wbich lays down a
middle pach184 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
bctwccn the two cxtremcs, which in ics rurn is based upon
the philosophicał
middle position prcsented in the "DiscoMrse Io
Kiityayana."
The belief in substancial cxistence or eternalisrn (a11hita,
sassata) leads to
self-denial (at111-kilamathanuyoga) and the idea of
nihilistic non-existence or
annihilationism (n'atthita, uccheda) coQtributes to
self-indulgencc (kiimasukhallikiinuyoga) (sec Iotroduction). Verses VIIl.3-4
refer to che substantialist
and annihilationist views of karma, both of which lead to
the abandoning ofa
morał life (iocluding morał responsibility) as understood by
the Buddha. Having spokcn of artha (effect, fruit, consequencc) in relacion to
pratyaya (cause,
condition) in Chapter I, Nagarjuna is herc
addressing·rumself to the question
regarding the •:fruit ofaction" (karma-phala), a
detailcd treatment of this problem being reserved for a lacer occasion (Chapter
XVII). In the prescnt chapcer,
Nagarjuna's iotcncion is to cxplaio the non-substanciałity
of the "agent'' and
the ''action," rather chan settlc the qucstion of mora]
responsiblity. However,
he could not help rcferring to the "fruics of action,"
primarily bccause the
mctaphysical nocions of "agent" and
"action" contributed to thcir vcry denial.
6. Phale 'sati na mokfiiya na s11argayopapadyale,
marga!? sarva-knya11am. ca nairarthak.yam, prasajyate.
When the fruit docs not cxist, the path of rcleasc or of
hcavcn is not ap--
propńatc. This would imply the futility of all activity.
MKV(P) pp.183-184; MKV(V) p .77 .
Not only is Nagarjuna interested in the ·:ultimate
fruit" (paramartha), i.e.,
freedom ·from sufferiog (mo/qa), he is also concerned with
the fruits (artha,
phala) chat actions can generate as human beings proceed
ałong the morał patb
(marga) gradualJy lcading to thac "ultimate
fruit." Hence his interest in
"heaven" (s11arga), so often discussed in the
"discourses" as the "fruics" enjoyed
by the "wayfa.rer." As far as Nagarjuna is
concerne<l, human actions arc
rendered "fruitless" or "meaningless"
(nir·artha), ifone were co adhere ro either
a theory of eternalism or of annihiłacionisn1 .
7. Kiirakaf? sad-asad-bhutal; sadasat kurute na tat,
par1Upara-viruddha~ hi saccasacc-aikatal? kutaf?.THE
EXAMINATION Of A cnoN AND THE AGENT
An agent who is both existent and qón-exiscent does not
perform an action that is both existent and non-existcnt, for they arc
self-contndictory.
Wherc can cxistence and oon-cxistencc co-exist?
MKV(P) p. 185; MKV(V) p. 77 .
185
After criticizing the subscancfa)jst as well as the
annihilationist views rclating
to agent and action, Nigarjuna examines the theory that
atcempcs. to combine
them. This follows the criticism at I.13. For Nigarjuna,
contradictory
predicates such as existence (sat) and non-cxistence (a.rat)
cannot be applied to
the same thing.
8. Sala ca knyate niisan niisata kriyate ca sat,
kartra sarve
prasajyante dofiis tatra ta eva ht'.
A non-existent action is not performed by a presently
existing agent. Nor
is an cxistcnt action performed by a prescndy non-existent
agent. Indeed,
if that wece to be the c.ue, all errots relating to the
ageots [mentioned
earlier] would follow.
MKV(P) p .185; MKV(V) p .78.
Existence (sat) and non-ex.istence (asat} applied to the
agent and action will
producc some other alternacive rheories than those mentioned
earlier, e.g. :
i. A presently exiscenr agent (santa) performs a
non-existent
(asat) action, and
u. a presencly ·non-existent agent (a.ranta) performs an
existent
(sat) action.
Herc, the agent is described by means of a present
patticiple (santa}.
9. Niisadbhutaf!J na stJdbhi1af/ sad-a.rad-bhuta1n eva va,
karoti k.iirakal? karma puN1ok11lir eva hetubhil/.186 TuE
PHllOSOPHY OF THE M IDDLE W AY
For rcasoos stated above, an agent who has come co be
existent does not
pcrform an action thac is non-existent or botb existcnt and
non-existent.
10. Niisadbhuto 'pi sadbhulaf?' sad-asad-bhutam eva va,
karoli k'iiraka4 karma.purvoktair e11a hetubhil,J.
For reasons -stated above, an agent who has come to·be
non-existcnt does
not pcrform an action chat is exisrcnt or both cxistent and
non-existent.
11. Karoti 1ad-a1ad-bhuto na san nasac ca kiirakal,,
karma tal tu 11ifiinty'iit purvoktair eva hetubhif?.
An agent that has come to be botb existcnt and non-existent
does not
pctform an action that exists and docs not exisc. This coo
should be
undcmood in terms of the rcasons adduced above.
MKV(P) pp. 186-1.87; MKV(V) p.78-79.
WhHe VIII.8 utiłized the present paniciple to refer to the
agent, the preseoc
verses ernploy the past participle: (i) an agent who has
come ro be existent(1adbhuta); (ii) an agent who has come co be
non-existenc(a.radbhula), and (iii) an
agent who has come to be bo~h existent and non-existent
(sadtUadbhuta).
VIII.10 is not found in the Ch inese version.
12. Prafitya karakal? karma taf(t pralitya ca karakaf{l,
karma p Mvarfale nanyal paiy'iimal/
siddhi-k'lżrat!a'f!I>:
An agent proceeds depending upon action and action proceeds
depcncJing upon the agent. We do not pccceive any other way of establishing
(them].
MKV(P) p.189; MKV(TI) p.79THf EXMvUNATION OF ACTION AND 1HE
AGENT 187
After criticizing the metaphysical ioterpretations of agent
(karaka) and action
(karma), Nagarjuna gives a positivc description of both in
terms of the principle of "dependent arisint' (prafityasamutpada). Indeed,
a mote posirive assertion sućh as, "We do oot perceive any other way of
establishing [them]"
(ninyat siddhi-karaf!af!' paśyamal/), is rardy met with in
the Kiirikiis.
13. Evaf!t vidyad upadiinaf?Z vyutsargad iti karmaf!.al/,
k.arttJś ca k4rma-k.artrbhya1~ fe1a11 bh'iiv'iin vibhavayet.
Following this method of the rejection of agent and action,
one should
understand grasping. The remaining existentS should be
c.ritically examined in terms of the concepts of action and agent.
MKV(P) pp.189-190: MKV(V) p.BO.
Nagarjuna began the chaptcr with the problem of grasping
(upadiin'ii). lf he
wece to accept the substantialisr notions of agent and
action, he could not explain grasping. During the course of this chapter, he
was able to anaJyse the
metaphysical (and, therefore, unacceptablc) implications of
the substaatialist
views such as the deniaJ of morał tesponsibility and
freedom. The abandoning
(vyulsarga) refers to the giving up ofsuch metaphysical
views. After giving up
such metaphysical views, he presented an aJccrnacive view,
oamely, dependent
arisiog of both agent and action (VIIl.12). Such a view
allows for a satisfactory
explanacions of"grasping" (11pidiina). A life with
reduced grasping contributes
to worldly fruics such as the attainment of
"heavenly" bliss. The complete
elimination of grasping culmioates in perfect freedom
(mok1a) or the ultima.te
fruic.
This does not mean tbat Nagarjuna has no conception of an
agent or an action or morał responsibility or freedom. It is mcreJy the
renunciatioo of wroog
vicws and che adopcion of more appropriate explanations of
these phenomena.
Such explanations, Nagarjuna concludes, should be extended
to all
phcnomena.CHAPTER
NINE
Examination of the Pri.or Entity
(Piirva-pank1a)
l . Darśana-śr11vt11{iidini vedanadini Clipy atha,
bha11anli yasyt1 prag ebhyaf? IO 'sflly elee 11adanly utll.
"For whomsoever there eicists seeing, heacing, etc.,
and feeling, etc., he
exists prior to these." So do some declare. -
2. Katharti hy avidyamiinasya dllr:ianidi bhavi.!yati,
óbi11<1Iya tasmat prag ebhyaf? IO 'sti blfiivo
t1yavmthitaf?.
How can there be sceing, etc. of an existent who is not
cvident?
Thcrcforc, it is detetrnined that, prior t(l.these things,
such an existent is.
MKV(P) p.192: MKV(V) p .81.
While the previous chapter is devoted to the refutation of
the Canesian enterprise adopted lacer on by some of the Buddhist
metaphysicians, the present
chapcer seems to be ca.king up specifically the Kantian
project, namely, the
assumption of a primordial condition for all forms of
koowledge , induding the
cogito. Heoce the questioo regardiog prior existcnce
(purva).
He could not have beeo unaware of the Buddha's attitude
toward the problem of the past (pubbanta). For a r~dicaJ cmpiricist like the
Buddha,
knowJedgc of the past (afilllf!J.IC n'iif!a) is as important
as any other knowledgc
(D 3.275). Indeed, knowledge of ''dependent arising"
(pa;kcaiamuppada) is
invariably based upon such knowledge. Yet, when the pursuit
of that
knowledge is attemptcd beyond its limi~. that is, when one
tries to achieve absolute certainty w.ith regard to such knowledge, one ends up
·in specułations
regarding the past (pubbanfiinudittht) rathcr than knowledge
(n'ii'!a). The
Brahmajiila-suttllnta refers to a whole hoot of mctaphysicaJ
views presented by
188EXAMINATION OF THE PR10R ENTITY 189
thosc who wece involved in such specułations (D 1.13
ff.,pubbanta-kappik4 =
purriiinta-kalpikii).
Nagarjuna was thus convinced that the concepts of the
cogito, the atman oc
s1111bh?i11a wcte fotmulated by the metaphysicians who wece
actempc~ng to know
the past with ccrtainty. No ocher expl~ation would satisfy
their yearning for
certainty regarding the past. Pec.tnancnt self, cternal
substance, pcc-existing
cogito, a transcendental unity of appercepcion-tbese could
account for wy
breaks or intcrruptions in.human experience as well as their
continuity. The ~mbolism of the chariotecr (Katha Upani1ad 3.3-6) as wcU as the
example .of the
two birds, one enjoying .the fruit, the other watching
(Mu11fhka Upanifad
3.1.1), adoptcd SO cnthusiasticalły by the Brahmanical
thinkers, were g1adually
making inroads into Buddhist philosóphicaJ thinking. The
SammitTyas (if not
identical with, at least relatcd to the Sau~antika school)
we.re accused of permitting such a bclief into the Buddhist fołd. So says
Cand~rkTrci. Yet, Sarvastivada, witb its svabhava-metaphysics is no less
culpable of this deviation
tban the Sammitfyas with their pudgala-mctaphysics or even
the later
Theravadins with the bhavanga·metaphysics. "Nagarjuna
begins the present.
chapter with a statement, not only of this theory, but also
of the rationalizations of thosc who formulatcd such a theory.
3. Dar:fana-fravat}adibhyo 11edanadibhya eva ca,
ya}/ priig 11yavasthito bhaval/ kena prajnapyate 'tha sal{.
Whatever existent is detennined as existing prior to seeing,
hcaring, et~.•
and also feeling, etc., by what means is he [it] made known?
MKV(P) p.193; .MKV(f1 p.81.
As usual, Nagarjuna's first objectioo against positing such
an entity that exists
pdor to the experiences such as seeing. hearing, etc. as wdl
as feeling, etc., is
epistemologicaJ. This objection should serve as warning
against those who
believe chat Nagarjuna recognizes a special intuitive
non-sensuous experience
through which_the so-called "ulcirńarc reality"
(paramiirtha?) is known. In fact,
this question on the pait of Nagarjuna is a elear
incJi§ation of che fact that he
was quite aware of the sort of empiricism advocated by the
Buddha, especiałly
in his "DiscoUISe on Evetything (Sabba-sutta, S 4.15;
sec also Kalupahana, "A
Buddhist tract on empiricism," in PEJP' 19
(1969):65-67).190 THE PHlLOSOPHYOFTHE MIDDLE WAY
4. Vinlipi
darlaniidini yadi casau 11ya11asthita4,
amuny api bha111jyan1i 11ina tena na sa1'!1faya4.
If he is determined as existing even without seeing, etc.,
undoubtedly
even these [i.e. , seeing, etc.] will exist without bim.
MKV(P) p.193; MKV(V) p.81.
After questioning the empirical validity of such an
assumption, Nagarjuna is
herc raising a logicaJ objection. lf a prior existing entity
can be determined
witbout depending upon its experiences such as seeing, theo
ie shouJd also be
logically possible that such experiences as seeing can be
determined without a
prior entity. Indeed, this logical conclusion seems to be so
suqng that Nagarjuna is willing to use the term asa~aya ("without
doubt") co describe it.
5. Ajyate kenacit kalcit ktfrJcit kenacirl ajyate,
kuta!; ki'l'(lcid vina kafcit ki'l'(lcit kaf!lcid 11ina
kutaf?.
Someone is made known by something. Something is m.ade known
by
someone. How coul.d there be someone without something and
something without someone?
MKV(P) p.194: MKV(V) p.81
Herc chen is Nagarjuna's method of explaining (vyakhyana)
the relationship
bctween substance and attribute. lt is a rdation of
dependence and neither che
~·óbstance nor che atuibute can be understood properly if
thcy were to be conceived of as .independent entities, cach having its owo
narure.
6. Sarvebhyo rlarianadibhyaf? kalciJ purvo na vidyate,
ajyaJe darśanadinam anyena punar anyadii.EXAMINATION OF THE
PRle>R ENTl'IY
Sorneone is not evident prior to all ofseeing, etc. Again,
on different occasions, one could bemade k.nown by things different from
_seeing, etc.
' •
MKV(P) p. 194; MKV(V) p .82.
191
While rejecting the view that there is an entity prior to
all fortns of experiences
such as seeing, Nigarjun.a is, at the same time, uying to
avoid the other extrt!me of assuming two different encities when the experiences
are di.fferent.
Avoidińg.a metaphysical nocion ofideocity does not mean that
one is invaciably
coinmitted to an equally metaphysicał notion of difference.
Just as much as
identity can be explained on the basis of an empiricał
notion of dependence,
Nagarjuaa seems to assen that differttnce can and need to be
accounted for oo
an empiricał basis. · /
7. Sf)rvebhyo darśanac/ibhyo yadi purvo na 11i4yale,
ekaikasmiit katha'!l pur110 darśaniidef? sa vidyate.
lf someone existing prior to all of seeing, etc. is not
evident, how can
someone existing prior to cach of seeing, etc. be evident.
MKV(P) p.195; MKV(V) p.82.
It seems that hece Nigarjuna is referring to an
interestiog-assumption underlying·an identity theory. The not1on of self
(atman) or substance (s11abhii11a)
would geoerally be presented in order to account for the
continuity in a large
number of dissimilar experiences. Taking that premise,
Nagarjuna is arguing
that ifit is not possible to discover someoó.e or entity
chat pre-exists all forms of
different experienc.es, then such a person or eotity would
not be available even
in the case of individual experiential situations. A
momentary cogito would be
as impossible as a permanent and eternal self (atman).
8. Df'a.ftfi sa
e11a sa frota sa eva yadi vedakaf?,
ekaikasmiid bhavetputva?!J e11afr.t cailan na yujyate.192
THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
Ifa seer is, at the same time, a hearcrand fecler, then
so1neone would exist prior to cach one [of the functions]. But this is not
proper.
MK.V(P) p.195 ; MKV(V) pp.82·83.
Only if the seer, hearer, and experiencer ace absolutely
identical. chen he will
prc-exist cach individual experiential situation. Nigarjuna
rightły denics any
ruch absolutc identity. He was probably assuming that even
in the act ofsceing
the same object at differcnt times, there cannot be absolute
identity, lee alone
in the acts ofsecing di.ffLrcnr objccts. The reason is not
chat human experiences
or even the objccts of expcricnce change every moment, but
that the circumstances under which such cxperiences take place could vary. (For
a discussion of the perccprual flux, sce WilliamJames, Some Prohlems
ofPhilosophy,
Cambridge , Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1979,
pp.31-32.)
9. Drtl!!finya eva frofjjnyo vedako 'nya!, punaryadi,
sari .ryad dnlffan· frota bahutvaf!l citmanif!l bhavel.
lf seer and hearer and fceler arc different, then, when
there is a seer,
there also would be a bearer, and as such there woułd be a
plurality of
selves.
MKV(P) pp.196·197; MJ.. 'V(V) p.83.
If absolute identiry is not a possibility, absolute
difference also would be im·
possible, for in that case within cach stream of experience
chere would be
plurality of distinct sdves or entities corresponding to the
different experiences.
10. D(lrfana-frava„adini vedanadini cipy atha,
bhavanti yebhyas
te/V e1a bhutepv api na 11idyate.
lt [i.e., the scH] is not evident in the elements from
włtich seeing, hearing, etc., and feeling, etc. come to be.
MKV(P) p.179; MKV(V) p.83.ExAMINATION OF 11-1E PRJoR ENnrr
193
In the Chąpter V on the "elemeocs" (dhatu),
Nigarjuna examioed the theorics
presented by the metaphysiciaos relating to the phy$ical
foundations of human
experiences such as seeing, hearing. etc. Even though the
Abhidharma
classified the fi~t five sensory organs as well as theiI
objects under the category
of derived matter (upadii rupa), there was no indicacioa
that this involved the
assertion of any self or subscance in the individual
elemencs that go to con·
stitute these sensory organs and objects. The interpreters
of the Abhidharma, as
reitcrated earlier, were responsible for sucb metaphysics.
Nigarjuna is herc going back to the analysis in the discourses as well as ia
the Abhidharma where,
not ooly in the combination of aggregates or elements, but
aJso in each in·
dividual element, there is oo recognition of such a
meraphysicaJ self or
subscance (see ałso Chapter IV).
11.
Dar1ana-fravaf!fid'ini vedanad'inicapy atha,
na vidyate
cedyasya sa na 111dyanta iminy api.
lfhe, co whom bclongs sceing, hcaring, etc. and feeling,
etc., is not evidcnt, thcn even thcse would not be cvidcnt.
MKV(P) p .198; MKV(V) p.84.
Nagarjuna starts with the negatioo of an opponent's view
chat there is a prior
cntit:y to which the expcrienccs such as sedng and hearing
belongs. The implication of the opponent's view is that the experiences of
seeing, etc. arc independent elemenrs appropriaced by an equally independent
prior entity. As
such, for Nigarjuoa, it is not merely the prior enricy that
is unacceptabJe, but
also the experieoccs themselves as concdved of by the
opponent. This,
tbcreforc, is not a simple denial of any and all forms of
description of experience. Rather, it is a parcicular type of disccimination
resortcd to by the
metaphysician chat is rejectcd.
12. Prak ~ayo darianadibhyaf? iii1!1-pralaf?1 cordhvam eva
ca,
na vidyate 'sti nasffti nz11r:tt'iis tatra ka/pana.
Whcrcin someonc prior to, simultaneous with or posterior to,
seeing, etc.
i.s not cvidcnt, thcrcin thoughts of existencc and
non-existeoce are a1so renounccd,
MKV(P) p .199; MKV(V) p.84,194 THE PMILOSOPHY OF TI-IE
MIDDLE WAY
The cxistence of an independent enciry in the
cxperientlaJ_prqcess, whe·ther it
be prior to experience, simultaneous with it, or posterior
to it, is rejected by
Nigarjuna. This does not mean that he was willing to accept
the independent
occurrence of impressions co~ing one afrer another in rapid
succession with oo
causaJ connectoins, as the Sautrantikas believed. In these
particuJar contexts
(t111ra), Nigarjuna is ready t.o abandon the thoughts (kalpanii)
of cxistence and
non-e.xistence (11Jli nasffh) in the way they were
understood by the metaphysi~
c1ans.CHAPTER
TEN
Examination of Fire and Fuel
(Agmndhana-pank.ra)
1. Yad indhanaf!l sa cedagnir ekat11af!Z kartr·karma11of?,
anyaf ced indhanadagnir indhanad apy rJe bhaveJ.
Iffire wcrc to be fucl, thcn thcrc would be idcntity ofagent
and action. If
firc wcre to be d.iffcrcnt from fucl, thcn 1t would cxist
evcn without the
fucl.
MKV(P) p .202; MKV(V) p .86..
Chapter Jl(, as pointed out, was devoted to an examination
of the cause or
foundation of the speculations that eveotually led to the
belief in me'taphysicał
notions such as "self' (atman) or "substance''.
(wabha11a). Such specu1ations perta.ined to the "past" (piirva). Why
should that anałysis be followed by an examination of che metaphor of
"fire and fuel" (agncndhana)? What is its
relevance?
Only a glance at the controvcrsies goiog on during
Nagarjuna's day can provi~e justification for this chapter. Once again,
Vasubandhu comes to our
assistance. In his Abhidharmakofa-bh'ii.[ya, he was
recording a conrroversy
among the Buddbists that was continued for centuries before
rum. And that
conuoversy could not have escaped the attcntion of
Nagirjuna.
The ninth chapter of the Abhidharmakofa is an appendix (Akb
pp.461-479; translated inro English by T. I. Stcherbatsky,
The Soul Theory of
the Buddhists, in
the Bul/eling de l'AC11demie des Sciences de Russie,
Petrograd, 1920, repriored 1970, Bharariya Vidya Pra.kasan,
Varanasi). lt deals
with the concroversial views of the YatsTputriyas
(considered to be the same as
the Arya-Samm~tTyas , sec Sakv p.699) who propounded the
view that there is a
"real person" (1anlaf!l pudgalar('). In the
discussion that foll9ws, the
Yatslputriyas arc made to admit tha~. this
"person" is neither a substance
(dravya), łike materiał form (ritpa), etc., nor a mac
designation (.prajnapti), a
merc name like "milk" (kfir11), this lacter being
norhing more than an aggregate ofsubsrances (dravya). Whcn the Sautrancika
V25ubandhu pressed his
195196 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
questioos as to whether the person is real or nominal. the
Yatslputriyas fell back
upon the metaphor of "fire and fuel" (agnindhana)
in order to illustrate their
point of aview (Akb p.461). This metaphor is then discussed
at length and
seems to have been the most important means by whic:h the
Yatslpuuiyas attempted to justify their concepcion of a "person."
Therefore, it is understandable why Nagarjuna. after dealing
with the quescion regarding a substantiał agent (karaka, Cbapter VTII) and ałso
the motiva·
tion for such a theory (nameły , the desire to rrac:e one's
identity to the past,
purva, Chapter IX), would settłe down to an examinacion of a
singularly imponant metaphor used by the substantiałists to justify their conception
of an
agent.
lt may be necessary to keep in mind that Vasubandhu, who
wrote the
Abhidharmakofa, was a Saucrantika who believed that a
"person" (pudgala) is
a merc designation (prajńapt1) without any realiry. Hence
his agreement with
the nominalist position (Akb p .461, a/ha prajńaptif?, vayam
apy evaf!J
brumaf?). The substancialist position (dravya-vada) was
therefore identified
with the Sarvastivada view. Even though the Sarvascivadins
did not actuałly
propound a substantialist theory of a person. their
conception of substance
(wabhavfl) could not escape such implications (sec Sakv
p.362, svabhavala iły
almalal/).
However, even if by implication, the Sarvasrivada theory
were to be iden-
1 tified with che substantialist view of a person (pudgala),
what sort of conception were the Yatslpucriyas upholding? They wece looking for
a middle position between substantialism (dravya) and nominalism (prajfJaptt).
The discussion in terms of the metaphor of "fue and fucł" was,
therefore, intended to
overcome soch dualiry.
The argument follows thus: "Without fuel . there would
be no designation of
fire. Yet, fire cannot be designated a.S sometbing different
from fuel, nor as
·something identical," (Akb p.462, Na hi
vinendhanenagnif? prajńapyale, na
canya indhanadagnif? iakyaleprajflapayifuf?J niipy
ananyal/). Similarly, a person is neirher identical nor different from the
aggregates. (lf we a.re to accept
the oegacive interpretation of the Nigarjunian dialectic, as
is ofren presented
by most modern scholars, tbe Madhyamika position would be no
different
from that of the Yatslputriyas as described above.)
Whc.n the question was raiscd as co which of the six sense
organs provide
knowledge of the "person," the Yatsłputriyas
answered: "By means of all six,"
(1aąbhir api, Akb p.463). They argued: "A 'person' is
rccognized depending
upon visualły cognized materiał form (ca./qur-vijńeyani
filPil'!t.). As sucha personshould be declared as being visualły cognizable and
visually not cognizable;
it is ,neither matecial form nor not materiał form ."
Tbese and ocher arguments seem to indicate thac the
YatsTputriyas were
following a dialectical method at arriving at a higher
synthesis by avoiding theEXAMINATION OF f IRE AND Full 197
dicbotomies of thesis and antitbesis. This, unfortunately,
is the view attributed
to Nigarjuna. The conteots of the present chaptet needs co
be carefully
evaJuated in the light of the Yatsipuuiya conception of a
person.
When the Yatsłputriyas maiotained that firc and fuel arc
neitber identicaJ
nor different, thcy were acruaJly admitting both. Por them ,
both firc and fuel
arc cach constitutcd of four substanccs (ubhayam
11.f{a-dharmakarp), the only
difference is that in the case of firc the heac element
(Uff!t1m) predominates,
whereas in the fuel it is latent. In this way , they arć
both idcncical or noodiffercnt. Yet they arc different in terms of the
difference in time (bhinnaktilatziiit). Thus, the negacivc description of the
Yatsfputriyas is not meant as·
a ncgation of metaphysical views, as it was in the case
ofNigarjuoa (see above,
commentary on the dedicatory verses), but an assertion of
both identity and
difference in order to arrive at a bigher synthesis. No such
move is found in
Nigarjuna when be criticizes the idenciry of fire and fuel
in che above verse.
For hisn identity of fire and fuel rneans identity of agent
and action. If they werc
diffcrent, chen cach could be independent.
2. Nitya-pradipla e1111 sjiidapradipana-helukaf?,
punar arambha-vaiyarthyam evarp ciikarmakafl sati.
A buming without a ause would be eteroally aflame.
Furthecmore, its
commcnccment will be rendercd meani.ogless (usdcss]. Whcn
that happcns, it will be without a function.
MKV(P) p .203: MKV(V) p.86.
The idcntity of fue and fuel recognized by the VitsTputriyas
(as cxplaincd in
terms of the eight elements, alta-dharmaka, sec abovc) would
lead to the view
that both firc: and fucl arc buroing all the time
(nilya-pradipta), for the caloric
element (uma) is found in both, the difference being
quantitativc rather chan
qualicativc. This fucthec lcads to the dcnial of the
e.mpirical fact of starcing a
fire. lf fire and fuel arc always burning, thcn fire would
be deprivcd of any
spcdfic function. Indeed, the Buddha's ust" of the
metaphor of the fi.re at M
l.487 is non-substantiaJist in implication He wantcd to show
rhat just as fire ~
not stoccd up anywhece when it is extinguished, even so a
"frced one"
(talhiigata) does noc e.ióst in ercrnal bliss afrer dcach
(param maraf!"ii). Nagarjuna's criticism of the mctaphor of "firc and
fuel" secms to follow doscly the
Buddha's own cxplanation of the phcnomenon of fuc.198 THE
P~nLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W AY
3. pt1ratrt1 nirt1pek;at11adapradipana-hetuktll/,
p 1111t1r arambha-11aiyqrthyaf!l nitya-pradiptal/
prasajyate.
A burning without a c:ause, bec:ause it is not contingent on
anothcr and,
therefore, etemally aflame, would imply the meaninglcssness
of itS commencemeot.
MKV(P) p.203; MKV(V) p.86.
A substantialist v.iew of fire makes it iodepcndcnt of other
clemcnts or things.
Hcncc, all the ,iinplications mcotioncd at X .2 will follow
from such a view.
· 4. Tatrt1ilt1smad idhyamanam indhanaf!l bha11afiti tet,
k.enedhyat'lim indhanarp, lat tavan matra1n idarrt yadfi.
Hercin, if it is assumed that fuel is the present buroiog
and, therefore,
that [i.e., buring] is mercly this [.i.e„ fuclJ, by what is
fucl bcing
burnt?
MKV(P) p .204; MKV(V) p.87.
The substancialist point of view cxpressed at X.2 is further
analysed herc. Iffuel
already has the caloric element (umt1) and, thcrefore, is
alrcady burning
(idhyam'lint1), one could not only raise the question as to
when it started buroing but also joquite as to whac it is that brings about
that burning.
5. Anyo naprapsyale 'priiplo na dha.ł!yaty adahan punal/,
na nirv'iisyaty anirva„a!, sthasyate 11a svalińgavan.
[Fuel] that is <liffertnt is not reached; the urueached
is not ignited. Furthermore, that wh.ich is n6t ignited does not cease. That
which does not
cease remains, li.kc one that has its owo mark.
MKV(P) p.205; MKV(V) p.87.EXAMJNATION OF FtRE AND FUEL. 199
lf it is assumed that firc and fuel arc different, a futther
serics of questions
arise. Difference in the prescnt case implies absolutc
distinction or in·
dependcnce. As such, one entity cannot reach up to another.
Fice canoot rcach
che fuel. Whcn firc cannot reach the fucl , it cannot burn.
lhat which does not
burn reroains for ever and does not cease. This expla.ins
the vicious circle the
metaphysical speculacions can lead to.
6. Anya evendhanad agnir indhanarrt prapnujiid yadJ~
stn sarrtpriipnoti puru1arrt j;urup1Ś ca striyar{Z yatha.
lf firc is diffcrcnt from fueł it would reach the fueł, just
as a woman
would rcach for a man and a man for a woman.
MKV(P) p.206; MKV(V) p.88.
lffire and fuel wece considered to be different yet
complemcowy, theoNagar·
juna is willing to allow somc son of mutual relationship. He
perceives such a
relationship bewteen a man and a woman.
Unfortunately, herc again 'we have a negacive interpretation
from Can·
dra.krrti. Without ta.king much trouble to cxamine the import
of the metaphor
of "man and woman" uscd by Nagarjuna, Candraklrti
assumcs that the rela·
tiooship exemplified by it is mcaninglcss
(dr1(iinta-t1aiy11rthyattz). On the con·
uary, Nagarjuna is throwing the gauntlcc at his opponent
asking him to show
that the sort of relationship chat cxists bctweeo a man and
a woman can a..lso be
obtaincd between firc and fuel as the opponenl has
conceit1ed ofthem.
Indccd, there could not be much difficulty in understanding
the empirical
rclationship betweeo a man and a woman. Because of their
complcmcntarity,
they arc attracted to cach other. Such a relationship is
dearly expresscd by the
Buddha in the first two discourscs in thc Ańguttara-.nikaya
(1.1-2). Yct the
Buddha ncver attemptcd to go beyond chat cmpirical relacionship-to
inquire as
to how it all happened. Such an inquiry was undoubtedly the
foundatioo of the
speculations recorded in the Upanz'!ads. Describing the
origin of the uaiverse
from a single unitary "self' (atman), the
Brhadiira1}yaka Upanifad (I.4.3-4)
says:
He, verily, had no delight. Therefore he who is alonc has no
dclight. He desir~d a second. He became as large as a woman
and a
man in dose cmbracc. He caused that self to fali into two
parts.
'200 T HE PHlLOSOPHY OF THE MIODLE WAY
From that arose husband and wife. .. . He became united with
her. From chat human bejngs wece produced.
She thought, "How can he unite with me after having
produced
me from himself?" Well, !et me hide mysdf. She became a
cow,
the ocher became a bull and was united with her and from
thac
cows werc boro.... Thus, indeed, he produccd everything
whatever exists in pairs. down to the antS.
This is the son of answer char emerges from an inquiry chat
is noc only
directed at understańding the absolute origin of things, but
also their substancialicy. The metapho,r of the fire and fuel wece utili.zed by
che VitsTputriyas,
not merely co undersr:and the relacionship between two
empirical evencs, but
also to justify the conception of a prior exiscent
"person" (pudgala), no differeot from the pre-cxisccnc
"self" ('iitman) assumed in the Upani/ads, which is
clearly exprcscd in the metaphor of "man and
woman."
Percepcive Nagarjuna was chus aware of the motivations of
those who
presented the metaphor. In the presenc verse he was
therefore allowing the
possibiłity of fire and fuel having a complcmcntary
relationship . Howcver, if
any ocher implication is drawo from such a reJationship,
Nagarjuna was ready
to expose its untenabiliry. This he docs in che verscs chat
foUow.
7.. Anya evendhanad agnir irzdhanam. kaman apnuyat,
agnlndhane yadi .rjiit'iim anyonyena tiriukrta.
The fue that is different from fueJ may rcach the fud only
iffue and fud
wece co exist mutually separated.
MKV(P) p.206; MKV(fi? p.88.
Here agaio, Nagarjuna is qualifying the sort of relatiooship
chat may obtaio
between fire and fuel ifthey arc atuacced to one another.
One of the first conditioos would be that they arc separate. Without such
separation it would be
meaningless to speak of one reachiog for the ocher. It is an
attempt to destroy
the belief in a myscerious underłying unity , any
substantial connection. Nagarjuna is wiUing to allow for the empirical
differences and the relationship of
dependence among such cvents. However, he is not prepared to
leave any room
for any speculation about underlying substances
(.r11abhava).EXAMINl.TION OF flRB AND FUEL
8. Yadindhanam apek,yiignir apek,yignif!J yadindhanaf!I,
katara/ purva-nqpannaf!I yad apek,yagnir indhanaf!I,
Iffire is contingent upon fuel and fuel upon fire, which of
them is p~
accomplished so that fire could be contingent upon fuel?
MKV(P) p.207; MKV(V) p .88.
201
The motivation of the substantfalists who were ucilizing the
metapbors of "fue
and fuel" (agnlnrlhana) as well as "woman and
man" (stff-puru1a), as exlained
at X.6, arc brought to the forcfront hece. Let fire and fuel
be related by way of
cootingence (apek,"ii). Nagarjuna has no objection to
it and this is clearly indicatcd by the manner in which Candrilirti himself
ucilizcs this particularcon;
ceptioo of cootingence on numerous oa:asionions (sec MKV(P)
pp.67, 189,
200, 202.. 345, 492, 527). Io the presenc case, Nagarjuna is
oot rejcccing the
mutual contiogence (paraspar?ipek,'ii) of pheoomena, but
ooly the inquiry
relating to the prc-accomplishmcnt or prior existence
(purva--ni,panna) of any
one of them. Chaptcr IX made it abundantly elear that
speculations regarding
the prior entity led to most metaphysical speculations.
Having raised the ques--
tion as to which one of thcse two thiogs-fue and fuel-is
prior, a questioo
that a substantialist cannot resist asking, Nagacjuna
procceds to analyse the
poss.ible answers and cxplain thei.r unsatisfactory
implication.~ .
9. Yadindhanam apek,fiignir agntl/ n'ddhasya sadhana1!J,
evaf!Z saffndhanaf!I capi bhavi,syati niragnika'f!'.
Ifftre were to be contingcnt upon fuel, there would be proof
of fire th.at
is already proved [to e:xist] . When that is the case, evcn
fucl would exist
without ftr:e.
MKV(P) p.207; MKV(V) pp.88-89.
Frustrating any attcmpt on the part of the substantialist,
Nagarjuna insists that
iffuel wece to be the prior entity (purva-nifpanna), and
that firc is contingent
upon it, then what is to be established is alrcady
cstablishcd. In other words,202 TFłE PHILOSOPHY OF nłE M IODLE W AY
the substantialist interpretations of contingence
(paraspar7ipekfi) would me2.0
that fire is aJready existenr in the fuel , which is itself
the prior entity. If it is
already existent in the fuel, tben the implication is that
it wiJI need no fuel for
its reaJ cxistence. Ifso, fue and fuel could not be murually
contingenc and one
can conceive of fuel without fire (nir-agnikaftl).
10. Yo 'peh,ya Jidhyate bhavas tam etiiipeiqya Jidhyatt~
yadi yo 'pek1ita11yaf? Ja Jidhyaliif(J kam apekfya kal/.
MKV(P) p.208; MKV(V) p.89.
Ifevents are to be truły concingent, then they should be
muruallycontingent or
dependent. If any one of two murually contingent entities is
to be fou o,d in a
substantiał or essential way in the other, then the notion
pf conringe11ce is
nullified. One becomes the essential and the orher the
superficial. The problem chen would be: which depends upon what? The
Wtsfpuą-iyas . as mentioned earlier, werc not looking fot means ofdissolving
idcntity and difference.
They arc struggling to cetain both identity and difference.
and then-move on to
a higher synthesis. Nigatjuna's attempt herc is not to allow
the metaphysici_an
the very concepts of identity and difference, which they
were going to ucilize as
a springboard for leaping coward the notion of a mctaphyskaJ
"person"
(pudgala).
1l . Yo 'pek.tya Jidhyate bhaval, JO 1Jiddho 'pek.tate
kathaf(J,
athapy 4pekfate Jiddhal? tv apek.tazya na yujyate.
Whatevct cxistent that is cstablished through cootingence,
how Cln tha_t,
ifit is not yet established, be conringent? Even so [how
can,] that whi~ is
already establishcd be contingent? F~r, _i~.coot:ingence is
not propec.
MKV(P) p.2ó9: MKV(V) p.89.EXAMJNATION OF flRE AND FuEt 203
X.10 refers to the fire that is already established
(.riddha), chat is, something
that is really existent (sad-bhuta). lfone were to move to
the other extreme and
speak about events that are not established (a.ui:/dha),
that is, those that are
really oon-existent (asad-bhuta), how can such events be
contingcnt (apekfya
sidhyate)?
Thus, neithcr the already established (siddha) nor the
unestablished (asiddha) can be relatcd by way of mutual contingeoce.
Contingence (apek{a) is not
established in thls substantialist way.
12. Apek,yendhanam agntr na nanapek!yagnir indhana1lJ,
apek,ycndhanam agni1lJ na n?inapek;y?ig~im indhana'f?t.
.Fire is .not conti.ngent upon fuel; fire is not
non-contingent upon fuel.
Fuel is not contingent upon 6re; fueł is not non-contingent
upon fire.
MKV(P) p.209; MKV(V) pp.88·90.
1fthe ideas expressed in tl)e present verse were to be
examioed independent of
wha.t went before, it would be. easy to łeap to the
conclusion that Nagarjuna is
here expressing the "inexpreśsible''; that the
negations such as "oon-ceasing''
(anirodhaf!I.) ind "non-arising" (anutp?idaf(l)
wece supposed to elear the way
for the ''non-cohceptual," l•non-dual" ultimate
reality (paramiirtha?). On the
conttary, if these thoughts are placed in their proper
cootext, namely, the
metaphysical explanations of "muial contingence"
(parasparapek!a), -then
'these oegative statements can be understood as outright
rejections of such
metaphysical explanations. As is evident from several
quocatioos from Candra.klrti hiroself (see X.7), "contiogence"
(ttpek!a) can be explained in a nonmetaphysicał or empiricał way, just as much
as the not.ion of cause or condition
(pratyaya) or the idea of motion (gatt) can be elucidated
without falling into
the quagmire of metaphysics (see Cbapters l,Il).
13. Agacchaty anyato nagnir indhane 'gnir na vidyate,
atrendhane śefam ukta11'f gamyamina-gafiigatail;.204 THE
PHJLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
Fi.te does not come out of something different nor is fire
secn to be in the
fuel. Herein, with regatd to fuel, the rest is m.tcd.as i.n
the case ofpresent
moving, the moved and the not movcd.
MVK(P) pp.210-211 ; MKV(V,l p.90,
Mter dealiÓg with che metaphysicaJ interpretations of
"contingence" (apekf1i)
assumed betwecn fue and fueJ, Nagarjuna retu.ens co the more
familiar
substancialist theories of self-causation (svata utpattt)
and external causation
(para/a utpatti). Fi(e is not inherent in the fucl nor does
it issue out of
something external. If any furcher explanations are to be
provided which arc
themselves founded upo·a sucb substantialist ideas, all such
expla9ations can be
analysed in terms of the mechods adopced in Chapter II
dealing with motion
(g_atz).
14. Indhanaf?J
punar agnir na ri1ignir'anyatra cendhanat1
nagnir indhanavan
riiignav indhaniini na teru sal{.
Furthermorc, fuel is not fire. Apart from fucl therc is no
fire. .Fire is not
possessed of fuel. Fucł is not in the fue, noc is it [i.c.,
fire] in them.
MKV(P) p.211; MKV(V) p .91.
The refutation of all metaphysical formulations of the
nocion of identity as applied to fire and fuel is presented here. This is done
in terms of the analyticaJ
methods followed in Chapter I.
15 . Agnzndhanabhyiif?I vyakhyata atmopadiinayoh. kramal;.
s4rvo niravaśefena sardhaf!J ghata-pa{iidibhil;.
Through the examples of fire and fuel, together with the
examples of
pot, cloth, etc. evcry method of analysis of the self and
grasping have
bcen cxplaincd without exccption.
MKV(P} pp.212-213; MKV(V,l pp.91-92.EXAMINAT!ON Of fl RE ANO
fUEL 20~
The metaphysicaJ ioterprecations of "self' (aJman) and
"grasping" (uparliina)
arc exposed here , especially in relacion to the metaphor of
fiie and fuel'
(agn'i'ndhana). Does thls mean thac there could be
ooo-metaphysicaJ expłanacions of both "self' and "grasping?" The
answer would be in the posicive,
especially in vew of whar Nagarjuna has said in reference to
"graspiog" and the
"one who grasps" (uparliitr) or the action and che
agent (ka"na-karaka).
Tbis analysis is not confined to the metaphor of "fue
and fueł" alone. lt applies to all other metaphors used during thls period
ofspeculatioo, such as"cłay
and the pót," and "thread and the doth."
16. Almamif ca satattvaf!Z ye bha11'iin'ii1?1- ca PrJhak
Prthak,
nirdiśanti na fiin manye fiisanasyiirtha-kovidiin.
Those who posit the substantialicy of the self as well as of
disaete existents- these I do not coosidcr to be experts in the meaning of the
(Buddha's] m~ge.
MKV(P) p.214; MKV(V) p.92.
Here then is a elear and unequivocal assercion oo che pan of
Nagarjuna. Those
who assert the substantial exi.Jtence (satat111am), whether
that be of a monistic
"self' (atman) or of distinct enticies (prthak PrJhak
bha11ant1'f!') are not conversant with the teachings of the Buddha. When
Nagaijuna makes that assertion
with the statement: "[I) do not consider"
([aha'!'] na manye), what sorr of self
was he recognizing? It certainly could not be anything like
what he was
refutiog. The answer to this question will be provided
łater.CHAPTER
ELEVEN
Examination of the Prior and Posterior Extremities
(PUrvriparakoti-pank.ra)
1. P"Urva prajfiiiyate kofir nety u11iica mahiimunil/,
J(lf!'J'iiro 'na11ariigro hi nasty adir napi paścimal/.
The Great Sage has stated that the prior end is not known.
The lifeprocess is without beginning and end. There is neither a beginning nor
an end.
MKV(P) p.219; MKV{V) p.95 .
The criticism of the "self" (atman) as a
substantial entity continued in the last
few chapters brings up more related issues for discussion.
If there is no such entity, how can the life process consisting of tepeated
births and deaths be explained?
Rebitth or rebecoming (ptfn(lbbhava) was an important
element in the Buddhist doctrine,, even though the Buddha was concetned more
with the problems of the present life than of the past. As mentioned earlier
(see commentary on IX.1-2), for the Buddha, the knowledge of the past
(afitat?Jse fJaf!a) was
an important means of understanding the present. Yet he did
not encourage
speculation regarding the past as he feared that this would
eventually lead to all
sorts ofmecaphysical views. For this reason, he remained
aloof from specułacing
on the absołute origin of things. That aloofness is clearły
implied in his statement: "lnconceivable is the beginning of this
life-process. The prior end is not
evident," (Anamataggo 1yat?J ... 1af{lJiiro pubbakofi
na pannayati, S 2.178,
193; 3.144.151). There is here no denial of the prior end or
the first beginning
of things, but ooly of its cooceivability or perceptibility.
However, with the
problems that emerged duting the scholastic period In the
matter of expłaining
any form of origin (utpada), not merely of the first
beginning (puN1a kop),
some Buddhists wece compelled to deny outrigbt any form of
beginning.
Whilc the Sarvastivada conception of substance left no room
for origin and
cessation, the Sautrantikas had difficulties explaining the
origin and cessation
of momentary events. The difficulcies invołved in providing
an explanatioo
206ExAMlNATJON OF'fHE PRJO,R AND PoSIB.RJOR Ex~REMfflEĘ 207
seems co have led the metaphysicians to assume the
absence·ofa prior end,
rather thao of its iocooceivability. Henc;e the term
ana'l!J4tagga ("inconceivable
is the begioning'') came to be replaced by anavqragra
("without end and beginning"). As such, Nagarjuna proceeds with the
exa.mination of the view current
during his day, only to revert back to the Buddha's own
approach to this problem in the cod. Cancłraklr6. confining himself to .the
literary tradition of his
day and influenced by a transcendentalist approach in his
interpretation of
Nagarjuna, does not seem to recognize the above mentioned
change taking·
place in the Buddhist conception of the life-process (.raf!liiira).
2. Naivfigtaf'!I navara?!' y11Sya tasya madhya1?Z kuto
bhavet,
tasmfin
natropapadyante purvapara-.raha-kramaf!,
How could there be the middle of that which has neither a
beginning nor
a_
n end? Therefore, the methock of (distinguishing) the prior,
the
posterior or both together (i.e., the middle) are not
appropriate.
MKV(P) pp.220-221; MKV(V) p.96.
Startiog with the cunent assumption that there is neither a
prior nor a posterior
end, Nigarjuna raises the quescioo as to how , in the
absence of these two extremities, one can speak of a "middle'' (madhya).
He then proceeds to apply
this cciticism to the conception of the life-process
(.raf!J-.riira) as- understood and
interpreted by the metaphysicians.
3. Piiroa'l(I /iitir yadi bhavejjarf,i..maraTJam utt(JrM(l,
nir-jarii-marar{ii1atir bhavej;ayeta camrtafl.
lf birtł:t·were to come fiist and decay and death were to
follow, then birth
wouid be withoutdecay and death, and an immortalwouJd thus
emergc.
MKV(P) p .221; MKV(V) p.96.
The difficułties cre~ted by the Sa.cvastivadios and the
Sautrantikas in the mat-208 THE PHILOSOPHY OF tHE MIDDLE WAY
ter of explaining causa) continuity have beeo discussed at
length. The linelU'
view of the causal process broken up into discrete events,
one fołlowing the
ocher, left these evencs without any possible relations . lf
the same model were
to be used in explaining evencs such as birth (jalt)
decay-death (jafii-mara„a),
then the implication woułd be that birth has nothing to do
with decay-death.
There is no necessary connection between them. If this
argument were co be
carried to its condusioń, then it could be maintained thac
there is immoctałicy
(amrta), for there coll.łd be sornething chat continues
without decay.death.
Here, Nagarjuna is not insiscing that decay-death should be
inherent in birth.
Rather, he is exposing the difficulties confrooted by the
metaphysicians who
upheld a linear view of the causa) process.
4. Pa1cajJalir
yadi bhavejjara-mara1Jam adita/?,
ahetukam
aj'iitasya syiij jarfi-mtlraf!a'l'(Z katha'l'(Z.
lf birth were to be posterio.r and decay-death anterior,
chen the łacter
would be without a cause. ·How couJd there be decay-death of
one who is
not bom?
MKV(P) p.222; MKV(V) p.97.
Pla:cing birth after decay-death in this lineat view of the
lite-process, the logical
conclusion is inevitabłe that birth cannot relace itself to
anythiag prior and,
therefore, is uncaused. lf birth cannot be explained, .just
as much as decaydeath could not be accounted foJ (as stated at X.1.3), then we
-are left with the
tJOborn (ajiita). Nagarjuna considers it inappropriate to s_
peak of decay-aeath of
>,'
something/someone who is not born.
5. Na jarli-mara'f!enai11a1a1iś ca saha yujyate~
mtiyeta /aJamanaś ca sfiic cahetukatobhayol(.
Indeed, decay-death as concomitant ofbirth is not proper.
[In chat case,]
what is in the process of being boro will a1so be dying and
both would be
rendered causeless.
MKV(P) p.223; MKV(V) p.97.EXAMlNA'TlON Of THE PfllOR AND
POSTBRJOR EXTREMITIE5 209
As mentioned in commentary on Xl.4, one way of expłainłng
the problems
raised at XI.4-5 would be to assume that decay-death
(jar'?icmaraf!a) is ioherent
in birth (/iitz). This celationship of inherence would mean
chat decay-death
begios at the same time as bin:h, and as sueh ie would be
appropriate to say that
one who is being boro is at the same time dying. If s0;
neither one of them
could be the cause of the other. Being uncaused, their
occurrence wou!d be
rather spontaneous.
6. Yatra na prabhavanty ettl purvapara-saha-krarnal;,
pra:pancayanti fii?'(l jiili?'!l taj jara-rnarfJ'!4f!i ca
kif!i.
Wherever such methods of (discriminating) the pńor, the
posterior and
the $Unultaneous do not arise, why be obsessed by such birth
-and such
decay-death.
MKV(P) p.224; MKV(V) p.97.
The speculation that is questioned herc is specifically
related to the sort of succession discussed previously. lt is not every form of
reflection that is rejected.
Even if the verb prapańcayanti wece to mean
"conceptualizing", as
understood by a majority of modern uanslators of Buddhist
texts, in chis context, it does not mean the emptying of the miod of all
concepts of birth and
decay-death. lt is the particular form of conceptualization
mentioned in the
previous statements as well as the earłier verses that is co
be avoided.
7. Kiirya?'!l ca kartzf!a'!(Z caiva lak!Ya?'!l lak!af!am eva
ca,
vedana vedtzkai caiva santy artha ye ca kecana.
Effett and cause as well as chara~terized and
characteristic, together with
feeling and fe.eter or whatever fruits there are.
8. Pfirva na vidyate kofif? sa?'(ZSaraJya nil keva/af!J,
sarvefiim api bh'Qvari'ii'l'{J. purvli kofi na vidyate.210
THE PHILOSOPHY OP THE MIDDLE .W AY
the prior end of thcscis notevidcnt. Of the cntire
life-process as well as of
all existcnts, the prior end is not cvidcnt.
MKV(P) p.224; MKV(V) p.98.
It is not suprizing to sec Nagarjuni concluding his analysis
ofextremities (kop)
of events, whether they be of cause and effect, or the
charactcrized and the
char~cteristic, of experiences, of the life-process, and
even of all existents
(bhava), with the assercion that thcy arc not cvident (na
vidyate). He does not
mainwn chat these events arc without extremities.CHAPTER
TWELVE
Examination of Suffering
(Du~kha-pan-k~a)
1. S11ayaf{' krtaf{'para·krtaf'?ldv'iibhyiif!I- krtam
ahetukaf{',
duf?kham ity eka icchanti tac ca liiiryaf!t- na yujyate.
Some assume that suffering is sclf-c:aused, c:aused by
anothcr, c:aused by
both or without a c:ause. [Suffering as] such an dfect is
indeed not appropriate.
MKV(P) p.227; MKV(V} p .100.
The discussion of the life-ptoccss (saf!t-fiira) leads
Nagarjuna to an cxamination
of the problem of suffering (dul/kha). lt sccms that when
compiling this
chapter Nagarjuna bad a copy of the Buddha's discoutse to
Acda-Kassapa (S
2.18-22; T1a 12.20 [Tairho 2.86a]) in front of him.
The Buddha's discourse co Accla-Kassapa begins witb the fout
cheories of the
causacion of suffering referred to by Nagarjuna in almost
identical terms. The
onł y difference is with regard to the explanation of the
fourth. Where Nagarjuna has ahetukatrz, the Buddha's discourse refers to
adhiccasamuppannaf{' (sec
Xll.9 below). Anotber difference is tha't while the Buddha's
advises Kassapa
not to get involvcd in such speculacions. insisting,
"Do not [say] so," (mah'
evaf!t-), Nagarjuna maincains chat thesc cheories arc not
appropriace.
2. Svayarp krtaf'?I yadi bha11et prafiya na tato bhavet,
skandh'iin iman ami skandhal/ sat?Jbhavanti prafiya bi:
.
lf[suffering were to be] self-caused, thcn ie could not
occur dependentły .
lndced, depending upon these aggccgates, these otber
aggregates occur.
MKV(P) p.228; MKV(V) p. 100.
2 11212 THE PHILOS0PHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
The nocion ofself-causation of,suffering is funher
elaboraced by the Buddha as
the view expressed in the statement, "He acts and he
[himself] reaps the consequences," (so karoti sopafisaf!l-vediy4tt). The
Buddha's reason for not accepting
such a view is that.it leads to the belief in ecernalism
(sassataf!I- eltl'f!I paretz).
Nagarjuna certainly koew that the Buddha was utiliziog the cooceptioa
of
dependence (paficcasamuppada) co avoid aay mecaphysical
theory of eternalism. This was the basie theme, not oo1y in the cliscourse to
Kaccayana, but
also in the diścourśe to Aceła-Kassapa , where it is ooce
again presented as the
middle position berween the excremes of eternalism and
annihilatiooism (S
2.20}. Ic is, therefore, noc surprising to see
Nagarjunarejectingthe conception
ofself-causation ofsuffcring on the grounds thai in sucha
case suffering would
not be dependently arisen (na prafftya bht111et).
Furthermore, the eternalism that comes to be embodied in a
theory'of selfcausation ofsuffering pertains moce to the individual selfor soul
(atman), and
not the substance (wabliiiv4). Thcrcfore, Nagarjuna insists
that what is being
asserted as a self or soul is nothing other than the arising
ofa set of aggregates
dcpending upon (praffy4) another set of aggregates.
3. Yr1dy amtbhya ime 'nye syur ebhyo vam'i pare yadi,
bhavet para-krtan;. duf?khaf!I- parair ebhir ami krtal;.
lffrom these those that arc differeot were to come to be,
oriffrom those
these different [things] wece to come to be, then suffering
would be caused by another, for these are caused by those that are different.
MKV(P) p. 229; MKV(V) p.100.
Here we find a definition of "external causation"
(para-krta) . Nagarjuna has
already explained the relationship between setf-nature or
substance (svabliiiva)
and other-nature (parabhiiva)(see f.3). There he maintained
that without selfnarure there cannot be other.narure (avidyamiine svabhave
parabha110 na
vidyate). In the prcsent verse, Nigarjuna applies the same
principle to explain
"causation by another. '' Thus, we find him utilizing
the ablative case
(amTbhyal;, ebhyal;), exprcssive of"source" or
"origin," 'in order to explain the
arising of somcthiog different from within something chat
preceded. In ocher
.words, even though the effcct is different frorn the
.cause, it acises from the
cause; that is, exteroal causation is invariably related to
self-causation.EX/.MINATION OF SUFFERJNG 213
It is important to distinguish this statemeot from that
found at XJI. 2 which ,
instead of ~ing the ablative case, empl0.ys the accusative
(iman skandhan
pmliya) in order co highlight the principle of dependence.
Indeed, the very term
idapp11Ccayafii (idaf!Z·PraJyayaJ'ii} utilizcd by the Buddha
to cxprcss the principle of dependence is couchcd in the accusacive case
(idaf!Z). instead of the
ablative of soucce.
4. Sva-pudgala-krJa1{l dul;khaf!Z yadi dul;kllaf!Z punQr
11inii,
wa-pudgalal; sa katamo yena dul/kha?!f- svaya1{l krtaf!Z.
lfsuffering is oused by ones owo person, thcn that own
person can exist
without suffcring. Who is he by whom suffering is
self-ouscd?
MKV(P) p.230; MKV(V) p. 101 .
As shown before, the Buddhjst mecaphysicians who adopted a
thcory of
moments had difficuJty explaining personal continuity or
identity in a more
empirical way. They were confronted with the problem of
expłaining good and
bad. suffering and happiness as pan of the personał
continuity. Thus, the Sarvastivadins would maintain that suffcring. etc. arc
mere qualities (lak,a„a) thac
characterize the substance (dravya}, or they would, along
with the Sautrantikas,
maincain rhat qualities are appropriated or become pan of
the stream
(.rvasaf!Jfiina-patila, A.K 2.36; Akb p.62; Poussin,
L'Abhidharmakofa, vol. 1.
p. 179). Such a perspeccive inevicably leads to a
di.stinction between the person
or the stream of personał identity, on the one hand, and
qualities like suffering
on the other. What Nagarjuna is atcempting to do in the
present verse is to bring out the metaphysical implications of this cheory.
According to this theory,
suffering is something cxternaJ to the individual. It is an
enciry having its own
reality. lt is something caused by a person, as a carpenter
woułd produce a piece
of furniture. As such, Nagarjuna questions the very nature
of chat person who,
being independent of sufferińg, causes suffering on its owo.
5. Para-pudga/11/af!l duf?khaf!Z yadiyasmaipradiyate,
pare71a kr111a lad duf?khaf!Z sa duf?khena vinii ku1af?.214.
THE PHILOSOPHY 0F THE MIDPlB WĄY
lfsuffering were to be produced by one personand given over
to anothet,
that suffering is caused by the former. How can the latter
be ide~tified
without suffering?
MKV(P) p.231; MKV(V) p .lOL
Ifone were to accept the·separation ofsUfferiog from the
person who produces
ie (i.e. , the theory cticicized at XII.4), then it will
lead to d.ifficulties not only
for one who adopts self-causation of sufferiog (svayaf!t
Artaf!t du//khaf!t), but
ałso for one who upholds the opposire view , namely,
suffering is caused by
another
(para-krtaf!t t:/uf?khaf!t). The latter will have to maintain that
suffe.ting
is caused by one person and passed on to another. But that
other wouJd himself
be independen~ofsuffering, in the same way as the person who
caused it. The
question stili remains ·as to how that person can be
identified.
6.
Para-pudgalafaf!t dul;kha1'{1 yadi kal? para-pudgala/?.
11ina dul;khena
yaf? krt1iii parasmai prahit1oti tat.
If suffering is caused by anothec person, who is that other
person who,
himsclf without ruffecing, causes ie and bestows it on
another?
MKV(P) p.231; MKV(V} p .101.
This is similar to the arguments presented before. The sharp
dichotomy between the agent of suffering and su:ffecing itsełf proinpts ~agarjuna
to question the nature of that othet person (para-pudga/4) who is supposed to
be the
author of suffering and who passes it oo to an.other.
7. S11aya1!J. krtasyiipra.riddher du//kht111J para;krta??J
kuta!/,
przro hi duftkha??J yat kuryat tat ta.rya syat svayarri
krta??J.
With the non-establishment of self-causation, how can there
be suffering caósed'by another? For, indeed, ifanother wcre to cause that
sufferiog, 'in rclaclon to bim it would be self-ca~. ·ExAM1NATION OF SUPr'ER1NG
8. Na l'iival wakrtaf!l dul/khaf!I na hi lenai11a lat
krtaf!l,
paro nii1makr1af cet sy'iid dul/kha'(l para,.krtaf!l
kathaf!l.
So long as suffering 1s not self-caused, it is, indecd, not
caused by oncself.
lf the ocher were not to do it by himself, how could
suffcring be causcd
by anotbcr?
MKV(PJ p.232; MKV(V) pp. 101- 102.
21S
The i.mplications ofXII.3 discusscd carlicr arc stated oncc
moce cłcarly and explicitly in thcsc two vcrses. If some othcr pctson wece co
causc suffcring, theo
that suffering, in relation to that particular person, would
be sclf-caused. Tuus,
if one pcrspcctvic is not valid then the other too would be
invalidaccd. This, as
pointcd out earlicr, is the method adopted at 1.3 to reject
both self-nature
(svabh'iiva) and othcr-narure (parabh'iiva).
9. Syiid ubh'iibhy'iif!l krkl?P dul;khaf!l sjiid
ekaika-krtaf!l yadi,
pafiik'iir'iiwayaf!lk'iiraf!l dul/kham ahetukaf?I kutaf!.
If suffeńng wece to be caused by both, it would be caused by
cach individually. Whcnce can thece be suffering that is causcd neither by
another nor by oneself aild is without a cause?
MKV(P) p.233; MKV(V) p.102,
The tbird chcory of the causation of suffecing refcued to in
the discoursc co
Acela-l<2Ssapa is a combination of causation by oncself
and causatioo by
anochcr (sayaf!l katan ca paraf?j katafJ ca). This is
understood by Nagirjuna as
caus;1.tion by cach individual (ekaika-krtał'!J) . Howevet,
he has already rejected
both typcs of causation.
lf suffcting were not caused ·by onesclf or another, chen
accordiug to the
Buddha ie would "arise one top of another"
(adhiccasamuppanna). Such arising
is contrary to "arising by moviog towards or depending
upon another" (pa#cca.samuppanna). This implies arising wichout any causa!
connection. Hcocc ,
atihiccasamuppanna becomcs a synonym for ahe111ka
(cause-less). For Nagarjuna, chcre is no such uocaused suffcring.216 THE
PHtLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDl.l! WAY
lO. Na kevala?(t hi dul?khasya c~rvidya'f?J· na vidyate,
bahyiiriiim api bhavana'f?J caturvidya'f!Z 11a vidyate.
lt is not that thefoutfold theory applied exdusively to
suffering is not cvident. Tbe fouńold theo.ry pertaining to other existents too
is not evident.
MKV(P) p.233; M.KV(V) p.102.
Iha-<ła's explanation that these are the "four-fold
pombie views" (caturvidhyanj)
(p,88) seems to leave no toom for.a fifth view which both
the Buddha (in his
discourse to Kassapa) and Nagarjuoa (at XII.2) wece very
clearly and unequivocaUy upholding, namely. "dependent arising of
suffering." Hence his
condusion that these four possible views can.equally be
applied to demonstrate
the impossibility ofas.serting ele1nents of the external
world. On the concrary,
Nagarjuna (as well as the Buddha) were mercly criticizing
the futility of
adoptlog these f91J! .particular views io explaining
suffering as weU as other
elements in the woi'td of experience. Indeed, Nagarjuna was
dearly aware of
the facr that these four are not the ooJy views explicating
the causation of suffering. Hence his statement in the very fust verse in this
chapter, "Some assert"
(eke icchanti), wruch meaos that it is not evecyone that
assects such theories.CHAPTER
THIRTEEN
Examination of Action and the Agent
(Sa1'!Jskara-pctrt°k!a)
l. Tan mr1a mo1a-dharma yad bhagavin ity a'bhi1ata,
sart1e C11
mofa-dharmaf!al? sa'f!'Skiirif? lena le mrfi.
The Ble$ed One has said that whatever is of deccptive
naturc, that is
delusion. All things that arc of deccptive nature involve
dispositions.
Therefore, they are delusions.
MKV(P) p.237; MKV(V) p.104 .
A chapter dealing with disposicions (saf!Jskiira)
immediately following an
anaJysis of suffering (duf?kha) need not create any
confusion. Nor should the
fact the the title of this chapter is prescntcd in the
Tibetan translation as lattva,
instead of sa'f!'Jkra (sec Inada, p .91), lead to
difficultics in undcrstanding it.
There cannot beany doubt that the original chapter was named
"Examinatioo of the Dispositions." Even the most cursory glance at
the statcments of the
Buddha in the discourses would reveal the naked fad: that he
never looked
upon all phenomena (sabbe dhammi) as "suffering"
or "unsatisfactory" (dukkha). However, the classicaJ Hindu
philosophers who misquoted the Buddhist
textS, and some of the modern intccprerers who wece guided
by such philosophm,
have been cesponsible for ponraying Buddhism as a
pessim.istic religion by
misintecpreting the Buddha-word, especially the doctrine of
"suffering" {sec
Kałupahana , "The nocion ofsuffering in early
Budclliism, compared with som.e
reflectioos of early Wittgenstein," PEW 27
[1977]:423-431.)
The three prominent characteristics, impermanence (iznicca),
sufie.dog (dukkha), and oon-substantiaHty (tJnątta) have·bcen recklessJy lumped
together by
these interpreters and appłied to all phenoffi:ena when the
Bµddha in innumbcrablc instances (M 1.228; S 3.133; 4.401; A 1.286; Dhp
277-279; T1a
10.7 [Tat'sho2.66b-67aj; Tseng 23.4 [Tairho2.668c) Ch'ang
1.1[Tairho1.9b))
and in every statement he made in regard to these three
ch~racteriscics, always
'l.1„218 TH!l PHILOSOPHY Ol' THE MIDDLE WAY
distinguisbed between Jankhara and dhamma. These duce
characteristics a.re
always mentioned as follows:
1. "AU dispositions are impermaneot" (sabbe
sankliiira aniccii).
u. "All dispositions ase suffering" (sabbe
sankh'iira dukkh"ii) .
iii. "AU phenomena a.re oon-substantial" (sabbe
dhammii anat/ii).
ln the first place, the elear distinction made by the Buddha
becween
"dispositions" (sar.mkiira) and
"phenomena" (dharma) and, secondly, the fact
tbat he specifically referred to the former being subject to
suffering, could not
have escaped the penetracing and careful eye of Nagarjuna, a
philosopher
whose wcitings have .influenced some of the best brains in
the East throughout
the cenrur.ies. Ifall disposit.ions were coosideced by the
Buddha to be subject to
suffecing, then there is no reason to doubt as to w4y
Nagarjuoa sbouJd not concencrate bis attention on these
"dispositions" aftcr his examination of the prob·
Iem of suffering. Hence che reason for the present chapter.
Why the Tibet.an translators should considet this to be an
examination of
truth (tat111a) is also nor a myscery. They were simply
loolcing at the conclusion
of the chapter. Is there any connection between
"disposit:ions" and "truth"?
As pointed out easlier (V.8), the "appeasement of
dispositions"
(Ia'f!lskiiropafama) .is the ultimatc goal of Buddhism.
Excessive lust (raga) is
supposed to lead to the strengthening or solidificacion of
one's dispositions,
which in ruro conuibutes to grasping, no~ only for the
objects ofsense pleasure,
but also for ideas. The result would be the dogmacie grasping
on to absolute
truth or truths. The elimination oflust wouJd then mean the
elimination of the
dispositions too (Ia?!J.rkiira-R,aya) which would imply
virtual death and oo
motivatioo for any action or even to continue with one's
preseot life. Thus, the
Buddha hlmsclf was willing to characterize the death of a
"freed one"
(tathagata) as the "cessation of dispositions"
(sańkharakkaya) (Dhp 383)
leading to the cessation of the stream of bccoming
(bha11a-sota).
Howcver, while recognizing the waning of lust (rag4k.khaya)
as the way to
freedom , the Buddha did noc encomage the complcte
elimination of dispositions which would mean suicide. Ie seems that che Buddha.
did not recognize a
one-to-one relationship betweeo the waning of' lust and the
cessation of
dispositions. Hence his emphasis on the appeasement of
dispositioos while living and the cessacion of dispositions at the .time of
death.
The sucngtheoing of dispositions, as meotiooed earlier,
leads to dogmacie
bclicfs. These would pert:Un to personal immort.ality,
conceived io the form of
a belief in an eternal soul or self (atman) or of a
universal reality (loka,
brahf!14n). Any form of eternalism (fiiśvata) would be che
consequence ofsuch
strong dispositional tendendes. The opposice of ie would be
annihilacionismEXA.WNĄTION Ol' ACTION AND THE AGENT 219
(uccheda), and it is not difficult to understand why the
critics of the Buddha
would refer to him as an annihilationist(ucchedatiiidi)
upholding the annihila·
tion ofreą.llyttisdng sentient being (M 1.140). They were
p.robably referring to
the Buddha's advocacy of the "cessation of
dispositions" (sankhtirakkhaya) at
death.
Yet, for th~ living human being the Buddha was nor
prescribing the elimination of dispositions. Rather he adyocated their
appeasement. This view has
significant epistemoidgkal implications. A living human
beiog needs to act.
Action involves ·understanding. Conduct (caraf!a) is
preceded by knowledge
(vidya). 'One needsJcnowJedge ofoneself as well of the
external world. "Omniscience" or knowledge of ever:ything :was not
available to the Buddha. Hence,
neither the absolute· oripn of things nor the absolute end
of things were
discussed in Buddhism (see Cł)apter XI). Any theoty that
attempts to explain
su<ih origins and ends, whether it._pertains to an
eternal selfoi: soul (atman) or a
substance (sva!Jliiiva), was unacceptable to the Buddha.
Dispositions are invariably assodated with the knowledge
derived from the
senses. The innumerable data provided by the senses cannot
easily be handled
by the human being. As William James characterized sense
experience, it is a
"big, b!ooming, buzzing confusion" (Some Problems
ofPhilosophy p .32). Being unable to deal with such con.fusion, human beings
are compelled to be
selective. They pick out the things that interest them,
leaving out others. In
tbat process, they devełop dispositions and these
disposfrions in turn conttibutes their share in gainiog knowledge of the world.
As such, the world of
ordered experience is one that is construćted , made, put together
(sam
+vkr. "to do, to make"), by the human being. This
is the ptagmatic conception of truth (latt11a) that is prominent in the
Buddha's teaching. The appeasement ofdispositions thus contributcs to the
e!imination ofdogmatism, of
grasping after absolute truth or tru~hs. when all the time
human beings are
creating truths. If a person is not aware of the process by
which he construcrs
the truths about the world, be wiU not only be confused but
also disappointed.
Dispositioos can thus rum out to be a great source
ofconfounding and delusion
(mr!a), unless one understands their function in the
formiJlation of uuths (lattva). The tram,łators of Nagarjuna's text into
Tibetan probably pcrceived the
direction of the argument in this chaptet and na.med it
accordingły.
Note that the dduslon (mrrii) is produced, not by all the
phenomena (saf'tla-·
dharma) but ooly by the way in which these phenomena are put
togecher
(sa'J'!Mkarott) for purposes of understanding (see Websters'
Seventh Collegiate
Dictionary, 1965, p. 219 where delusion is defined as
"self-deception concerning facts or situations"). That putting
together is the function of dispositions
~S<l'f?tskara) . Hence, for Nilgarjuna, as it was fór the
Buddha, if anything is to
contribute toward delusion that would noc be all phenomena
(H1rve dhr1mi1iJ,),
ratbei: it would be all dispositions (sarve
sa'J'!Mliii.ra'1).220 THE Pl flLOSOPl-IY OF TifE MIODLE \'(/AY
2. Tan rnriii mO!a-dharma yad yadi ki1?J tatra mufytlte,
etat tukta?(l bhagavat'ii IUnyata-paridipaka'f!'J.
II, whatever that is ofdeceptive nature is delusion, what is
it about which
thece is dełusion ? That too, namely, that which illuminates
emptiness,
has been spoken of by the Blesscd One.
MKV(P) pp.238-239; MKV(V} p.104.
Ifdispositions cause delusjons, what is 1t about which there
arc delusions? The
answer would be: ''The world of e.xperience." The
Buddha bas spoken of thac
world coo. lt is the world that is non-substantial, is empty
of any permanent
and eternal entity. All delusioos arise rega.rding that
world which is
dependently arisen and non-substantial, but which is being
uoderstood as being either eternal or absolutely unreal.
3. Bhav'iin'iif!l nil/svabha11at11a1(l
anyatha-bhava-darśan'iif,
asvabh'iivo bhavo ,,,;Jsti bh'ii11'ii1iii'f!'l śiinyat'ii
yataf?.
Because of the perception of change, the absence of
self-nature of existents is [recognized]. Because of the emptiness of
existencs, there is no
existent without self-nature.
MKV(P) p.240; hfKV(V} p .105
Tbis is a elear statement that truth or reaJ.ity (lattva)
(there being no provisional
truth and ultim<tte reality) is neither substantial
exisrence nor nihjlistic nonexistence. The perception of change or variacion
(anya1habha11a) confirms the.
non-substantiaJity of phenomena (nzl1svabha11a). This is
anothcr way of expressing the idea embodied in the discourse to Kaccayana that
"ro hi.in who
percdvcs through right wisdom che cessation of the world as
it has come co be,
the notion of existence (atthit'ii) in the world does not
occur," (S 2. 17).
Cessacion (nirodha) or change (anyathabhava) does not imply
complete anruhilation. Hence Nagarjuna's view that there is no existent that is
without
substance (a-svabhava), thac is, soroething that goes into
complete oblivion
after Cl(tsting for a white (bhiitva prativigacchatt)
leaving no trace at aJI. TheEx.AMIN/\TJON OF ACTION AND 'Jlle. AGENT 22!
discourse to Kaccayana says that he who perceives arising
(iamudaya) does not
hold on to the non-existence of the world . In other words,
arising (Iamudaya or
.ramutpiida)
contradicts nihjlistic non-existence (na.rtifii, a-.r11abha11a). Nagarjuna
perccives this to be emptiness (!unyatfi).
This, then, is the way in which "dependent
arisiag" of phcnomena
(prafitya.ramutpada) becomes a syoooym for "empciness''
(śunyata) or "nonsubstantialicy" (nairatmya) whkh will be further
elaborated in Chapter X.XIV.
4. Ka.rya .ryiid anyatha-bhava/J .rvabhav/JŚ cen na vidyate,
ka.rya sy'iid anytha-bhavaf? .rvabhavo yadi vidyate.
Whose change would rhere be, if self-nature were not evident?
Aga&n,
whose change would there be, if self-nature wete evident.?
MKV(P) p.241; MKV(V) p. 105.
Nigarjuna is here conuasting identity and difference. If
tbiogs are compłetely
different from one another, then there is no reason to $peak
of the change of
things (a»yathabhava). If, on the contrary, the.re were to
be a substance
(.rvabhava) which is assumed to be permanent and eteroal, it
could not change.
5. Ta.ryaiva nanyatha-bhavo napy anyasyaiva yujyate,
yuvii na j'iryate ya.rmiidya.rmiij/i"!O na jiryate.
Neither change of something in irself nor of someth.ing
different is proper. The rea.son being that a youth does not age nor does an
aged person
age.
MKV(P) µ. 241; 11r1KV(V) p.106.
Nigarjuna cootioues to emphasize the view thac change
(anyathabhava) is inexplicable in the contexr of identity or diffecence.
"Of itself" (ta.rya eva) means
"of somethffig chat has substantial exiscence;"
"of anocher'' (anya.rya eva) implies "belonging co something
completeły differenc.'' As mentioned previously222 TuE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE
WAY
(VII.24), "decay" (jara) was not cejected by
Nagarjuna. In the pcesent context,
what he intends to convey is that such decay makes no sense
wheo applied to
explain a person who is metaphysically conceived eitheras
possessing an eternal
self or as being dlfferent fcom moment to moment.
6. Tasya cedanyatha-bha11af? kfTram eva bh1J1Jed dadhz~
kftrad anyasya k.asyacid dadhi-bhavo bhavi[Jati.
Ifchange were to be ofsometbing in itself, then milk
itselfwould be butter. Butter-ness would then be something other than milk.
MKV(P) p.242; MKV(V} p.106.
Ifchange were to be applied to somethingrecognized as
exisiting in itself, i.e.,
asubstance, thcn the conception ofchange would be negated.
Hece we find the
example of milk and butter (kflra-dadhi) utilized by the
Vitsłputriyas, along
with the metaphor of "fi.re and fuel" (Akb
pp.432-433), to illustrate the relationship becween the aggregates and the
self. If butter is considered to be
substantialły the same as milk, chen butter-ness wiU have to
belong to
something different from milk. Otherwise we will be left
with two differeot
substances having the same substantial constitution.
7. Yady a:śunyatrJ bhavet kt7?zcit syiic chunyam iti
ktf?tcana,
na kitrJCid asty a:śunyatrJ ca kutaft śunyatrJ bhavzjy(lti.
lf there were to be something non-empty, there wou1d chen be
something called empty. However, there .is nothing d~at is
non-empty.
How could there be something empty?
MKV(P) p.245; MKV(V) p. 107.
The conception of "empciness" or
"non-substantiality" is intended to eliminate
the belief in substance and attribute conceived in a
me_raphysical sense.
However, if"emptiness" itself wece to be used in
an attributive sense, that is as'
EXAMINATION OF ACTION AND THE AGENT 223
a characteristic of something substantial, theo
"emptiness" itself becomes
"something" (ki'f!Jca114). A substaocial thing is
a "non-empry-something''
(aśUnya'f!' ki'l?Zcit). Such a thing does not exist. lf so,
there cannot be something
called "empty'' (śUnya1!l iti kitp.cana) .
This is the clearest warning from Nigarjuna against moving'
towards the
mecaphysics of "empciness" (śUnyata du!i. sec
below).
8. ŚUnyalii sarva-dr1fina'f!J prokfii nil;saratJa'f!t
jinail;,
ye1af!Z tu śUnyafii-dr1fis tan asadhyan babha#re.
The Victorious Ones havc announced that entptiness is the
relinquishio.g
ofall vicws. Those who are possessed of the view of
emptiness are said to
be incorrigible.
MKV(P) p.247; MA"V(V) p.1084.
The inevitable conclusion to be derived from XIII.7 is that
the conception of
"emptiness" (śunyata) or
"non-substaotiality" (nairatmya), utilized by the
Buddha io order to free ooeself from all metaphysical views
(dN!t), can turo out
to be. an equa lły unsatisfactory view. ifits application is
to be carried beyood its
proper limits. lndeed, Nagarjuna perccives such activiry as
leading to worse
forms of dogmatism. ·CHAPTER
FOURTEEN
Examination of Assoc1atiQJJ
(Sa1!Jsarga-jJartkła)
1. DraftavJa'lt darśana1,!t dra[{i.i Jiff!Y efiini dviśo
dviiaf?,
sarvaśaś ca na sa1,!tSargam anyonyena vrajanty uta.
ihe object ofseeing, the seeing and the seer-these threc do
not function
in mutual association either in pairs or all together.
2. Evaf?'l ragaś ca rakla! ca rafljaniya~ ca drfyafii~.
traidhena śefiil{ klefi.iś ca śefany ayatanani ca.
Lust, the Iustful as weU as the object of łust shoułd be
scen in the same
way. The retrulining defilements as well ~s the remaining
spheres ofsense
should be seen in the tńadic mocie.
MKV(P) pp.250·251; MKV(V) p.110.
The pragmatic theory i;if truth, that is, truth as somethiog
put together according to human disp\lsitions (sa1,!tJkiira) depending upon
something experienced
(dhamta), is not a very palatable one, especialły for some
analytical philosopher
who wants to carry his analysis to the very extreme. In the
present treatment of
Nagarjuna's philosophy, it has been repeatedly pointed out
thar an extremist
analysis łeft the Buddhist metaphysician with absolutely
distioct entities. For
hlm (and this was the position accepted even by a
philosopher like Hume),
1'What is distinguishable ~ ałso separable." Of coutse,
these metaphysiciaos
would theo proceed to explą.in events in terms
of"composition," of putting different entities rogether
(sa1,!tSkaraf!a) accotc!ing to ooe's dispositions (.ra1,!tSkiira)
or, as Hume iosisted, in teons of one's imaginatioo.
However, they will have to
cairy the burderi of explaining how only cettain things can
be so put·together
and not aoytfllog a.od everytbing. For example, one can
insist thac it is possible
224ExAMtNATION oi: Assoc1ATION 225
to bring togecher events such as the eye, color, and visual
consciousness
togecher to produce the impression called "perception
of color." Yet, one can·
nor, either jo terms of dispositions or accordiog to any
imaginarion, put
together the eye, sound, and guscatory consciousne~ and
produce either a visual
im
pression or an auditory impression.
The onły way in which sucłi metaphysicians can explain any
possible association is by assuming a substanciał reł acion, an iohereot nature
a.moog chose
events thac are so associated . This is how che anaJysis of
events into abso łu tely
different entities contributed co the recognition of
mysterious subsrances. The
Sarvastivada notion of substance or self-nature
(111abliii11a) was, therefore, an
inevitable answer to such extremist analysis, in the same
way as Beruand
Russełl's theory of relations, defined as neither mental or
physical, was the
answer to the Humean analysis.
For such philosopbers, a pragmatic theory ofi truth, where
truth is defined as
something "made" (ItJf!likrta), becomes a problem
bccause their analysis has
deprived them of any empirical relations in terms of. which
ch ings can be
associaced . ft is, therefore, not surpózing to see
Nagarjuna raking up the quescion of associadon (saf!lsarga), in order to show
chat ie does not work in the
background of the metaphysicał assumpcions of certain ana
łysts.
Thus 1t becomes necessary co keep in mind chat Nagarjuna's
cricicism of
associacion is spcdfically rełarcd co che associacion of
eveots chat wece so
distinguished chat each was assumed co have its own nature
(111obha11a). He
begins this chapter with a reference to the various
categories he has alrcady examined at the very oucset in this secdoo of the
book, namely, seeing (darśana),
the objcct ofseciag (drQłfavya) and the seer (drflłtr)
(Chapter III). XIV.2 refers
to another set of categories examined in Chapter Vl. This
appłica tion is then
extended to aJJ occurreoces such as the defiłements and facu
lcics.
3. Anyenanyasya sarruargai? tac canyatvaf!l na vi~yate,
drtl!{avya-probhrliniif!J yan na IIJT(Mflrgflf!l vrajanty
ataJ?.
Association is of the mutually different [events). Such
difference is not
evident in the ol:ijecrs of seeing, etc. Therefore, they do
not function in
mutual association.
MKV(P) p.251; MKV(V) p.1 10,
Association, as mencioned above, becomes a philosophical p
roblem only wheo
distinctions or differences are rendered absolute.
Nagarjuna, basing himself on226 THE PHILOSOPHYOFTHE MIDDLE WAY
the principłe of "dependent arising," insisrs chat
such distinccions arc not
avai labłe among objcccs of seeing, etc. lf these are
discinguished or djffe1enciarcd in the way metaphysicians do, then they cannot
enjoy mutual harmony
or associaaon.
4. Na ca ke11alam anya111a1{Z drQ!fa11yader na 11irlya1e,
kasyacil kenacit iiirrlha'(J nanyatvam upapadyate.
lt is not only that the difference with regard to objects of
seeing, etc. is
not evident; the possibility of something possessing
difference jointly
with another is also not appropriate.
MKV(P) p.2)2 ; MKV(V) p. 110.
This is an interesting analysis of idenciry and difference.
The dilemma of
substance is broughc out clea.rly in this analysis. ln order
co relace things, differences need to be recognized. Once the differences a.re
retognized as being
absołute, each thing is assumed ro have ics owo nacure. Ir
becomes a subscaoce
different from any ocher substance. If cach subscance is
,differenc, ie cannot
have a substance that is shared by another. If it does.. the
difference breaks
down. Eithcr rhere is differcnce or therc is idencity.
5. Anyarlanyat prafityfinyan niinyadanyad rte 'nya1af?,
yat prafitya ca yal lasmiit Jad anyan nopaparlyate.
Diffcrcnt things are de~ndc.nt upon cliffcrent things.
Different things
arc not witbout different things. Because something depends
upon
someching, a different thing is not appropriate.
6. Yady anyad anyad anyasmat/ anyas11iiirl apy rte bha11et1
tad anyad anyad anyasmiirl rte nasti ca nasty ataf?.
If a thing is different from anothcr bccause it arises from
a different
thing, then it would ex.ist cven without that other thing.
Howevcr, thatEXAMINA110N OF A SSOCIATION
other thing does not exist without the other, and therefore,
it does not
exist.
7. N1inyasmin 11idyate 'nyat11am anany1111nit1 na vidyate,
a11idyamane C'iif!yatve nasty anyad va tad eva Va.
A diffcrence is not evident in rełation to a diffcrent
thing. Nor is it not
evident in a diffcrcnt thing. When diffcrence is not
evident, rhcrc is
neither diHercnce nor ide.ntity.
MKV(P) pp.252-255; MKV(V) pp. I I 1-112.
227
These verses seem to higblight the face that one cannot
speak ofdependence so
long as one .recognizes absolute difference among events.
They arc a reminder
of the detaiłed treatment of the relacion of contingence
(apek.fii) undenaken
previously in relation to the metaphor of "fire and
fuel" (Chapter A.1.
8. Na tena ltJJya I(Jf!MaTKO nanyen'iinya.sya yujyale,
saf?Zsr/yamiinaf!t saf!IS!l!af?Z saf?ZSr(ll{a ca na
11idyate.
The association of identical things or of diffcrent things
is not propcr.
Neithcr the associating nor the associated nor even the
agent of association is evident.
MKV(P) pp.255-256; MKV(V) pp. I 12-13.
ldencity and difference -assumed by the Buddhist
metaphysicians cannot solve
the problem of truth, especiaJly its pragmacic version. The
only solution
avai łable to them is a recognicion of the Buddha's
"omniscience" (saroajflatva),
which they unhesitatingly attributed to him, even without
atcempting to
define what "omnis'' (saroaf?Z) stood for in the
Buddhist context (see commentary on IX.3).CHAPTER
FlFTEEN
Examination of Self-narure
(Svabhava-parzk.ra)
l. Na Jt11!Jbhavaf? svabhavasya yuktal? pralyaya-hetubbif?,
hetu-pratyaya-sat!Jbhuta-1? .rvabhavaf? krtako bhavet.
The occurrence of self-oatnre through auscs and conditions
is not proper. Sclf-narure that has occurrcd as a rcsułt of causcs and
conditions
would be something that is made.
MKV(P) p.259; MKV(V) p.1 14.
Chaptcr XV is the condusioo to Part II of Nagarjuna's text.
The maio thrust of
Pan 11, as cxplaincd in the Intioduction, is in the
direccion of clarifyiag the
conccption of dharmas (in the plural), whcthcr they rcprescn
tcd ideas, things,
events, or phenomena. As was evident from an examioacioo of
the preceding
cwelve chapters, Nagarjuna's analysis ofdharmas was intended
to eliminate·thc
metaphysical ideas relating to idenrity and d.iffereoce
(ekiirtha-naniirlha). In
that proce~. he refuted the meraphysical notions of arisiog
and ceasing
(utpada-nt'rodha) , of cternalism and annihilationism
(Uiśvata-uccheda) and of
appearancc and dJsappearancc (agama-nirgama). These
metaphysical ootions
werc the rc:sult of assuming a substancc or sclf-narure
(svabhava) io
phcnomcna, an assumption that is muruaUy related by a
conception of absolute
"otherncss" (parabliiiva).
Self-narurc or substance (111abhava) thus being the major
~ue , it is natura!
for Nigarjuna to concludc this scction with an cxamination
of this particular
concepuon.
In rcfuting the conception of substance, Nigarjuoa relies
heavily upon the
Buddha's own conception of a "middle position,"
nameJy, "dependent
arising." Because he was herc concecned maioly with
refuting che mecaphysical
extremcs, Nigarjuna rcfers only to that section of his locus
classicus (i.e„ the
discurse to Kityayana) that deals with the ewo extremes of
exiscence (aslitva)
and non-existence (nastitva).
228EXAMINATION OP SEl.l'-NAlURE 229
In the very first verse, Nigarjuna statcs his owo pragmatic
view of truth as
something made (krtaka) depcncling upon causes and
conditions (he111-
pra1yaya-sarpbhutaf?). ·subscance or sclf-nature, if it wece
to ocist, couJd not
escape the principle of dependent arising
(pralilya.Iamutpada).
2. 'S11abha11af? krtako niima bhavi!Jalipunal/ kathaf!I,
akrtn'maf! svabhavo hi nirapelqaf? paratra ca.
Again, how could there be a self-natute th2t is made?
Indeed, an unmade self-
. .
nature is ałso non;.contingent upon another.
MKV(P) pp.260-262; MKV(V) pp.114-11 ~ -
.A.n artificial substance (krtakal? svabhival/) is not
possible, for by defio.ition a
subscance is etcrnal and therefore not subject to acising
and ceasing. Anyching
that is subjcct to arising and ccasing cannot be a substance
and, bence, concrary
to dependent arising. lt is simply non-contingent
(nirapelqaf?).
3. Kutafl s11abha11t1.Iyabha11e para-bhavo bhav#yatt;
svabhaval? para-bha11asya para-bhavo hi kathyate.
In the absence ofself-nature, whence can there be
other-nature? For, selfnaturc of othcr-nature is called other-nature.
MKV(P) pp.265-266; MKV(v,I p. 116.
This represeots a rcpetition of che argument used by
Nigarjuna at I. 3 and
XIV.4 to indicate the rclativity ofself-nature lµld
other-natu!C. lf one is not acceptable, the other too is not ~dmissible.
4. S1111bh'ii11a-para-bha11abhya1n rte bh'iivafl kutal?
punaf?,
svabhave para-bhave vii sali bhii110 hisidhyati.230 THE
PHtLOSOPHY OF Tl-lE MIDDLE WAY
Without sełf-nature and other-nature, whence can therc be an
existent?
For, tbe existent is established only when there is
self-nature or other·
nature.
MKf/(P) p.266; M.k'V(V) p.ll6.
This probably could serve as evidence against the belief
that Nagatjuna
recognized an ultimate reality beyond bothself-nature and
other-nature. In the
case of the Yatslputriyas, the "ultimatdy real"
emerges on the basis of an assertion of both idencity and difference, (see
commentary on X.1, "Fire cannot be
designated as something differenc from the fuel, nor as
something idencical.")
. The Japanese Buddhist scholar Y. Ueda perceives a unique
logical principle
adopted in Madhyamika logic detived from the metaphor of
"fire and fuel."
According to rum, ''There are inherent conditions in each
sucb tbat their
ultimate rdatonship into a whole or unity entails a mutual
dcnial of cach
other,'' (see Ioada, p.80, emphasis added). However,
Nagarjuna is here raising the question; "Distinct from self-nature and
other-nature, whence can
there be an existent?"
Thus, the eight negations are not intended to prove or
establish the nature of
reali.ty, as it is ońen and loudly asserted. They are
primarily and solely intended
to eliminate metaphysical notions, not co characterize
either an ultimate reali.ty
or dependent arising. Dependent arising is a totally
differnt way of expressing
the truth or reality.
In the second statement above, Nagarjuna maintains that
svtJbhav4 and
parabha11a are both dependen.t upon bhava. They represent a
further bifurcation of bhava.
5. Bhavasya ced aprastddhir abhavo naiva sidhyatz;
bhavtJSya hy anyatha-bh411am abhavaf!l bruvate janiih.
When the existent is not established, the non-existent is
also not
established. It is, indeed, the change of the existent that
people generally
call the non-existent.
lef.KV(P) p.267; MKV(f1p. ll7 .
Whlle svabhava ' nd parabhiiva reprcsent a bifurcation of
bhiiila, the łatter isEXAMINATION OP SELF-NATURE 231
itself dependent upon abha11a. Ordinarily peoplc speak of
abliii11a as change in
bhava. The bha11a - abhava, chough moce comprehensive than
che wabhava
-parabha11a dichotomy, carries the same implications as the
lacter. Boch involve
the metaphysical nocions of idencity and di.fference.
Neither the Buddha's conceptioos of "dependent
arising" (paf1cca.ramuppada) and "non-substantiality" (anatta)
nor Nagarjuna's views on dependence
and emptiness (śunyatii) should be understood as involving
or crearing the
metaphysical notions of identity and di.fference. In face,
the intcrpretation of
fUnyafii by some scholars as an "ultimate reality'' has
brought about an immediate respoose from others who characterize it as
"oothingness." The
dichotomy thac ordinary people assume is immediately fuought
into play herc.
It was chis incorrigibilicy (aiiidhya) that Nagarjuoa was
referring to at Xlll.8.
Hence. Nagarjuna's declaration that follows.
6. S11abhava1(' para-bhava?[I ca bha11t11(' cabhiivam eva
ca,
ye pafyanti na
paśyanli te tattvarri Buddha-fasane.
Those who pcrceive self-natutt as well as other-nature,
existence as well as
non-existence, they do not perceive the tmth embodied in the
Buddha's
message.
MKV(P) p .267; MKV(V) p.117.
lt is not merely self-oature and other-nature that arc
rejected, but also existence
and oon-existence. The former pair covers a limited range
ofexplanation, compared to the moce comprehensive notioos of ex:istence and
non-cxistence.
An empirical definition of existence, as presented by the
Buddha, would
mean some thing, some event, some phenomenon available to
the sbc senses (see
S 4.15, Sabba-sulla). Such a phenomenoo is assumed to have
come to be oo
che basis of cooditioos (pa.f1ccast1muppanna), to remain for
a while showing
signs, ac the same time, of decay (!hita.rsa afJflathatta),
and then cease to exist
(nirodha, 11yaya)1once agaio depeodiog upon conditioos. So
thal even ordioary
unenlighcened people would say: "Change of what is
existent is non:exiscence"
(bhiivasya hy anyathabhavam abha11a1(' bruvate janiil/,
XV.5).
However, che metaphysicians can take over from this ordinary
man's
language, especially with its use of the geoecive or
possessive case (bhavasya).
He will assume that change is something possessed by the
existenc (bhiiva)
which is always the same. Y et he cannot say the same about
non-existence232 THE PHLLOSOPHY OFTHEMIDDLE WAY
(abhava). The metaphysicians part company here. one
dogmaticaUy holding oo
to a theory of eternal existence (śaśvatq), the other
advocating absolute nonex.istence, which is annihilationism (uccheda).
Another metaphysician who is interested in explainiog the
empirically fclt
"selfhood" and "others" wiłl attempt to
bifurcate existence (bhava) as selfnature (svabhava) and otber-nanue
(parabhava). Wheo applyiog this latter
dicbotomy to the explanation ofcausality, the metaphysician
once again brl.ngs
the duality of existence and non-ex.istence into play.
Such metaphysics has no place whatsoever in the Buddha's
explanation ofexistence and oon-existeoce. Hence Nigarjuna's statement that
those who adhere
to these notions do not understand the truth or reality
expressed in the
Buddha's message.
7. Katyayanavatiiide ca.stili n'iisliti cobhayaf?J.,
prati[iddhaf?J. bhagavat7i bliiiv'iibliiiva-vibhavina.
In the admonition to Katyayana, the two thcories Jimplying]
1exists' and
'does not exist' have been refuted by.the Blessed One who
.is adept in existence as well as in non-existence.
MKV(P) p .269; MKV(V,) p. 117.
This, as mencioned in the Iouoduction, is the single most
imporrant piece of
evidence avaiłable in the work of Nigarjuna, which ca!1
rdate him to the Buddha as presented in the Pali Nikayas and the Ch.inese
Agamas. Inada's note on
th.is versi:: is too brief and vague: "The Saoskrit
Katyayaoavavada, either refers
to the sutra or the iosttuctions given to Katyayama [sic.)
by the Buddha,"
(p.99).:Tfiis statement of Nagarjuna deserves much moce
attention than has
ever beeo accorded to it.
The main theme of the diścourse is to expose thć
untenability of che two
metaphysical views .of existence (astitva) and oon-existence
(ntistitva). This is
clone b.y appealing to the empiticaJ notions of arising
(utpiida) and ceasing
(nirodha). With the fifteeo chapters (induding the present).
Nigarjuna has
presented an outstanding explaoation of how the empirical
conceptions ofarising and ceasing, of irnpermanence and change;, can proficably
be used to expose the futility of metaphysics. Hence, he is satisfied with
meręly referring to
that porrion of the "Discourse to Katyayana" whi~h
deals wirh the rejection ofEJV.MlNATION OF SELP-NATIJRE 233
the two metaphysicaJ extremcs. A discussion of the remaining
ideas expressed
by the Buddha in this discourse, especiałly the positive
description of the
human personalicy as well as its experiences, is reserved
for a later occasion,
8. Yady as1tt1111f!J pr11kr1ya syiin na bh1111ed asya
nastilii,
prakrter anyatha-bha110 na hijatupapadyate.
Ifexistcnce wece to be in terms ofprimal natuce, then
therewouJd not be
its non-existence. A change of peimal nature is certainly
not appropriate.
MKV(P) p.271 ; JHKJ/(V) pp.118-1 19.
This and the oext three verses seem to constitute a digesr
of the detailed and
meticulous analysis of the two extreme views presented by
Nagarjuna so far.
lf existence is·understood in the sense of primal narure
(pr11kr11), in the way
the Sańkhya school clid, for. in fut, the Sańkhya used the
term 111abhii11a to refer
ro che primal oarure, then there cannot be its
ooo-cxistcnce. The rea.son is that
change and primal nature or substance arc incompacible.
9. Pf'flkrtau kasya casatyam anjathat11a1'{1 bha11ifya1i,
prakrtau kasya ca salyam anyatha111a1!J bha11i;yati.
When pei.mal nature is non-existent, whose change would
there be?
When prima! nature is existent, whose change would there be?
MKV(P) p.271·272; MKV(V) p.119.
Not only the existence of primal nature, but also its
non-existence is iocompatible with change. Herc primal nature is understood as
the substance and change
as the attribute. If the substance is nor available, the
attributes cannot be applied to it. If the substance is present, the attributes
become superficial. In
brief, the substantialist enterprise coosists of reconciling
subscance and attribute aftcr creating a sharp and irreconciliable discinction
between them (see
Chapter V).234 TuB PHILOSOPHY Ol' 1'HE MLDPLE WAY
The above explanatioi1 would eliminace the need for assuming
that the first
line of the verse represents a question raised by an
opponent to which Nagarjuna gives his own reply in the second (see Inada p.99,
who follows
CandrakTrti's interpreracion of this verse.)
10. Asliti Saivata-graho n1islity uccheda-darfanat?J,
tasmiid astitva-nastitve naśiiyeta vicak!at!tll/.
"Exists' implics grasping after eternalism. "Docs
not exist" implics the
philosophy ofannihilation. Therefore, a discerning person shouJd
not rely upon either existence or non-existence.
11. Asti yadd hi s11abha11ena na tan niistftfiiśvatat?J,
nasfidiintm abhut purva11z ity ucchedal; prasajyate.
"Whatever that exists in terms of self-nature, chat is
not non-existent''
implies eternalism. "lt does not ex:ist now, but
existed before" implies annihilation.
MKV(P) pp.272·273; MKV(V) p.119.
These theories of existence and non-existence are not simple
and harmless ones.
They contribuce to unforrunate consequeaces. The theory of
existence kads to
the dogmacie grasping on to the belief in eternalism. The
conception-of nonexistence leads to an equally dangerous view of annihilation,
both o~which , as
will be pointed out later, are damaging to the moral life.
Hence, a wise man
would not associate himself with such extreme views.
This seems to be a most appropriate condusion to an anaJysis
chat was intended to establish che non-substantialicy of all phcnomcna
(dharmanairatmya). Nagarjuna did not allow any toom for the reificarion of any
one
single phenomenon that was refcrred to as being pan of human
experience.CHAPTER
SIXTEEN
Examination of Bondage and Release
(Bandhana-mok.fa-partk~a)
1. Sa1p.skiiraf?
sa'l!'saranti cen na nityal; sa1!'Jaranli te,
sa'l!'saranti ca ti4nityal/ sattve 'py e1a sam.aft kramaf?.
If it is assumed that dispositions transmigrate, they would
not
transmigrate as permanent entities. Neither do they
transmigrate as impermanent entities. This method (of analysis) is applicable
even in the
case of a sentient being.
MKV(P) p.280; MKV(V) p .123.
Part Thrce, according to our analysis, consists ofChapter
XVI-:XXVI; and is different from Part Two io its treatment of the subject
matter, even though the
subject matter itself appears to be similar in them. While
Part Two was concerned with the analysis of the elements of existence (dharma)
showing how
they are lacking in any substance (dharma-11airalmya) and
how tbey are
dependently arisen (parfitya.ram11tpanna), Part Three is
concerned more with
the explanacion of the human personality (pudgala) without
falling into
meraphysical uaps. The human persooality, both in bondage
and in freedom ,
is analysed here. The problems of "self' (atman),
questioos regarding morał
responsibility and its associated concepts of time and
fruitioning, are discussed
fust. Movfr1g therefrom, Nagarjuna takes up the problem of
the person who
has anained freedom, the question of rruths, of freedom
itself, rrying to deal
ooce again with the metaphysicał iotetpretations, until be
reaches Chapter XXVI when he presencs the most positive explanation of that
human personal·ity.
The present chapter beings with one of the most popularly
held misconceptions about the Buddha's teachlogs pertaioing to rebinh
(punabbhava). Even
duriog the Buddha's day, when he spoke about rebirth being
causally conditioned or ' 'depeodentły acisen" (patźci;asamuppanna), and
enumerated several
conditions that would contribute co ie (M 1.265), one of his
disciples picked out
one among these conditions, namely, consciousoess
(11ifJffiif!a), maintaining
235236 T HE PHlLOSOPHY OF THE MI DDLE WAY
that it is "This very same coosciousness that
transmigcates, not aoother" (:dam
eva viflłfiifla?(I sandhavatt.' Ill1(1Saratt.' anaflfla?(I,
M 1.256; Chung 54.2 [Tairho
1.766c)). There certainly were many others, including some
of his disciples,
who cootinued to uphold such views throughout che centuries.
The widespread
p.tevalence of this view seems to indicate the adamant way
in which people
believed that for survival to ta.kc place there must be a
permanent and eternal
subscance:
The Buddha's answer co rhese believers in a permanent and
eternal selfor entity is that any factor that conrributes to human survival,
whether ie is consciousoess (vififiafła) or disposition (sankhara), or action
(kamma) or even
graspiog (upadiina), aJl these arc dcpendencly arisen. For
the Buddha, contłnuity can be explained in a more empiricaJ way by following
the principle of
dependence of impermanenc faccors of cxistence, where on
leaves an impression on another, thus eliminating the need for assuming a
permaoent entity.
Nigarjuna is herc referdng to rwo extremes, i.e., permanence
(nitya) and
impermanence (anitya) , this latter being the momentary
destruction (k!af!abhańga) advocated by the Buddhist metaphysicians. The.
former cepresents the
Sarvastivada point of view; the lacter, the Sautrantika.
If the dispositions (Ia?(lskiira) arc presenred as being
either pcrmanent or impermanent whcn thcy rransmigrate, and if there is no
mention of causaJ conditioning of rhese dispositions as well as the ocher
factocs, then the theories of
eternalism and annihilatiooism are inevitable. Furthermore,
such excreme condusions arc especiaJly unavoidable when one factor or eotity is
singled out and
shown to be the factor lnvolved in transmigratjon.
2. Pudgalaf?
sa1(1Jaranti cel skandhayalanadhaltJ!U,
paflcadha
mrgyama,,.o 'sau nasti kal? sa1(1Sari/yati.
lt may be assumcd tbat a person transmigrntes. Yet, such a
person,
sought for i.o the fivefold way in the aggrcgates, spheres
(of sense) and
elements, does not cx.ist. Who chen will transmigrate?
MKV(P) p.284; MKV(fl? p„124.
lt is interesting to note that in the previous statement
Nigarjuna rejects only
the view that dispositions cransmigrate. He did noc deny the
disposicions
them$elves. However, in the present verse Nagarjuna
maintains chat if a
transmigrating "person" (pudgaia) is sought for
(mrgya11tano) in the ag-EXAMINATION OF BoNDAGE ANO RELEASE 237
gregatcs, faculties, and elements (as Nagatjuoa tried to do
in the last fifteen
chapters) one does not discovcr him. The "person"
referrcd to bcre is no ordjnary person. This person shouJd possess the same
characteristic which, according to the previous verse, made it impossible for
the "dispositions" to
tranSmigcate, namcly, permanence.
!nada seems to miss the meaning of the term mrgyt1m'ii11a in
his translacioo
of this verse.
3. Upadiinad up'iidiinaf!J sa'(lsaran 11ibha110 bha11et,
11ibha11aś c'iinupadiinal/ kal? sa ki'(l Itlf!Jiari;yali.
Moving from one form of grasping to anotber, t~ere would be
othcrbecoming. Who is this person who bas ceased to be and is [therefore]
non-grasping? Wherein does he transmigrate?
MKV(P) p.284; M.KV(V) p. 124.
I
Uoderstanding the causa! process in a lioear way one runs
into difficulties in expłaining "grasping" (upadiina) as a reason,
not only foc transmigration but also
for conceptualizing a person. White grasping was considered
a.o impoctant
cause for the unhappiness and suffering (dukkha), as aJso
the rebirtb of a
human bcing, "non-grasping" (anupadiina) was. a
conditioo for happiness
(sukha) in this life and for not bcing reborn in a future
life. In adclition, eveo
the vcry notion o'f a substantial "self' (alta) is
supposed to be the result of
grasping on to the five aggregates (upadiinakkhandha).
However, if graspiog is singled out and explained in a
lioear way. then moviog from one moment of grasping to another, one will be
faced with otherbecoming (11ibha11a). To explain this broken or inrerrupted
series of graspings,
one. needs to assume that there is something to be grasped
so that grasping can
continue. The: aggregates do not continuously provide a
foundation for grasping. They arise and cease. With such arising and ceasing,
grasping itself would
be ioter.rupted. This me.ans chat grasping that has come to
be non-existent
(11ibha11a) would also be noo-grasping (anupadiina). If so,
where is this socalłed permanent cnticy and where does he transmigrate?
4. Saf'!J.Ikaiiif{iirp na n_iro'ii'łarrt katha?!Jci'd
upaparlyrrle,
sa1t11a.ryapi na niroar;a'!t katharp.cid upap11dyate.238 THE
PH!LOSOPl-IY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
The cessation of dispositions is somehow not appropriate.
The cessation
even of a scntient being is also not appropńate in any way.
MKV(P} p .288; MKV(V) p.126.
The Buddha left unanswered the quescion regarding the narure
of a "freed person" (tath'iigata) aftec death (param1nara11a).
Nagarjuna wiU return to this
question in his finał chapter, "The Examination of
Views" (Dr1fi-pank1a). In
the present context, Nagarjuna is concecned mostly with the
living person. The
previous verses referred to the mecaphysical views regarding
a living person in
boodage. The present verse is, thercfore, devoted to an
exarninatioo of the
mecaphysicaJ view percaining to a living person who has
attained freedom.
Speakiog of chat fre.edom, Nagarjuna doc:s not wanc co
assume chat it is the
cessacion of dispositions, QI of a "person." He
was probably aware that che Buddha spoke of the pacification of disposicions
(sańkhara-upasama) in relation to
a living person who has attained freedorn. He was also aware
that the Buddha
did not advocate the annihilation of a sentient being
(1att11a, see commentary
of Xlll. l ). Heoce his present st~tement.
S. Na badhyanle na mucyanta udaya-vyaya-dharmit!af?,
.Iaf!IJliiiral? purvavat satto badhyate na na 1nucyate.
Dispositions that are of the nature of upńsing and ceasing
are neither
bound nor rcleased. A sentient being, like the foregoing, is
neither
bound nor released.
MKV(P) p.290: MKV(V) p .127.
According co the substanciałisc way of thinking , an erernaJ
selfor soul (at1na11)
is in bondage because it is bound co various ephimera1
factors such as che
psycho-physical personalicy (see. Bhaga11adgll'ii, Chapter
Xlll). Such a self has to
break away from i-ts bondage in order to be free. Having
rejected a pcrmancnr
cntity Jike the self, if the Buddhisrs were to consider the
disposicions as the condition for bondage, such disposidons, being of the
nature of arising and ceasing, could neither be bound nor freed . In ocher
words. one canoot look at rhe
dispositions through the eyes of the substantialist. The
same t.-an be said of a
sentient bcing (sanva).EXAMINATION Ol' BONDAGE AND RELEASF.
6. Bandhanaf?l cod uptirliinaf?l soptirliino na badhyate,
b11dhy11te n?inuparliinai/ kim avastho 'tha badhyate.
lfgrasping were to be considered a bo.ndage, one who is with
gcasping is
not being bound. Neither is one without gcasping being
bound. A person in which state is then bou.nd?
MKV(P) 290; MKV(!'? p.127 .
239
The substance/anribute distinccion that emergcs from the
statement such as
"one who is with grasping" (sa-uptiaano) militatćs
against saying that he is being bound (b11t/hy11te). In this sense, the
attribute is ałre.ady implicit in the
substance and there is no point in piling,up another
identical attribute on it. If
the substa0ce is without attribute (as in the case of
an-upadiina), then there
.seems to be no way in which one can atuibute an attribute
to it. They could
always remain independent. These difficulties relating to
identi.ty and difference give rise to the questipn regarding the status of the
person who is being
.. ~
bound. ·
7, Badhn'iylid bandhanaf?l kamaf?l bandhy'iit purvaf!J
bhavedyadi,
na casti tal fe.fa'n uklaf!J g11v1yamana-gatiigalail/.
Ifit is assumed that bondage existsprior to the binding
ofthat which is co
be bouod, that does not exist. The rest has been explained
by [the
ąnalysis of] present moviog, the moved and the not moved.
MKV(P) pp.291-292; MKV(V) pp 127-1?8.
lf, in answer to the question raised in the previow verse,
it is said that bondage
exists prior to someone being bound, such bondage, according
to Nagarjuna,
does not exist. The analysis in Chapter·II as well as in
Chapter X can be utilized
hete to refute the implications of a substantialist view. of
bondage. ·
8. Baddho na tntJcyate fiivad abaddho 114i11a mucyate,
s:f?itii'!l badtilhe mucyam?ine yugapad-bandha-mok/ane.240
'fHE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MJDDl..E W AY
One who is bound is not rcleased. nor is one who is o~t
bound freed.
When there is rcleasing of one who is bound, then thcrc would
be
simultaneous occurrcnce of bond.age and release.
M.KV(P) p.29); MKV(V) p.128.
One who is substantially bound (baadha), i.e.. one who bas
the sełf-nature
(s11abhiiJ1a) of bondagc, cannot be frced. Similarly, it is
meaningless to spcak of
somconc who is absołutely free (a-baddha). i.c.• whose
sełf-naturc is frccdom,
as one beiag frccd. Ifone wcrc to speak of someoae who is
idready bound and is
beiag freed, thca bondage and freedom would be simułtancous.
9„ Nirvasy'iimy 11nupadiino nir:iii1!1Zf(I me bh1111i./yati,
itiyefiif(J grahar tefiim upadiina-11111ha-grahaf?.
"Noi;i-graspiag, I sball be free. Freedom will then be
mine." For whomsocver tbere is grasping in tbis manner, that will be a
gigantic grasping.
MKV(P) p.295; MKV(V) p.129.
Nagarjuna is herc prescnting a fundamcntal idea expressed in
the early
dtscounes (sec M 1.145-151, Ratha11inl~sutta) as well as in
the Praj1r\iparamita literaturc, espedally the Vajra&chediliii. It is the
idea that one
Caruiot be frced and still eling to frecdom, let along braggiog
about it.
Howcvcr, one nced not construe µie Buddha's statcment at M
1.171
1(Anyapariyesana-iutta) as an instance of such bragging.
That statemcnt was
Jl)a°dc by the Buddha in responsc to a question raiscd by
Upaka at a time whco
.the only frced one in the world was the Buddha hirruelf. He
was simply dcscrib-
/ing to Upaka th~ abscnce ofany one who bad attained freedom
, in the sense in
which the Buddha understood the conccption of freedom.
Whether the Buddha would make such a statcment subsequcnt to the prcacbing of
the first scrJ mon and the attainmcnr of colightcnment and freedom by his fll~t
fivc
disciplcs is extremdy doubtful. ·ExAMINATION Of BONDAGE
ANO.R!rLEASE
10. N11 niNii'!11-s11miiropo 1111
sllf!ISt1rtip/Jkq11111111f!I,
yatr11 kas tatra Sllf[ISiiro niwii1111f!1 kif?Z
11ikalpy11te.
Wheccin there is neither the attribution of frecdom nor the
elimination
of the life..process, what is it that is being discriminated
as life-process or
as frcedom?
MKV(P) p.299; MKV(V) p.130.
241
This concluding verse provides a beautiful summary of the
metapbysical views
rełating to a life of bondage (st11[1Sir11) and frccdom
(ninliif!t1) and can servc as a
key to unlocking the mystcries sucrounding the chaptcrs
to.come. The constant
debates among modern scholars as to the implkacions
ofNigatjuna's famous
chapter on Niroa11a (XXV,) tan easily be eliminatcd if we
arc to keep in mind
the nature of the theories pertaining to bondage and freedom
that Nagarjuna
h:od to deal with. ·
Presented in the substantialist moułd, freedom becomes an
attcibution
(samiiropa). while the life-process with its suffering
requires elimination
(apak4r!tJ'!ll)_, No such frcedo~ or life proccss is
accepted by Nagarjuna. Such a
description was too metaphysical for bim.
Attribution and elimination imply the existence of a neutral
substance to
which freedom can be attt:ibuted or suung on to, while
bondage in the form of
łife-process can be wrestled away from . If no neutral
substance is recognized,
there couJd be two ocher ways of explaining freedom and
bondage. First, it is
possible to say tbat the substance is inherentły free and
that it is held in bondage by adventitious elements. Tuus, the Upani~adic or
the Brahmaoical notion
of "self' which is pure and luminous is understood as
something kept in bondage to the ·psycbophysical personality, like a sword kept
in its sheath. The
originally pure mind (prakrti-pra6hiiwfll'a-~itta) ofthe
Buddhist metaphysician
(sec Lank.avatiira, ed. Nanjio, 1956, p.358) resembles the
Upan4aclic and
Brahmanical vie.ws of the ''self." Secondly, if such an
originaUy pure encity is
not acceptablt:, then it is possi,ble to argue that wbat is
called the life-process
(sa?!Mara) is completely annihilated and a completely new
process offreedom is
initiated. The former has nQthing to do with the latter.
lndeed, one cannot ig·
nore the solutions offcred by the·Buddhist me.taphysidans
when they carne to
analyse che personal stream of becoming (bhava-sota) into
discrete entities. Thę
concepts of ''atcainment'' (praptt) and "non-attainment"
(a-piiiptt) providcd·a242 THE PHJLOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE WAY
solution that is almost identical with those meotioned
above. Niroa,,_a thus
becomes a prapti that fall into the stream
(111a-Iaf!'t(ina-patita) and at that
point sa'!'Jara becomes at;i a-prap1i.
As pointed out in the lntroduction, the Buddha's conceptions
of bondage
and freedom (and this woułd also appJy to Nagarjuoa's views)
have nothing to
do with aoy one of the alternacive explanations mentioned
above.CHAP'J'ER
SEVENTEEN
Examination of the Fruit of Action
(Karma-phala-partk!ti)
1. Atma-sflr(tyamakartt cetafl paranugrahakaf?l cayat,
maitrartt sa dht1rmaf! lad bl/af?l phalsya pretyt1 ceha ca.
Self-resti:aint as well as benefitting othets-this is the
friendly way and it
constitutes the secd that bears fruit here as well as in the
next life.
MKV(P) p.303; MKV(V) p.132.
The present chapter, unlike Chapter VIII , deals with the
problem of morał
responsibility. It is an attempt to explain the
"fruits" (phala) reaped as a result
of one's actions (karma). The docuine of the fruits of
action or morał responsibilicy is pivotal to any explanation of human life,
whether it is in bondage or
in freedom. However, in the present chapter, the idea of the
accumulation of
merit and demerit (pu'!ya-papa) (for future benefit) is
examined at length,
primarily because this parcicular idea is mostly associated
with the Jife-process
(saf?Jsara) in .bondage. The Buddha insisted that such
accumulatioo of merit
and demerit is abandoned (prahlf!a) by a person who is
enjoying freedom (nirvaf!a), even though he does not transcend morals or is not
unconcerned with
questions relating to mota! responsibility.
Inada assumes that verses 1-19 represent the popular
explanation of karma.
This is questionable. Io fact, the popular, and therefore, a
mistaken view of
karma is presented only in verses 6-12. Verse 13, as will be
pointed out, refers
to a more sophisticated theocy of moral responsibility held
by the Buddha and
his disciples.
The present verse deals with two importaot
virtues-self-restraint and
benevolence-and these constitute the friendly way (maitraf?1
dharmafl) which
serves as the seed that fruitions herc as well as in the
furure. !nada reads three
virtues-self-restraint, kindness towards others and benevolence.
On the conuary, m(litrarrt seems co quality dharma, and Kumaraj1va undetstood
it in this
latter sense.
243244 ThB PHILOSOPHY OFTHE MIDDLE WAY
2. Cekina celayi111ii ca karmoklaf{l p11rama-r11f!'ii,
1asy'iineka11idho bhethl/ RaN1lllf!l1Q parikrrtitaf?.
The Słłpteme Ascetic has said tbat action is volition as
well as volitio.nal.
Many distinct varieties of that action have ałso been
expounded.
MVK(P) pp.30~- 306 ; MKV(V) p.133.
At A 3.415 (Chung 27.5 (Tairho l.600a]), the Buddha
idcntified karma witb
"volition" arid maintaincd I.bat karµ-ia, whcther
it b_c bodily,·vcrbal, or mentaJ,
is to be ra:ognizcd as karmaifit is volitional (Cetana
'haf?l bhikkhave kammaf?Z
11adiimi. Cetayil11'ii kllmmaf{l karoti kayena t1acaya
manasii ca). ihe emphasis
oo volitjon was intendcd to ełiminate the wrong beliefthat a
person is responsible for any and every action be pcrforms, a view that was
advocated by theJain.a
thinkers of pte-Buddhist India (sec Kalupahana, Causality,
pp.125-126). The
distinct varieties of karma referred to herc arc ·the one's
preseoted in the
canonical Adhidharma, and these arc based upon the
discussions availabłe in
the early discowses.
3. Tait" yac cetanety uklaf{l karma miinasaf{l
smrtaf{l,
cetayitva ca yat tuk.taf{l tat tu kayik<1-11acikaf{l.
Herein, what is called volition is J"eminisced as
menralaction. Whaceveris
called volitiot1al consists of the bodily and verbal.
MKV(P) p. 306; MKV(V) p.133.
A difference is noticcable between the Buddha's owo
explanarioo of karma in
the statement from Ańguttara quoced acXVII.2 and the present
description of
Nigarjuna. While cetana or volition is dcfinicely meotal,
che Buddha seems to
assume that not all mental actioos·are volitiooal. Hence his
statement that all
,three forms of kar,na, bodily, verbal and mentał , can be
determined by volition. However, in the presen.t statcment, volition seems to
have been identified
with mentaJ action, the vołitional being confined strictly
co bodily and vetbal.
This laner view may be a reflexion of the Buddba's own staccment
at M 2.25
(Chung 47.2 [Tairho 1.720)), whcrcio both bodiły and verbal
actioos ace con·
sidered co havc mind as a basis.Exi.MINATION OP THE FRUIT OF
ACTION
4. Viig· fli/Pando 'viratayo yliś
ca11ijntipti·saf!Z}lłilii'1,
avijlłaptaya e11'iinya'1 smrlii viratayt1.S taiha.
5. Paribhoganvayaf!Z p11„yam apu„yaf!Z ca trJthavidha.f!Z,
cetana ceti
saptaite dharma!? karmiińjanal; smrtal;.
Whatever words and deeds that arc wociated with dclight and
dcsignated as non·intimation, and also tbosc others
rctniniscod as nonintimation, but arc associated with non-delight; similady,
merit as well as
demerit consequent upon enjoymcnt, and finally, voliti?n-
these arc
reminisced as the scvcn things that arc productive of
action.
MKV(P) p.307; MKV(V,} p.133.
245
Some of the ter~ used here to define the various forms
ofkarma appcar for the
first time in the Abhidharma (sec Akb iv.1-2; Akb
pp.162·164; Adv
pp.118-119). They arc absent in the eady discourses.
However, takcn in
themsełves, they do not seem to crcate any philopsophical
problems. The
philosophical problcms arose because of the manner in which
these actions
wece interpreter/. These interpretations are then taken up
for ex:aminacion by
Nigarjuna in the following verses.
6. Ti!thaty apaka-k'ii/iic cet kt11'm4 tan nityafiim iy'iit,
niruddhatp cen nirudrlhaf!l- sat ki'f!Z pha/af!Z jpnayqyati.
lfit is assumcd that action remains during the time it
ismaturing, then it
will approach permanence. If it is assumed to have ccased,
thcrt having
ceased, how can it produce a fruit?
MKV(P) p.311; MKV(V,} p .134.
This is actually the point at which Nagarjuna begins his
analysis of the
metaphysital assumptioos. Hece he immediately turns on to
the theories of
idencity and difference. The assumption taken up for
criticism in the :first line
needs to be examined carefully. UodoubtedJy, it is the
problem ofpotentilJIex-246 THE PH!LOSOPHY OF rnE MIDDLE WAY
istcncc. Such cxistencc may be undcrsrood in various ways.
Potcntialiry may be
takco as the cxistence of conditions that would eventually givc
rise co some particular cvcnt. Nagarjuoa, as may be scen in a moment, does not
sccm to objcct
to such an explanacion. Oo the contrary, if potentiality is
undcrstood in the
sense of substantial existcncc of the panicuJar.evcnt (in
this case, karma), even
when it has not marurcd or come to fmitioo, thcn that
assumption lcads to
ctemalism. This lattcr view is cenainly not acccptabłc to
Nagarjuna. It also
leads to the contrary view, that is, if the evcoc is
complcccly abscnt (and this
absence pertains to the very conditions that will cvenruaJJy
give cise to the
cvent), chen thcre will be doubts about the occurrence of
the cvcnt at all. This
is annihilationism. Thus, Nagarjuna is not dcoying the fruit
of action but only
the manocr in whicb it is explaincd.
7. Yo
'nkura-prabhrtir bl1at sa?r)tano 'bhipra11artate,
tata!? pha/af?Z
rte b'ijat sa ca nabhipra11artate.
Wbatcvcr serics that begins with a sprout p rocccds from a
sccd, and thcn
produccs a fruit. Howcver, without a sccd, such [a sccics]
would not procced.
MKV(P) p.312; MKV(V,J p .13).
The mecaphysical assumptions of the Sautraotik.a doctrine of
karma are under
review herc. The atomistic view of the life-process acccpted
by the Sautrantikas
compelled them to analyse an event into a series
(saf(Jt'iina) of moments. Their
major difficułty lay in explaining how one series (e,g. , a
sprout-series) comes to
be tied up with another preceding scries (e.g., a
seed-series), since thcy are different. If they are radicałly different, theo
the sprout-series CUl occur cven in the
absence of the seed-series. Nagarjuna maintains chat thls
docs not happeo. Io
other words, he is insisting chat philosophers like the
Sautrantikas will have to
acccpc the view tbat no evcnt can come inco being unless
therc wcre condicions
tbat give rise co ie; in this case it is the see_d-series.
8. Bi/ac ca yasmiit saf{Jtanaf? rtZf?Zlaniic ca
phalodbhavaf?,
brja-puroaf?Z phalaf?Z tasmiin nocchinnaf?Z napi
f(iŚ'l/ataf(J.EXAbilNATION OF TI-IE FRUIT OF AcnoN
Since a series arises Crom a s«d and a fruit ariscs from a
series, a fruit t.hat is
prcceded by a seed is, thereforc, neither inteuupted nor
etcrnal.
MKV(P) p.313; M.k'V(V) p. 135.
247
Lo answer to the question raised by Ni\garjuna, a
Sautrantika can i:espood tbus:
lnstead of conceiving of these as two differeot series, łet
us say that a series is
produced from a seed. ·This series then gives rise to the
effect (whk h is the
sprour). ln that sense, a fruit is preceded by a seed
(btja-purvarp phalaftl).
Understood in this way, one does nor fall into either the
eternałistic or the annibilationist view.
9. Yas tasmlic cittt1-Jt1ftlfiinflf cetaso 'bhipmvartate,
latał? phaltlftl
rte citfiit sa ca n'iibhipravarlate.
1 berefore, wbatever thought-series therc is, that
proceedsfrom a thought
and ftom that fruit. That thought series would not proceed
without a
thought.
10, Citfiic ca yasmlit SflftJfiinaf? IflftJfiinac ca
phalodbhaval?,
karma-purvaftl phalaftl tasmlin nocchinnaf!J napi
śifvatrw.z.
Since a continuous series arises from thought and from the
continuous
.series the uprising of\l fruit, the fruit that is preccded
by action is neithcr
intcrrupted nor etemal.
MKV(P) p.313-314; MKV(V) p. 135.
The Sautrantika continues: Similarły, a though series
(cilta-sam,fiina) cmerges
from a chought (cela.raf?). From that se.ries arises the
fruit. Thus, without a
thought, the fruit does not come to be. The thought followed
by a thoughtseries thus gives rise to the fruit. The fruit is thus preceded by
a thought which
is its cause. & such, it is neither permaoent nor
interrupted.
The causa! connection envisaged by the Sautriintikas abovc
is simple
antecedence.248 THE P!ill.OSOPHY OPIBE MIDPLli w/.Y
11. DharmtHya iiidhanoplijiil/ ś11klii'1 karma-path'ii
ritJSa,
phalt11?1 kiimagu'!il/ pańca dharmasya prety(I ceha ca.
The ten pure paths of action are the means of achieving
good. The five
smnds ofsetlSC pleasutc represent the fruit ofgood, here as
well as in the
next life.
MKV(P) p.314; MKV(V) p.136.
Following the causal pattern łaid down above, namely,
antecedence, the
Sautrantika would explain the tenfold path of action
(karma-patha) as beiog
initiated by volition (cetan'il) which puts it together
(tatliiibhisa7?1skilra„al, A.kb
p.248). Volition WU$ becomes the karma, and the series
ofaccions, bodily and
verbal (k'iiya-1iik), dctermined by that volition, becomes
the vchicle of action"
(karma,,af ca pantliiinaf?, ibid.). The pure bodily and
verłnl actioos would
then be the mcans by which good is achieved (dharmasy11
fiidhanop'iiyiif?). The
five strands ofpleasurc to be cnjoyed in a
"heavenly" life (svarg11), cithcr herc or
in the next world, wouJd be the fruit ofthe goód voJition.
This is the manncr in
which the Sauttantlkas otplained the Buddha1s notloo ofkarma
and its effect.
12. Bahavai ca mahantaf ca daiiil; syur api ka/pana,
yady eia tena
naiflai .fii kalpanatropapadyate.
If there were ro be such a thought, there would be many a
gren error.
Therefore, sucha thought is not appropriate hece.
llf.](J/(P) p.316; llf.](J/(V) p.136
Nagarjuna is not impressed by such an explanatioo. He
perceivcs many and
substantial errors in such conceprualizations. Hence he
considers them to be inappcopriate.
Inada's translacion, once again, skips an cxtremdy important
qualific.ation
made by Niigarjuna. "IfconcepruaJi.zations arc
permittcd, there will arise many
as weU as great errors," (p.107). The implicarion woułd
be that Nigarjuna rejccts all conc'Cptualizations. However, this is not the
case. Niigatjuna is very specific
in bis reference when he says: e1a kalpa!Ui, "these
concepcualizations," whereExAMINATION OF THE FRUIT OP ACI'ION 249
"these'' refers to the prcceding conceptualizations or
explanations. Indeed, it is
for this rcason that Nagarjuna can turo.around and speak ofa
more appropriate
thought or con~ptuaHzation in the next verse.
13. lmiif!' puna!?pravqk/yami kalpanaf!t yatra yojyate,
buddhail, pratyeka-buddhaiś ca fravakaiś canuvaf'T!ittlf!'.
Moreovcr, I shall expou.nd the following thougbt which is
appropriate
a.nd which has bcen extolled by the Buddhas, the
self-enlightened ones
' '
and the disciplcs.
MKV(P) p.317; MKV(V) p.13.
The preseot statement by Nagarjuna should.servc as an
antidote to most of the
misunderstandings that have prevailed so far regarding his
views about thought
and languagc. Nagarjuna is about to explain in no unclear
terms a more appropriate thought or conceptualization (ka/pana}, a right
thought (samyaksaf!'kalpa), a right view or perception (samyag-duft) relacing
to karma and its
fruit (phala). It is one that is extolled not only by the
Buddha, but also by his
disciples (fravaka) and the self-enlightened ones
(pratyeka--buddha). IfNiigarjuna had recognized a linguistically transcendent
ttuth or reality, he could not
have made the above statement.
14. Pattrat'(t
yatha 'vlprar{iiśas tatha-r1111m iva karma ca,
ca1t1TT1idho
dhatulai? sa prakrtya 'vyakt;taf ca sal,.
Li.kc an imperishable promissory note, so is debr as well as
action. It is
fourfold in terms of rcalms and indeterminate in terms
ofprimal nature.
Jrfl(V(P) p.317; jij}(l/(V) p.1)7
Herc, a.debt and karma are compared to an imperishable
promissory note. The
metaphor is significant and needs to be carefully cicamined.
It is used by
Nagarjuna to iłlustratc the doctrine of karma as described
in one of the most250 THE PHII.OSOPHY OF THE MJDDLE WAY
popular and authoricative scacements in the Indian Buddhist
craditioo. Two
centurics łater, Vasubandhu wrote a whole treatise -
Karmasit/-
dhtprakara,_,a - attempting to explain this statement.
Candrakirci quotes it
cwice in his commentary (pp.324,390). The fact that he does
not quote iratthis
point, where it seems to be most relevant, indicates thac he
was using it to
illuscrate a compłetely different point (sec bclow XVII.21).
The staccment runs
thus: "Karmas do not pcrish cvcn after hundreds of
millioos of aeons. Rcaching
the harmony of conditions and the appropriatc time, they
producc conscqucnces for human beings."
The first statement, taken in isolation, will convey the
impression that the
Buddhist theory of karma is detcrministic in an extreme
sense. However, the second scatement provides sufficient qualificacions to take
the dctcrminist sting
away. What seems co have compelled !nada to assume that
herc, "With equal
force he condemns any idea of an indestructible continuing
action (avipra„afakarma) which gives the sense of continuiry or transirion in
man's cvcryday life
and.deeds" (Niigarjuna, p.104), is his failure to
cvaluate thefirst statement in
the light of the qualifications provided in the second
statement, In the prcsent
chapter Nagarjuna is simply expłaining the fust statement,
i.e., "karmas do
not perish" (na pra,.,afyanfi karma'!t). His analysis,
at this point, is confined to
it. He leavcs the second Statemeot to be exarruned in two
ocher chaptcrs that
follow. After examiniog what an imperishable karma is,
N:igarjuna wants to
keep any soul-theory out of the way, and this he docs with
Chaptcr XVIIl. And
from thcrc, he immediately gets down to anałyse the conteots
of the second
statemeot by compiłing two chapters: (i) Cbapter XIX on the
"Examination of
Time" (Kii/a-pank.iii) and (ii) Chapter XX on the
"Examination of Harmony"
(samagn-pankfii). As such, it would be inappropriate to come
to any definite
concłusions regardiog the contents of this chapter uoril the
three followiog
chapters arc carefully cxamined. However, Nagarjuna's
statement at XVIIl.13
thar he "will state thi's moce appropriatc view"
(imaf!l kalpanaf!J pravak.$yami
yatra yojyate), which he thcn attributes to the Buddhas, his
disciples, and the
Pratyeka-buddhas would certainJy seem to indicatc chat he is
presenring an acceptabJe view, tather than one that should be rejected.
Furthermore, having made such a strong statement indicacing
chat he is
presentiog "this'' (imiitp) appropriate view, if
Nagarjuna were to follow it up
with a theory that he is condemoing, one will need to think
twice before considcring Nagarjuna to be a second Bucłdha.
To return to the metaphor of the prornissory notc (patra)
that one signs when
borrowing money- this metaphor being Nagarjuna's owo - he is
not speaking
of a permanent and eternal promissory note , but something
that wilJ remain so
long as it is not redeemed. As long as a promissory noce is
preserved, and u~css
one were to honor ooc's obligations, one will eveorualły,
dcpeoding upon timeEXAMIN/\TION OF THli FRUIT OF ACTION 251
and cooditions, have to face the consequcnc;cs. The
imperishability of the promissory note may aJso mean that even if th'c
promissory note is descroyed there
is an obligation on onc's part to honor such an agreement.
If', in order to account for such an obligation, one wcre to
assumc a substanda1 oature (prakrti = wabhava) in that act, Nagarjuna's reponse
is chac sucb a
nacure is i.not determinate" or is
"inexplicablc" (avyakr1a), an :11.nswer that the
Buddha himself gave when qucstioncd about metaphysical
issues (sec Chapter
·XXVII).
Finally, in terms of the realms in which the consequences
may be reaped.
such actions can be foutfold. Candarkini rcfers to the
fourfold realms as (i) the
sphere of sensuality (kiimiivacara), (ii) the sphere of
materiałity (rupivacara),
(iii) the sphere of the formless-{ariipavacara) , and (iv)
the state of freedom or
absence of influxes (aniifrtWa).
15. Praha,,,10 na prr1heyo bhavana-heya eva va,
tauniid avipra11a1ena1ay111e kaf'lfJa1'ł1if!' phala'f!J.
That [i.e., the impcrisbablc karma] would not be
relinquishcd by simplc
relinquishing. lt is to be relinquished on1y through
cultivation. Thus,
through the imperishabłe ;arises the fruit of action.
16. Praha„ataf? praheyaf! ryat karmaf!af! sa1t1krame„a 11a,
yadi do1af! prasajyeraf!IJ tatra karma-1111dhiyal/.
If it is to be relinquisbed through simple relinquishing or
througb the
transformation ofaction, thcn therc would follow a vańety
oferrors soch
as the destructi0n of actions.
MKV(P) pp.319-320; MKV(V) p.137-138.
When spealcing ofimperishable karma, naturally the question
can be raised as
to how it can be gottern rid of. Is it possible to nullify
the effect, say. of a bad
karma by simply not doing it again (praha„aJo praheyo)? The
theory ofprtipti
("attainment") and aprapti
("non-attairunent'') may impły such a sicuation.2)2 THE PHlLOSOPHY OFTHE
MIODLE WAY
Preventing the momenwy sueam of life from appropriacing a
bad karma
would mean the nulłification of the effects of aH previous
karmas. Nigarjuna
perccivcs this to be a negatioo of the docuine of karma
(leaf'fllll-11adha). He
therefore insists that the abandoning of the fruits of karma
c.an be aclUeved , not
through simple abandonment, but through constant practice
(bhiivanii), i.e.
constant performance or promotion of good accions and the
constant avoidance
of cvil actións (cp. sabbapiipassa akargf!tlf'!Z kusfllassa
upmampadii, D 2.49;
Dhp 183).
17. Saf'IJefiif'!Z vi/abhiiganiit?J sabhiginaf!Z ca
kArma'fl'iif!Z,
pratUaf!ldhau
sadhatiinii'?I ekA utpadyate tu saf?.
Of all thcse accions, whether dissimilar or similar,
bclonging to certain
realms, only one would arise at the moment of birth [of a
being].
MKV(P) p.321; MKV(V) p. 138.
Even though this statement of Nigacjuna is in perfect
conformity with the
Buddha's owo explanation of the doctrine of karma, it may
come as a surprise
to most Nigarjunian scholars, cspecially because it
confliccs with most opinions
exp~d about Nigatjuna's philosophy. Herc is an cxplanation
of rebirth (.punarbhavt1) cxamined in rełation to past karma. In the eyes
ofmost scholars, Nagar·
juna could nevec make a statemeot Jike this. Herc, karma is
presented a~ the
connecting link between two lives. lt is one of a myriad of
karmas an individual may have petformed, whether they be similar or dissimilar.
The face
chat only one (elea) among such actioos of a life-time may
appear at the time of
the conception of a being (pratis'tl~ht) and which can
influence the new lifeprocess is acknowledged by Nagarjuna. He could not have
been unaware of the
statement. of the Buddha that consciousness (viflłfii11a
which is inextricably
bound up with volitional karma) was a possible connecting
link between two
lives (D.3.105; Chang 12.2 [Taitho L 77bJ) and also of the
ernphasis placed by
his fellow Buddhists on the last thought of the dying person
(culi-citta) as hav·
ing influence over a new life-process (pafisandhi-cilta, sec
detailed discussion
at VbhA 155-160). Without falling back upon a mecaphysical
theory of
moments, as some of the Abhidharma interpreters did,
Nagacjuna is hece
recognizing the dependence of rebirth (pratisam,dht) oo at
least one previous
karma. lt is a similar cecognition chat made the Buddh.a
declare: "Beings have
karma as their own, karma as inheritance, karma as the
source, karma as kin. IrExAMJNATION OP 'fHE FRuJT OF AcnoN 253
is karma that distinguishes human beings, for example, as
inferior and
superior," (kammassa~a . .. satt'ii 'kammadiiy'iidii
kammayonikammabandhu,
kammaf!' salte 11abhaj<1ti yatlidatrt hln.appańilllfiiya,
M 3.203; Chung 44.1
[Tairho 1.704c]). Unfortunately, Buddhaghosa's explanation,
though retaining
the i.deas expre~scd by the Buddha as well as Nigarjuna, is
marreci by a thcory
of moments (see VbhA 156). Just as much as mcmory is bcing
described by
most psychologistsas being "owned"
.withouthavin~toassume its permanence,
bere we find a person's karma bcing perceived as something
"owned'' by bim.
18. Karma~111?
karman.o drrte dharma utpadyate tu .rab.,
d11i-prak'iirasya sarvasya 11ipakve pi ca tif/hati.
That [imperishable] arises in the present life,
corresponcłing to all the actlons having dual natures [similat and dissimilar,
good and bad, etc.] and
stays so even when matured.
MKV(P) p . 321.; MKV(V) p.138.
A further explo.-atioo ofthe Buddha's docuine ofkarma is continued
bere. The
phrase Jute dharme is a sanskritizatio.n ofPali dt{tha
dhamma, which itselfcan
be traced back co drrta-Janman, meaning "the present
life." The fruitioning of
kanna .into good and bad consequences is admitted hece.
19. Phalll~11jalikrafft4d 11a sa marrJ'!ad va nirudhyate,
anafravatrt I tilra11aftt ca vibhagaf!' tatra lakrayet.
Tbat [imperishable} ceases as result of theintetruption
ofthe fruit or as~
result of death. lierein, a clistinction betwcen one with
influxes and the
one without inflm:es is to be signified.
MKV(P) p.322; MKV(V) p . L38.
The so-caJled imperishable action (avipraf!afa-karma) cao
terminate as a result
oftwo 'evcnts: (i) the interruption of the
fruit(phala-vyatikrama) , or ((ii) death254 TuE PHlLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE 'iY/AY
of the individual. ln the case of the latter, it is
necessary to remtmber what was
said at XVII.17, i.e., that all accioos performed during a
lifetime are not continued. Only one of the myriads of actions performed can
domioate the last
thought: moment ofa person. This wouJd mean that many other
karmas, even
though all of them have not matured, may become nułlified at
the time of
deat~.
20. ŚUnyata ca na cocched4// sa'!l-s'iiraf ca na
śiiśvata'!I-,
karma'ło 'vipraTJaśaf ca dharmo buddhena defitaf?.
Emptiness, however, .is not annihilarion; life-pcocess
is.also not eternal;
the imperisbability is of acrion-such is the doctrine taught
by .he Buddha.
MKV(P) p ,322; MKV(V} 138.
Ifwhat is said before is an approptiate explaoation of
karma, then Nagatjuna
can maintain that "emptiness!' (JUnyalii) does not mean
"annihilatioo" (uccheda). At the same time he can maintain that the
life-process (saf'!JJara) is not
a permaoent and etemal (fafvata) process. In such a context,
an irnpcrishabłe
action (avipraf!aśa-karma) simply means the continuity of
that life-process conditioned by kanna until some ofthese karmas bear ftu.it or
~e lost on the way,
while others łike the threads of a web can contioue to
iilfluence the future lifeprocess. In any case, the eotire process is one of
depeodence- dependence
upon a whole composfre of factors.
Nagatjuna has no hesitacion in attributing such a doctrine
of karma and personal idenity to the Buddha himself artd praising it as the
Buddha-wotd, even
though the atuibution ofsuch a doctrine co Nagarjuoa would
be unacceptable
to some of the dassicaJ and modern foUowers of
N""agarjuna himself.
21. Ki11'f!la
notpadyate kasmiit nil{svabhavaf?t yai(lI tata!?,
yasmac ca tadanutpannaf!Z na tasmiid
vipra„aśyati.EXAMIN.<\TION 01' THE FRUIT OF ACTION
Why does action not a.rise? Because it is without
self-bature. Since it is
non-arisen, it docs not perish.
MKV(P) pp .323-324; MKV(Jl) p.139.
255
Havjng <:oncluded the- explanatioo of the more
appropriate view.of karma as
advocated by the Buddha, Nigarjuna does not leave the
discussioo without
taldng a look at the possible metaphysical interptetacions
or any m.i.sunderstanding of th.is doctrine. He has already spoken of the
arising (utpaa'a)·ofkar.nia at
the moment of rebirth (pratisaf!U/hi). That arising is
understood iii ręlacion to
the principle of dependent arising (prafityasamutpada). ·The
i.mperishability
(avipra'łfifa) is introduced in order to explain the
continuity in the fruitioning
ofaction. It is not intended as a justification for the beliefin
a permanent and
eternal substance (svabhava). However, some of the Buddhists
did utilize a notion ofsubstance to account for the functioning of karma. It is
this particular
notioa of substaace that is taken up for analysis.
If karma is "non-substantial" (nil/svabhava) in
the way the Sautrantikas
understood it, i.e., without any perceivable cootinuity, but
ooly as something
that is continually inter.rupted, then the arising of such
karma cannot be explained. If arising cannot be accounted for in such a
metaphysical way , neither
can cessation be admitted. Imperishability (avi'prar;afa),
as explained by
Nigarjuna, becomes the only othet alternative.
UnfortunatĆly, Candrakrni, who favored a rather absolutistic
interpretation
of Nigarjuna (sec comments on the Dedicatory Verses),
utilizes the conception
ofinlpecishability in order to denyany form ofarising. It is
because he had such
..an interpretation in mi'nd that he quotes the famous
ve.rse elucidaciog karma at
this .point rather thao utilizing itwhen the
i.mpecishabiliry was first meotioaed
by Nigatjuna at XVII.14. As has been shown alieady,
Nagarjuna was n~t
critical ofany and every form of arising or ceasing. He was
only rejecting the>
metaphysical ideas.
22. Karma svabhavataś cet sy?i« chaftlata'f(l syad
a.ra'J'!Zśaya'f(l,
tJktttJT(l ca bhavet k.armt1 knyate nrz hi śiifvafaf?t.
lfit·is aSSwned that actio.o comes to be from self-nature,
i-t certainly will256 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
be etccnal, and action would a1so be uncaused, for that
which is crernal
is, indeed, not caused.
MKV(P) p.324; MKV(V) p.139.
If the arising of karma cannot be accounted for by following
tbe Sautrantika
mcthod, can it be explained in terms of the Sarvastivada
conception? Nagarjuna's answer is negative. He seems to know with great
cenainty (asaf!Zfayao/,)
that the Sarvastivada solution docs not work. It implies
permanence and as a
result karma would appear to be "un-done" or
"uncreated" (akrta).
23. Akrliibhyiigama-bh11y11f!Z syat karmiikrtakaf!Z yadi,
abrahmacarya-11asai ~a do!as tatra prasajyate.
lfan action werc not pecformed [by the individual], then
there woułd be
fcar ofbeing confronted by something not perfocmed [by him]
. Anignoblc life as wcll as error would follow from this.
MKV(P) p.325; MKV(V) p. 140.
If actions were to be something noc performed, then a person
would be
.baunted by the fear (bhay11) or anxiety that he bas no hand
in the organization
of his own lifc-process. Fears and anxieties, according to
Na~rjuna's view, arc
one's own creations. Deny one's owo rcsponsibility, one does
not have to justify
a life of maral purifY (brahmacarya-vasa). This is a elear
and uncquivocal assercion of personal res}»onsibility for onc's owo pufity and
defilement.
24. Vyavahara
virudhyante saroa eva na sa1?1fayal/,
puf}ya-papa-krlor
naiva pravibh~gai ~ yujyate.
Uadbubtedly, all conventions would tben be contradictcd. The
distinction benveen the_performance of merit and evil will aJso not be proper.
MKV(P) p.325 ; MKV(V) p.140.Ext.MINATION OF 'THE FR\JIT OF A
cnoN 257
With the cejection of a life of morał purity resulting from
the deoial ofhuman
responsibility for act~ons, all motał conventions like merit
and demedt (pu„yapapa) would be reodered 1Peaningkss. lt is interescing to note
thac Nagarjuna
is not referring to the good-bad (dharmt1-adhamz.a or
kusala-akusala) distinc·
tion , for this łatter distincc~n is differctnt from the
former in regard co ics value
as a convencion (11ya11ahar~). This is compacible with the
Buddba's own explanation of 'karma. On 'pragmatic grounds, the Buddha
recognized the
merit/ deme.cit distinction. ltwas helpful in leading
theordinary people coward
accepting a morał life. However, the notions of merit and
demerit coułd be
harmful in che long run. especiałly because it involves the idea
of accumułation
of merit for the sake offuture enjoyment and pleasure.
Funhermore 1 it is easily
assoc.iated with che notions of reward and punishment, a
notion that the Buddha was not willing to relate to the doctrine of karma (see
M 1.373; Chung 32. l
[Tairho l.628b]). As such, the Buddha insisted that a
morally perfected person.
would ełiminatc: the desire to accumuJate merit or demerit
(punna-papapaht11a, Dhp 39; samiliitiipaliiiya punnapiipaf!I, Sn 540). Yet, it
does not mean
that suc~ a person also abandons the good/ bad
(kusala-ak_usala) distinction
which is the very basis of merit and demerit. lod~ed , a
morally perfect person is
expected to promote good, while eliminating evil or
uomed.torious actioits (see
above XVU.l , 17). lt may be for this reason that even a
łater Mahayana
philosophir like Dogen deemed it approprate to compile a
whole treatise on
this subject.
25. · Tad vipakva-vipiikaf!I capunar~va 11ipak1yatt;
karma 11yavasthita1!J yasmiit tasmat s11abha11ika1'!J yadi.
If actio.n wc:re to be detcrminc:d, because it possesses
self-oature, thcn a
matuńry that has maturcd will again maturc.
MKV(P) p.326; MKV(V) p.140.
If an action wc:re to take płace without being performed by
someone
(akrtakaf!I), theo it will occur on its owo. It will possess
·its own oature
(s11abhii11a). Such a substantiaJ action will have its own
consequences (111jiiik11)
inhereot in it. In that case_, what is being described as
the fruitióning of kanna.,
namdy, a mar_iifestation ofits consequences, wouJd merely be
a re-fruitiooing.258 THE PHILOSOPHY Ol'nfE MrooL.E WAY
This is the same sort of criticism that Nigarjuna made
ofself-causation (st1atautpa1Jt) in Chapter I.
26. Karma klefiitmaka11J cedafl.J te ca kleśii na
tall11ataf),
na cet te
tat111atal/ klefiil/ karma sjiit 1att11atal; kathaf{'.
lf thls action is associatcd with defilements, these
dc6.1emcnts, in tum,
arc not found in themśelves. lf deftlements arc not in
themselvcs, .how
coułd there be an action in itself?
MKV(P) p.236; MKV(V) p.140.
The substantialist explanation of karma presented at XVII.
25 would lead to the
distinccion bctwcen karma and its quality or attribute.
Qualities refcrred to as
dcfilements (kleśa), etc.. would be merdy incidental. A
karma can then make
ddilement "ies owo" (kleiat11111ka) or it can be
freed.from defilements (nil/-
kleśiluif. Such a subscantialisc perspective, as mentioned
so often by ·Nagarjuna, would rendcr the defilements unreal (na tatt11atal/).
cspecially because
thcy come and go, arise and pass away, and hence without self-oacure.
Karma,
in sucha case would be substantial, and the acuibutes
non-substancial. Nigarjuna, the empiricist, sees no way in which sucb a
substancial karma, divorced
from the acuibutes, can be identified.
27. KaTYTlll klefas ca dehiinaf{' pratyayif? samudiihrtal?,
kamtti klem ca te Junya ya_di dehetu ka katha.
Action and dc61cmcnts arc specificd as the conditions of the
[different)
bodies. Howcver, if these actions and defilemcnts arc empty,
what could
be said about the bodies?
MKV.(P) p.327; MKV(V) p.141.
Herc Nigarjuna moves on to a rugher generality. Botb karma
and defilements
_arc geoerally considered to be the conditions that
decermine the iodividual. AsExAMINATION OF 1HE FRurr OF ACTION 2~9
such, karma and defilments become attributes ofthe personaJity
(de/.a). In the
ptevious verse, Nigarjuna questioned the substantial reality
of both karma and
defilmcots. lfthey arc cmpty ofsuch reality, what could be
said about the per·
sooaJity itself?
28. A11idya-ni11r10 jantus tr111a-saf!J:fojanaf ca sal?,
sa bhoklii sa ca
na kartur anyo na ca sa eva saf?.
A sentient being, beclouded by ignorance, ualso fettcred by
craving. As
an experienccr, he is neither idcnticał With nor
differentfrom the agent.
MKV(P) p .328; MKV(V) p.141.
The Buddha's discourse to Acela-Kassapa, the discoursc which
served as the
fouodation for Nigarjuna1s treatment of
"suffering" (Chapter Xll. Dukkhapanlqii), rejected the thcories
ofself-causacion and exteroaJ causation of sufft.cing. Rejecting
self-causation, the Buddha maintained: "Kassapa, co say that 'a
person acts and he himself expedences the consequences,'
wbcre self-caused
suffering belongs to one.who has existed from the bcginning,
implies etcrnalism" (so karali JO pafisaf(Jvediyaff ti kho KaJsapa adito
salo sayaf(JRalafP
dukkhanti iii vadaf!J sassalaf!J elaf(I pareli, S 2.20; Tsa
12.20 [Taisho 2.86a]).
On the contrary, "To say thac 'one acts and another
expcriences the conscqucoccs,' where the suffering causcd by another belongs to
one who has been
afflicted with pain, implies annihilationism" (afllło
karoli afllło
pafisaf!l.vediyaff ti .. . vedanabhitu'!'!fZSsa salo
paraf(1kataf(1 dukkhanti iii
vada~ ucchedaf!# elQf(J pareti, ibid.). lt is interesting to
note that in the former
case, the Buddha refers to the bclief in a bcing who existed
from the bcginning
(adilo salo), an idea that is generally considercd both by
the Buddha and by
Nigarjuna as contributing to a beliefin a permancnt entity
(sec ChapterIX on
Piirv11-pank1ii).
In the present verse, Nigarjuna is faithfully following the
Buddha'~ owo
argument to reject the identity as well as differeoce
bctween a doer and an cxpcriencer. A person who believes either in ideotity or
in difference is looked
upon a someone who is beclou'ded by ignorance (avidyii) and
craving (trf'!ii).
29. NQ pratyaya-samutpannaf(J niipratyaya-samullhitaf!J,
aJti ymf!iiitl idaf!J k.armll tasm41 kartipi niisty aJał.260
T HE PHILOSOPHY Of THE MIDDLE W AY
Since this action does not exist as ańsen from a condition
nor as issuing
forth from a non-condition, evco an agent does not exist.
MKV(P) p.328; MKV(V) p.141.
The causa! cxplanations of karma offcred by the
metaphysidans, oamcly, selfcausation, cxternal causation, etc., or the
ooo-causal cxplanations arc not accep~blc . If karma itscłf cannot be expłained
in thls way. it would ·be futile to
attcmpt any such explanations of an agent of karma. Note the
use of the term
i"'1fl.J (this) to ccfer to wma, similar to the use of
the term efii at XVII.6, thus
spccifying the typc of explanation that is rcjected by hirn.
Por this rcasoo, we
prefer to confine his cdticism only to the mctaphysical
views mcntioned in the
verses immediateły preceding (XVII.21-28), lcaving the moce
appropriate view
he mentioocd untouched. Tbis secms to be the only way in
which one can
rccognize consistency in Nagarjuna's statements throughout
this chapter.
30. Kllf1'/'la cen niisti karfii Cli llukll/ syi1
hlrmaja'f!' phalat?J,
maty 111ha phale bhokti kuta eva 'bh1111i1y11ti.
lfboth action and agent are non-existent, whett could therc
be the fruit
boro of action? When there is no fruit, where can therc be
an ex·
pericncu?
MKV(P) p.329; MKV(v,) p.141.
In the absence of either an aciton or an agent
metaphysically coaccived, there
could be oo fruit or consequcoce boro ofsuch action
(hlrmafat?J phala?!Z)· Herc
again, itis not a denial offruit or consequcnce born
ofaction, but only of those
that arc bora ofsuch action as explained previously. If the
(ruit or consequence
is not obtaiocd, its cxperiencer (bhoRfii) would also not be
appropriate.
31. Y111ha nirmilt1ka'f!' 1'iistli nirmimlta rddhi-111mpadii
nirmito nirmifliitlinya?!Z sa ca nirmitakal/
punal/,EXAMINATION OF THI! FRUIT OF A cnoN
Just as a teacher, through psycho-kinetic power, were to
create a figurc,
and tbis created figure were to create anothe.r, tbat in
turn woułd be a
created.
32. Tathi nirmitakaral; karla yat karma taf kr:tam.,
Mlyalha nirmiteniinyo nirmito nirmitas tatha.
In the same way, an agent is like a crcated form and his
action is łike'his
creation. lt is like the created form created by another who
is cr~ted.
MKV(P) p.330; MKV(Vj p.142.
261
One metaphysical view lcads.to anothcr, that to a further
mctaphysical view.
Such is the W1CAcling citdc. A metaphysical view is, indced
fabricated by som~
one. Yet the fact that sucha mctaphysical view turns 9ut to
be empty does
not mean that the cxpcricncc dcpcnding upon which the
metaphysical view
was formulated 0or the proccss of conception arc thcmselvcs
non-existent. Expcriencc as well as concept arc availablc. ·Only that the
conception is carricd
bcyond itS limits to assumc the existence of independent
entities, .whcther they
be atman or svabhiiva. To understand the significancc of
Nagarjuna's statement h~re it would be nc:cesary to cake a look at one of the
rarc statemcnts of
the .Buddha recorded in the Siimańfiaphala-.ruttanta (D
1.76-77). In this
passage, which explains the fruit of redusesbip, the Buddha
refcrs to two forms
ofknowledge a contemplacive could develop before he directs
his a~tention to
the so-called higher forms of knowledge (abhififiii}. The
first is dcscribed as
fu~M: · · .
With hiS mind thus sercne, made pute, translucent, cultured,
devoid of evłl, supple, ready to act, firm and
imperturbable..he ap.
plies ·and bends down his mind to that knowledgc .and
insight
whereby he gtasps the fact: "This body of mine has
form, it.is built
up of the four clements, it springs from mother and father,
is continually rencwed by so much ~oiled rice and .juicy foods, itS very
nature.is impcrmanence, it is subject·to erosioo, ab~asion,
clissołution, and clisintegration; and therein lics this consciousoess of
mine, too, boun1d up„ on that it ąoes depeod.262 THE
PHILOSOPHY OFTiłE MIDDLE WAY
This represenu the Buddha's expeńence and cooceptioo ofhis
owo personality.
Having stated this, he i.mmediately proceeds to examine
whether there is
aoytliing beyood this experience and cooceptioo. What he
describes is no mote
than the funciton ofman(IS, the faculcy which is responsible
for the formulacion
of the metaphysical ideas of self(atman) and substance
(s11abha1111). The statement reads:
With his mind thuś serene, . .. firm and impercurbable, he
applies and beods down his mind to the calling up ofa mental image.
He calls up from this body aoother body, having form, made
of
mind (mano-maya), having all (his own body's) limbs and
pans,
not deprived of any organ.
This is how manas becomes a sensus communis surveying the
sensory fields of
other faculties (M 1.295) and maiotaining a feeling
ofidentity, which then gets
· converte<ł to a permanent and eternal iitman. Could it
not be póssible that
Nigarjuna was aware of the above statement of the Buddba?
What could be
the 'differe.oce between the cteation ofa non-existeilt form
thtough the power
of psychok.inesis and thć generation ofa belief in a permanent
and eternal self
tbough the activities of manas? It seems that human beings,
with fa:culties
through which they arc able to perceive and conceive, a.re
not the objects of
Nigatjuna's critidsm. lt is only the manner in which
perceptions and.conceptions arc formulated that is under criticism.
·33. Kiesa/; kaT'11'Ji11i deha.f ca karliiraf caphaliini ca,
gandhaf"lla-111Jgarakara mtJiici-.wapna--sa??Jnibhal;.
Defilements, actioos and bodies, agents as well as fruits,
all these aie similar to
the cities of the gandharvas, arc comparable to mirages and
dreams.
MKV(P) p.334; MKV(V) p.143.
The metaphors usecł at the end of Chapter VIl to illustrate
the natutc of
m~tapłiysical theories pe~taining to arising, stasis, and
ceasing, arc employed
here to elucidate the character of similarly conceived
theories relating to
defilements, actions, personalities, agents, and
conscquences. .CHAPTER
EIGHIEEN
Examination of Self
(Atma-par"ik.fa)
1. Alma skandhii yadi bhaved udaya-vyaya-bhiig bha11et,
skandhebhyo 'nyo yadi bhaved bhavedaskandha-lakfa'laf?.
Ifthe selfwcrc to be idcntical with theaggreptcs,
itwill.pattakc ofupr:ising and ccasing. Ifit wcrc to be diffcrent from the
aggrcptcs, it would
havc the charactcristics of the·non-aggreptcs.
MKV(P) p.341 ; MKV(fl? p. 145.
'
The conception of an individual self (atman) was previously
cxamincd in a
varicty ofcontc:xts. The prcscnt anałysis was occasioned by
a occd to cxplain the
lifc-process as cooditioned by human actions (karma), the
subjcct mattcr ofthe
preccding cfuptcr. ·
The Buddha's analysis ofthe human personałity into five
aggrcgates (paflcllkkhandha) was intended to show that underlyiog the
empirie.al factors constituting the human pcrsooality there is oo pcrrnaneot
and eteroal self. The
Buddha's view was that chcsc five factors servcd .as the
basis for any conceptuałization of a self or soul. Hence thcy arc ałways
referrcd to as aggregatcs of
grasping (upiidiinakkhandha).
Nagarjuna bcgios his investigatioo into the conception
ofself by raising two
questions pertaining to the nature of the self, espccially
in .its rcłatiooship to
the fivc aggrcgates. If the self and·thc aggrcgatcs werc
identical, thcn the self
would havc to paru.kc of the characteristics of the
aggregatcs. Thcsc latter bcing subjecc to arising and ccasing, the self cannot
remain pcrmanent and etcrnal. On the contrary, if the self and the aggregates
wece to be diffcrent, theo
the former could not have the $arrIC characteristics as the
latter. Leaving the
argument at that, Nagarjuna is allowing the rcadcrs to come
to thcir OWll conclusions.
So far Nagarjuna has not givcn any indication that he
tecognizcs a spcciał intuicivc faculty througb which one can sec beyond the
world of change and impcrmancnce. Indecd, all that be has admiucd points to his
i:ccognition ofsense
263264 THE PHILOSOPHY OP THE M IDDLE WAY
c:xpcrienccs as the foundation of human knowledge. The
impcrmanent·aggregates constitute not only the human personality, but also its
experiences. If
the self is considered to be different from the aggregates,
Nagarjuna is herc implying that it is unknowable, not merely inconceivable, for
it will not have any
of the characceristics of the aggregates chat are all that
we know through sense
cxpcnencc.
2. Atmany 41ah·ciitniiyaf!l kuta e11a bha11i.fyati,
nirmamo nirahaf!lkaraf? samiidiitmiitmani·nayof?.
·Jn the abscnce ofa self, how can there be something tbat
beJongs to the
self? From the appeasement of the modes ofself and
self-hood, one abstains from acating the notions of "minc'' and
"I."
MKV(P) p .34~-347; MJ(V(V) pp.147·148.
If a permancnt entity does not exist, one cannot assumc the
existence of
anything that bdongs to ie. The deniaJ of a permancnt entity
does not mean
that Nigarjuna is committed to a rejcction of self-awareocss
or selfconsćiousncss . The rejcction of the lattec would undcrmine the very
foundation
of his cpistemology. As mcntioned carlier (sec lll.17),
Nagarjuna, following
the Buddha, recognized consciousness (and this includes
sclf-awareness), not as
a pre·existent cogiJo, buc as part of the human personałity
condicioncd by facrors such as the sense organs and the objects of perception.
Sclf-awarcncss or
self.instinct can be pursued to its extremc limit. The
result is che "construction
of a self' (ahaf!l + kara) , which eventualły leads to the
belicf in permanence.
The other cxueme is the complete rejetton ofany form
ofself·awareness, which
is tantarnount-to annihilation.
Without falling into these two exttemcs, Nigarjuna is herc
prcsenting the
Buddha's owo "middle way" philosophy when he speaks
of the appeasement
(f11ma), not the complere cradication, of the "self'
(at.man) and ''whatever that
pertains to a self" (itmant)..This is pecfectly in
accord with the "appeasement
of dispositions" (1ą~kiiropaiama), the
"appea5ement of the object"
(drf11(t111yopaśama), ~nd the "appeasement of
obsessions" (prapaficopafama),
discussed eatliec·(see commentary on V.8).
Through the appeasement of the self-instinct one eliminates
the
met2physical nod ons of a self (atman), and through the
appeasement of the
object (drtlłf'WJopaśam11) one is ablc to realize the
non-substantiality ofE:JW.ł lNATlON OF SELF 26~
phenomcna and would not eling to them~ "ooe's own"
('iitmani). These
culminate in the absence of self1Shness (ni"'1'1ma) and
the absence of egoism
(niraha'f(lkara). ·
The dual meaning of the term 11h11'f(l/dira isworth noting.
Ah11f?Jkir11 (literaJly. "1-making") mcans both ego-centcredness and
pride. )Vhile the term
aha'l.'kira has come to be so popula,r in ordinary languagc,
it is interesting·to
note that oo such term is construcied with the pluraJ
ofahaf!I, namely, maya'f(I,
as ""'Jllf!IUra ("we-making1') would have
expressed an idea which is eq'ually
unacceptable to the Buddha and Nigarjuna, for they were not
willing to
e~te th~ notion of oneself (aha'f!I) altągether in favor of
an equ~lly
mc~physical notion of a "social self" , ·
3. Nirmamo nirahaf!luro yaś ca .ro 'Pi na 11idya1e1
·nirmama?'(J niraha'f(lk'iiraf!Z yal/ paśyati na paśyati.
Whosoever is free from selfisbness and egoism, he too is not
evident.
Whoever perceivcs someone as lree from selfisbness and
egoism, he too
does not eerceive.
MKV(P) p. 348; MKV(V) p. 148.
Nigarjuoa approvingly spoke of the appeasement of the ootioo
of selfand th~
conscquent elimination of sełf1Shness and egoism. However,
koowiog his contemporaries who were so prone to metaphysical speculacions, he
was not willing
to rest satisfied with such a statement.
As a remind~r to those who have not achieved the
"appeasement of the nocion of self," Nigjlrjuna pointS out' that
someone who is assumed to havc got·
ten rid of egoism 'and pride is alsó not available. The
constant attempt by the
metaphysicians to reify things, entities, persons, etc. was
kept in mind by
Nigarjuna whenever he roakes any positive assertion.
.
4. Me.mety aham iti '-!Tt!e·bahirdhidhjiitmam e~a ca1
nirudhyata upadiinattz lat k!afiijjanmanal; R!ayal;.
Wben views pertuning to "mine" and "I" ,
whether they arc assodated266 THE PHllOSOPHY Of rnE MIDDLE WAY
with the interna!._or the exterml, have wancd, 'chen
grasping comes to
cease. With the waning of that [grasping], there is wani.ag
of birth.
MKV(P) p.349; MKV(V) p.149.
The usc of the iii formula as mama-iii and 11ham-ili in the
prcscoc scatcment
makcs it sigoific:antly differcnt &om the founcr
statcrncnt at XVlll.2. In the
former statement, Nigarjuna spoke of 111m11n (self) and
'iilm"iy11 (that which
bclongs to the self) and cmphasizcd the nccd ro appcasc such
awar~ncss or f~eling. Iń the prescnt verse, he refers-to t1h11m ("I")
and mt1ma ("mine") using the
iii-formula and insists upon thcir complete elimination.
(.ł,r11jt1) . Thus, it is not
che fact of self~awarencss that causes problems for the
human beings but the
theorizing bascd upon such sclf-awarencss. The cogito may
thus ruro out to be
harmless, so long as it is considered to be a product of the
sensory process (sec
m. 7), but ergo sum is what is dangerous, episcemoJogically
as wcU as ethically.
When such thcorizing has waned (kf.i11e), t}?cn there is
cessarion of gtasping
· (upadin11-nirodh11), which is frecdom whilc living. The
cessation of grasping
cvcntually lcads to the waning of rebirth (j1111man11f?
k,rayaf?).
5. Ka1"f1Ul-kle111--k1ayan mok,ra karma-kiera
vikalpataf?,
te prapańcat
prapałlcas tu filnyat'iiy'iif{i nirudhyate.
On the waning of dc6Jemen~ ofaction, therc is relcasc.
Defilemcnts of
action bclong to one who discriminatcs, and thesc in turo
result from
obsession. Obsession, in ics tuto, ccases within the context
of emptiness.
MKV(P) pp.349-350; MKV(V) p.149.
The face that this statement of Nigatjuna immediately foUows
his criticism of
theorizing relating to "mine" and "I,"
that is, speculation relatlng to subject
and object, becomes very valuable in deterroioing the
meaning of the cerm
flWŃp11, a term that has caused much confusion and
misunderst:anding.
Vikalpa can mean two differenc types of discriminatioo. One
is the type of
discrimination made at the pheoomenaJ.levcl. lt is the
discrimioation referred
to at XVIII.2, a discrimination that'is empiricaJły
grounded, but which should
bekcpt under control (fama). The second ~ the type
ofdiscrimi02tion made at
a mecaphysical Jevcl. lt is the discrimination referrcd to
at XVIII.4, which hasExAMJNATION OF Sm.F 267
gone far beyond the cmpiricał levcl and thus become
theorecicał or speculative.
For Nigarjuna, che defilements óf action foJłow from the
łatter, not from the
former. It scems that this is the primary reasoo for his
rcfcrence ro and criticism
of11ikalpa at XVIIl.5 rathcr than at XVIIl.3.
Wrong actions (mithya-karman111). i.e„ actions chat are
defilcd, emanate
from wrong beliefs (milhy1i-dr1/I), which arc the results of
wrong thoughts or
discriminations (mithya-sa~kalpa, mithjii 11ikalp11).
Obsessions arc- the inevitable tesults of such wrong discr.iminations. When-
such obsesśioos arc appcased, then a person does not get involved either in a
ootioo ofa permanent
self or in a theory ofcomplete annihilacioo. The reałizacion
that self-awareness
is dcpeodently arisen (IlL7) is a realization that it is
empcy of a permanenc
subsrance (svabhava-iunya). This latter is the middle path
that avoids eter·
nałism and annihilationism.
6. Atmety qpiprajflapitam an'iitmety (lpi deiita~,
buddhair niitrnii na caniitmii kaicid ity api deii.ta~.
The Buddha's havc malce known the conception of self and
taught the
doctrine of no-self. At the same time, they have not spoken
ofsomethiiig
as the self or as the non-self.
AfKV(P) p.355; MKV(V/ p.152
Ifthe distinctions made in XVIII.2 and 4 are not recognized,
it is nacuraJ for the
interprecers of Nigarjuna to run into diffićułcies in
explaining the contents of
tl:iis verse. Hece agin we have che use of the iti-formula,
this time used with the
terms alman and anatman, as atma-iti and anatma-iti.
However, the differeocc bctween the Buddha's specu łations and those of the
metapbysicians in
this regard is thac the Buddha does not speculate on any
enaty (kaicid) as
alman OC as anatman. In other words, he does not reify
either atman or
anatman. Reifying atman one eods up in eternaJism; reifying
anatman one is
led to annihiJationism. Withouc resorcing to such
reificacion, the Buddha has
indicaced the meaning of atman.(atmetz'prajnapitaf!I) and
has spoken of·the
implications ofanatman (aniitmeti deiita~) . Both atman and
an1ilman are explained by the Buddha in terms of dependent arising
(.prafityasamutpada).
This doctrine of dependent arising eliminates the need for
posrulating either
permaoence or annihilation.268 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE
WAY
As such, the distinccion that Inada attempcs to make
bctweenprajflapilaf!J as
"provisionally empłoyed" and defitarrz. as
"instructed '' becomes untenabłe. 1f
" provisiona ł explanation" is to be achieved by
the use of words, it r.ould not be
different from "instruction." Both need the use of
language. Just as much as
the Buddha could instruct on the "true idea of
anatfnlln," he could have instructed on the rrue idea of atman, without
falling into mctaphysics in either
case. If che·use of the cmpirical terms can be ucilized in
one case, thece is no
reasoo to assume any difficułcy in using them in the ocher.
The problem then is
not with regard to language as such. but only in regard to
the way in which it is
used.
7. Nivrttam abhidh'iita11yatp ni11(t1e ctlta-gocare,
anutpann'iiniruddh'ii hi nir11'iil!am iva dharmatii.
When the sphere of though łw ceased, that which is to be
dcsignated aJso łw
ceased. Lilce freedom, the oature of things is non-arisen
and non-ceased.
MKV(P) p.364; MKV(V) p.154.
"Whereof thought has ceased, thereof speech also has
come to
cease."
Abhidhiilllllya meaos "that which is to be
dcsignatcd." It rcfecs to the' Jb~Jd
ofobjects. lt ~ the same as abhidheya which, ifwe follow
Nigarjuoa's roethod
of exposition, is mutuałły relatcd to abhidhana,
"designation." Bot&
abhidheya and abhidhana would thus cease to be ałong w1th the
ccssacioo of
the sphece of thought (citta-gocara).
"Wbeceof one canoot spea.k, thereof one must be
silent."
lt is possible for the incerpreters of Nigatjuna to assume
that herc is the idcotification of the "unspca.kabłe" with
"cmptiness" (śUnyafii), generalły cefecred
to iq negative terms as "non-arisen, non-ceascd"
(anutp(lnnaniruddha), which
is then identificd with both "true oature"
(riharmat"ii) and frcedom ~nin.iii11a).
This is the easy route to the bełief in the so-całlcd
"non-conccptuał" (nir·
vikalpa) ultiroate reality (paramiirtha, tallva).
Howcver, the fust lice ofNagarjuna's scatcment should
prcvent anyone EromEXAM1NATION OP Sm..F 269
reaching such a conclusion. Nowhere has Nigarjuna asserted
any form of
knowłedge that transcenps the six senscs. For him, what is
perceivable is ałso
conceivable. He may, reflecting upon the conceptualization
of the metaphysicians, admit that what is not perceivable is also conceivable.
Yet, it woułd be
improper to assume that he will recognize the non-conceptual
(11ir-11ikalpa) as
being perccivable. Conceptualiziog and concciving arc not
two different activicies. Hence his statement: "When the realm of thought
has ceased, that
which is to be dcsignated also has ceascd.„
As pointed out in the inuoduction, a similar statemcnt was
made by the
Buddha in relation co a tathagata who has passed away, and
the present context, in which the mctaphysical nocion of s~lf(atman) is
discussed , is no more
differcnt from that in which the Buddha made that statement.
·
Sofar as Nigarjuna's analysis is concerned; it has become
elear that his ncgations pcrtained primarily to metaphysics, whether it be the
nocion of a pcrmanent and eternaJ self (atman) or a substance (wabhava). Along
with the negation of a permanent anq eternaJ self, Nigarjuna also rcjected
absolute
"otherness" (para-bhava). Existence and
noo-existence, in ·this metaphysicaJ
sense , wece rcjccted by him. As pointed out in the analysis
of the Dcdicatory
Verscs, the "non-arising" (anutpada) and
"non-ceasing'' (anirodha) wcre intendcd as criticisms of ruch metaphysics.
Ifone rccognizcs a substance, Nigarjuna would say it is non-ceasing: if one
rocognizcs annihilation, Nagarjuna
would characterizc is as non-arising. In other words,
ifabsolute arising and absolute ceasing wece to be acceptcd, thcsc would ncgate
empirical arising and
ceasing whicb is the basis of "dependent arising"
(pralityasamutpada). W hcn
both "the way of phcnomeoa" (dhtl1'mtzli1) and
frccdom (nirva11a), which arc
expiaincd k terms of "dependent arising'' (pralityasamutjiida),
arc referred to
as "non-arisen and non-ceasing", it is mor~
appropriatc to assume that herc
they arc to be distinguishcd from absolute arising and
absołute ceasing. Arisiog
and ceasing in an absolutc sense represcot inappropriatc
conceptualizations.
Neither che nature of phenomcna nor frccdom should be the
subject of such
inappropliate conceptualizations.
8. Saf'l!atrz tathya1'(J na va tathyaf?'l tathya1'(J
c/jtathyam eva ca,
nai11atathya1'(J naiva tathyam etad buddhanufiisanaf!J.
Evcrythi.ng is such, not such, both such and not such, and
oeither such
.and not such: this is the Buddha's admonition.
MKV(P) p.369: MKV(~ p.157.270 THE PHllOSOl'HY OF 'Il-IE
MIDDLE W.AY
On the basis of this statement, Inada, following his
predecessors in the interpretation of Nigarjuna, rcachcd the conclusion that
"truth is non-relationaJ,
non-descripti:ve, non-diffcrential. ... it is thatness or
thusness," (p.113).
Refercing specifically to XVIlI.8, he says 'that herc
"Nigarjunaintroduces the
famed Four-corncred Logic, , , . i.e„ the póssible
conditions ofis, is not, both
is and is not, and ncither is nor is not, in order to
exhibit the fact that fina!
truth uanscends all these possibilities; it is fUnyllt'ii
per se" (ibid.)
Śo far, 0our analysis ofNagarjuna's statcmcntS has failed to
reveaJ any form of
four-cornered logic that he uscd to establish an ultimate
truth. Whenever he
ucilized it, he did só i.o order to rejcct metaphysicaJ
assumpcions, rather than to
establish something or some theory.
Mter srating the fact that metaphysical views, especially
those relating to a
tr1thagata after death, take us beyond the sphere. of
thought
(citta-gocara)(XVUI. 7), Nagarjuna is here expanding the
discussion to include
one of the most persistent problems ofmetaphysics, namcly,
"everything" (sarVa'f!Z). lt is the problem that led the
Sarvastivadins to uphold the view that
Comments
Post a Comment
7000